Advertisement
Guest User

Untitled

a guest
Oct 29th, 2015
420
0
Never
Not a member of Pastebin yet? Sign Up, it unlocks many cool features!
text 201.19 KB | None | 0 0
  1. The Project Gutenberg EBook of Relativity: The Special and General Theory
  2. by Albert Einstein
  3. (#1 in our series by Albert Einstein)
  4.  
  5. Note: 58 image files are part of this eBook. They include tables,
  6. equations and figures that could not be represented well as plain text.
  7.  
  8. Copyright laws are changing all over the world. Be sure to check the
  9. copyright laws for your country before downloading or redistributing
  10. this or any other Project Gutenberg eBook.
  11.  
  12. This header should be the first thing seen when viewing this Project
  13. Gutenberg file. Please do not remove it. Do not change or edit the
  14. header without written permission.
  15.  
  16. Please read the "legal small print," and other information about the
  17. eBook and Project Gutenberg at the bottom of this file. Included is
  18. important information about your specific rights and restrictions in
  19. how the file may be used. You can also find out about how to make a
  20. donation to Project Gutenberg, and how to get involved.
  21.  
  22.  
  23. **Welcome To The World of Free Plain Vanilla Electronic Texts**
  24.  
  25. **eBooks Readable By Both Humans and By Computers, Since 1971**
  26.  
  27. *****These eBooks Were Prepared By Thousands of Volunteers!*****
  28.  
  29.  
  30. Title: Relativity: The Special and General Theory
  31.  
  32. Author: Albert Einstein
  33.  
  34. Release Date: February, 2004 [EBook #5001]
  35. [Yes, we are more than one year ahead of schedule]
  36. [This file was first posted on April 1, 2002]
  37.  
  38. Edition: 10
  39.  
  40. Language: English
  41.  
  42.  
  43. *** START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK, RELATIVITY ***
  44.  
  45.  
  46.  
  47.  
  48. ALBERT EINSTEIN REFERENCE ARCHIVE
  49.  
  50. RELATIVITY: THE SPECIAL AND GENERAL THEORY
  51.  
  52. BY ALBERT EINSTEIN
  53.  
  54.  
  55. Written: 1916 (this revised edition: 1924)
  56. Source: Relativity: The Special and General Theory (1920)
  57. Publisher: Methuen & Co Ltd
  58. First Published: December, 1916
  59. Translated: Robert W. Lawson (Authorised translation)
  60. Transcription/Markup: Brian Basgen <brian@marxists.org>
  61. Transcription to text: Gregory B. Newby <gbnewby@petascale.org>
  62. Thanks to: Einstein Reference Archive (marxists.org)
  63. The Einstein Reference Archive is online at:
  64. http://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/einstein/index.htm
  65.  
  66. Transcriber note: This file is a plain text rendition of HTML.
  67. Because many equations cannot be presented effectively in plain text,
  68. images are supplied for many equations and for all figures and tables.
  69.  
  70.  
  71. CONTENTS
  72.  
  73. Preface
  74.  
  75. Part I: The Special Theory of Relativity
  76.  
  77. 01. Physical Meaning of Geometrical Propositions
  78. 02. The System of Co-ordinates
  79. 03. Space and Time in Classical Mechanics
  80. 04. The Galileian System of Co-ordinates
  81. 05. The Principle of Relativity (in the Restricted Sense)
  82. 06. The Theorem of the Addition of Velocities employed in
  83. Classical Mechanics
  84. 07. The Apparent Incompatability of the Law of Propagation of
  85. Light with the Principle of Relativity
  86. 08. On the Idea of Time in Physics
  87. 09. The Relativity of Simultaneity
  88. 10. On the Relativity of the Conception of Distance
  89. 11. The Lorentz Transformation
  90. 12. The Behaviour of Measuring-Rods and Clocks in Motion
  91. 13. Theorem of the Addition of Velocities. The Experiment of Fizeau
  92. 14. The Hueristic Value of the Theory of Relativity
  93. 15. General Results of the Theory
  94. 16. Expereince and the Special Theory of Relativity
  95. 17. Minkowski's Four-dimensial Space
  96.  
  97.  
  98. Part II: The General Theory of Relativity
  99.  
  100. 18. Special and General Principle of Relativity
  101. 19. The Gravitational Field
  102. 20. The Equality of Inertial and Gravitational Mass as an Argument
  103. for the General Postulate of Relativity
  104. 21. In What Respects are the Foundations of Classical Mechanics
  105. and of the Special Theory of Relativity Unsatisfactory?
  106. 22. A Few Inferences from the General Principle of Relativity
  107. 23. Behaviour of Clocks and Measuring-Rods on a Rotating Body of
  108. Reference
  109. 24. Euclidean and non-Euclidean Continuum
  110. 25. Gaussian Co-ordinates
  111. 26. The Space-Time Continuum of the Speical Theory of Relativity
  112. Considered as a Euclidean Continuum
  113. 27. The Space-Time Continuum of the General Theory of Relativity
  114. is Not a Eculidean Continuum
  115. 28. Exact Formulation of the General Principle of Relativity
  116. 29. The Solution of the Problem of Gravitation on the Basis of the
  117. General Principle of Relativity
  118.  
  119.  
  120. Part III: Considerations on the Universe as a Whole
  121.  
  122. 30. Cosmological Difficulties of Netwon's Theory
  123. 31. The Possibility of a "Finite" and yet "Unbounded" Universe
  124. 32. The Structure of Space According to the General Theory of
  125. Relativity
  126.  
  127.  
  128. Appendices:
  129.  
  130. 01. Simple Derivation of the Lorentz Transformation (sup. ch. 11)
  131. 02. Minkowski's Four-Dimensional Space ("World") (sup. ch 17)
  132. 03. The Experimental Confirmation of the General Theory of Relativity
  133. 04. The Structure of Space According to the General Theory of
  134. Relativity (sup. ch 32)
  135. 05. Relativity and the Problem of Space
  136.  
  137. Note: The fifth Appendix was added by Einstein at the time of the
  138. fifteenth re-printing of this book; and as a result is still under
  139. copyright restrictions so cannot be added without the permission of
  140. the publisher.
  141.  
  142.  
  143.  
  144. PREFACE
  145.  
  146. (December, 1916)
  147.  
  148. The present book is intended, as far as possible, to give an exact
  149. insight into the theory of Relativity to those readers who, from a
  150. general scientific and philosophical point of view, are interested in
  151. the theory, but who are not conversant with the mathematical apparatus
  152. of theoretical physics. The work presumes a standard of education
  153. corresponding to that of a university matriculation examination, and,
  154. despite the shortness of the book, a fair amount of patience and force
  155. of will on the part of the reader. The author has spared himself no
  156. pains in his endeavour to present the main ideas in the simplest and
  157. most intelligible form, and on the whole, in the sequence and
  158. connection in which they actually originated. In the interest of
  159. clearness, it appeared to me inevitable that I should repeat myself
  160. frequently, without paying the slightest attention to the elegance of
  161. the presentation. I adhered scrupulously to the precept of that
  162. brilliant theoretical physicist L. Boltzmann, according to whom
  163. matters of elegance ought to be left to the tailor and to the cobbler.
  164. I make no pretence of having withheld from the reader difficulties
  165. which are inherent to the subject. On the other hand, I have purposely
  166. treated the empirical physical foundations of the theory in a
  167. "step-motherly" fashion, so that readers unfamiliar with physics may
  168. not feel like the wanderer who was unable to see the forest for the
  169. trees. May the book bring some one a few happy hours of suggestive
  170. thought!
  171.  
  172. December, 1916
  173. A. EINSTEIN
  174.  
  175.  
  176.  
  177. PART I
  178.  
  179. THE SPECIAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY
  180.  
  181. PHYSICAL MEANING OF GEOMETRICAL PROPOSITIONS
  182.  
  183.  
  184. In your schooldays most of you who read this book made acquaintance
  185. with the noble building of Euclid's geometry, and you remember --
  186. perhaps with more respect than love -- the magnificent structure, on
  187. the lofty staircase of which you were chased about for uncounted hours
  188. by conscientious teachers. By reason of our past experience, you would
  189. certainly regard everyone with disdain who should pronounce even the
  190. most out-of-the-way proposition of this science to be untrue. But
  191. perhaps this feeling of proud certainty would leave you immediately if
  192. some one were to ask you: "What, then, do you mean by the assertion
  193. that these propositions are true?" Let us proceed to give this
  194. question a little consideration.
  195.  
  196. Geometry sets out form certain conceptions such as "plane," "point,"
  197. and "straight line," with which we are able to associate more or less
  198. definite ideas, and from certain simple propositions (axioms) which,
  199. in virtue of these ideas, we are inclined to accept as "true." Then,
  200. on the basis of a logical process, the justification of which we feel
  201. ourselves compelled to admit, all remaining propositions are shown to
  202. follow from those axioms, i.e. they are proven. A proposition is then
  203. correct ("true") when it has been derived in the recognised manner
  204. from the axioms. The question of "truth" of the individual geometrical
  205. propositions is thus reduced to one of the "truth" of the axioms. Now
  206. it has long been known that the last question is not only unanswerable
  207. by the methods of geometry, but that it is in itself entirely without
  208. meaning. We cannot ask whether it is true that only one straight line
  209. goes through two points. We can only say that Euclidean geometry deals
  210. with things called "straight lines," to each of which is ascribed the
  211. property of being uniquely determined by two points situated on it.
  212. The concept "true" does not tally with the assertions of pure
  213. geometry, because by the word "true" we are eventually in the habit of
  214. designating always the correspondence with a "real" object; geometry,
  215. however, is not concerned with the relation of the ideas involved in
  216. it to objects of experience, but only with the logical connection of
  217. these ideas among themselves.
  218.  
  219. It is not difficult to understand why, in spite of this, we feel
  220. constrained to call the propositions of geometry "true." Geometrical
  221. ideas correspond to more or less exact objects in nature, and these
  222. last are undoubtedly the exclusive cause of the genesis of those
  223. ideas. Geometry ought to refrain from such a course, in order to give
  224. to its structure the largest possible logical unity. The practice, for
  225. example, of seeing in a "distance" two marked positions on a
  226. practically rigid body is something which is lodged deeply in our
  227. habit of thought. We are accustomed further to regard three points as
  228. being situated on a straight line, if their apparent positions can be
  229. made to coincide for observation with one eye, under suitable choice
  230. of our place of observation.
  231.  
  232. If, in pursuance of our habit of thought, we now supplement the
  233. propositions of Euclidean geometry by the single proposition that two
  234. points on a practically rigid body always correspond to the same
  235. distance (line-interval), independently of any changes in position to
  236. which we may subject the body, the propositions of Euclidean geometry
  237. then resolve themselves into propositions on the possible relative
  238. position of practically rigid bodies.* Geometry which has been
  239. supplemented in this way is then to be treated as a branch of physics.
  240. We can now legitimately ask as to the "truth" of geometrical
  241. propositions interpreted in this way, since we are justified in asking
  242. whether these propositions are satisfied for those real things we have
  243. associated with the geometrical ideas. In less exact terms we can
  244. express this by saying that by the "truth" of a geometrical
  245. proposition in this sense we understand its validity for a
  246. construction with rule and compasses.
  247.  
  248. Of course the conviction of the "truth" of geometrical propositions in
  249. this sense is founded exclusively on rather incomplete experience. For
  250. the present we shall assume the "truth" of the geometrical
  251. propositions, then at a later stage (in the general theory of
  252. relativity) we shall see that this "truth" is limited, and we shall
  253. consider the extent of its limitation.
  254.  
  255.  
  256. Notes
  257.  
  258. *) It follows that a natural object is associated also with a
  259. straight line. Three points A, B and C on a rigid body thus lie in a
  260. straight line when the points A and C being given, B is chosen such
  261. that the sum of the distances AB and BC is as short as possible. This
  262. incomplete suggestion will suffice for the present purpose.
  263.  
  264.  
  265.  
  266. THE SYSTEM OF CO-ORDINATES
  267.  
  268.  
  269. On the basis of the physical interpretation of distance which has been
  270. indicated, we are also in a position to establish the distance between
  271. two points on a rigid body by means of measurements. For this purpose
  272. we require a " distance " (rod S) which is to be used once and for
  273. all, and which we employ as a standard measure. If, now, A and B are
  274. two points on a rigid body, we can construct the line joining them
  275. according to the rules of geometry ; then, starting from A, we can
  276. mark off the distance S time after time until we reach B. The number
  277. of these operations required is the numerical measure of the distance
  278. AB. This is the basis of all measurement of length. *
  279.  
  280. Every description of the scene of an event or of the position of an
  281. object in space is based on the specification of the point on a rigid
  282. body (body of reference) with which that event or object coincides.
  283. This applies not only to scientific description, but also to everyday
  284. life. If I analyse the place specification " Times Square, New York,"
  285. **A I arrive at the following result. The earth is the rigid body
  286. to which the specification of place refers; " Times Square, New York,"
  287. is a well-defined point, to which a name has been assigned, and with
  288. which the event coincides in space.**B
  289.  
  290. This primitive method of place specification deals only with places on
  291. the surface of rigid bodies, and is dependent on the existence of
  292. points on this surface which are distinguishable from each other. But
  293. we can free ourselves from both of these limitations without altering
  294. the nature of our specification of position. If, for instance, a cloud
  295. is hovering over Times Square, then we can determine its position
  296. relative to the surface of the earth by erecting a pole
  297. perpendicularly on the Square, so that it reaches the cloud. The
  298. length of the pole measured with the standard measuring-rod, combined
  299. with the specification of the position of the foot of the pole,
  300. supplies us with a complete place specification. On the basis of this
  301. illustration, we are able to see the manner in which a refinement of
  302. the conception of position has been developed.
  303.  
  304. (a) We imagine the rigid body, to which the place specification is
  305. referred, supplemented in such a manner that the object whose position
  306. we require is reached by. the completed rigid body.
  307.  
  308. (b) In locating the position of the object, we make use of a number
  309. (here the length of the pole measured with the measuring-rod) instead
  310. of designated points of reference.
  311.  
  312. (c) We speak of the height of the cloud even when the pole which
  313. reaches the cloud has not been erected. By means of optical
  314. observations of the cloud from different positions on the ground, and
  315. taking into account the properties of the propagation of light, we
  316. determine the length of the pole we should have required in order to
  317. reach the cloud.
  318.  
  319. From this consideration we see that it will be advantageous if, in the
  320. description of position, it should be possible by means of numerical
  321. measures to make ourselves independent of the existence of marked
  322. positions (possessing names) on the rigid body of reference. In the
  323. physics of measurement this is attained by the application of the
  324. Cartesian system of co-ordinates.
  325.  
  326. This consists of three plane surfaces perpendicular to each other and
  327. rigidly attached to a rigid body. Referred to a system of
  328. co-ordinates, the scene of any event will be determined (for the main
  329. part) by the specification of the lengths of the three perpendiculars
  330. or co-ordinates (x, y, z) which can be dropped from the scene of the
  331. event to those three plane surfaces. The lengths of these three
  332. perpendiculars can be determined by a series of manipulations with
  333. rigid measuring-rods performed according to the rules and methods laid
  334. down by Euclidean geometry.
  335.  
  336. In practice, the rigid surfaces which constitute the system of
  337. co-ordinates are generally not available ; furthermore, the magnitudes
  338. of the co-ordinates are not actually determined by constructions with
  339. rigid rods, but by indirect means. If the results of physics and
  340. astronomy are to maintain their clearness, the physical meaning of
  341. specifications of position must always be sought in accordance with
  342. the above considerations. ***
  343.  
  344. We thus obtain the following result: Every description of events in
  345. space involves the use of a rigid body to which such events have to be
  346. referred. The resulting relationship takes for granted that the laws
  347. of Euclidean geometry hold for "distances;" the "distance" being
  348. represented physically by means of the convention of two marks on a
  349. rigid body.
  350.  
  351.  
  352. Notes
  353.  
  354. * Here we have assumed that there is nothing left over i.e. that
  355. the measurement gives a whole number. This difficulty is got over by
  356. the use of divided measuring-rods, the introduction of which does not
  357. demand any fundamentally new method.
  358.  
  359. **A Einstein used "Potsdamer Platz, Berlin" in the original text.
  360. In the authorised translation this was supplemented with "Tranfalgar
  361. Square, London". We have changed this to "Times Square, New York", as
  362. this is the most well known/identifiable location to English speakers
  363. in the present day. [Note by the janitor.]
  364.  
  365. **B It is not necessary here to investigate further the significance
  366. of the expression "coincidence in space." This conception is
  367. sufficiently obvious to ensure that differences of opinion are
  368. scarcely likely to arise as to its applicability in practice.
  369.  
  370. *** A refinement and modification of these views does not become
  371. necessary until we come to deal with the general theory of relativity,
  372. treated in the second part of this book.
  373.  
  374.  
  375.  
  376. SPACE AND TIME IN CLASSICAL MECHANICS
  377.  
  378.  
  379. The purpose of mechanics is to describe how bodies change their
  380. position in space with "time." I should load my conscience with grave
  381. sins against the sacred spirit of lucidity were I to formulate the
  382. aims of mechanics in this way, without serious reflection and detailed
  383. explanations. Let us proceed to disclose these sins.
  384.  
  385. It is not clear what is to be understood here by "position" and
  386. "space." I stand at the window of a railway carriage which is
  387. travelling uniformly, and drop a stone on the embankment, without
  388. throwing it. Then, disregarding the influence of the air resistance, I
  389. see the stone descend in a straight line. A pedestrian who observes
  390. the misdeed from the footpath notices that the stone falls to earth in
  391. a parabolic curve. I now ask: Do the "positions" traversed by the
  392. stone lie "in reality" on a straight line or on a parabola? Moreover,
  393. what is meant here by motion "in space" ? From the considerations of
  394. the previous section the answer is self-evident. In the first place we
  395. entirely shun the vague word "space," of which, we must honestly
  396. acknowledge, we cannot form the slightest conception, and we replace
  397. it by "motion relative to a practically rigid body of reference." The
  398. positions relative to the body of reference (railway carriage or
  399. embankment) have already been defined in detail in the preceding
  400. section. If instead of " body of reference " we insert " system of
  401. co-ordinates," which is a useful idea for mathematical description, we
  402. are in a position to say : The stone traverses a straight line
  403. relative to a system of co-ordinates rigidly attached to the carriage,
  404. but relative to a system of co-ordinates rigidly attached to the
  405. ground (embankment) it describes a parabola. With the aid of this
  406. example it is clearly seen that there is no such thing as an
  407. independently existing trajectory (lit. "path-curve"*), but only
  408. a trajectory relative to a particular body of reference.
  409.  
  410. In order to have a complete description of the motion, we must specify
  411. how the body alters its position with time ; i.e. for every point on
  412. the trajectory it must be stated at what time the body is situated
  413. there. These data must be supplemented by such a definition of time
  414. that, in virtue of this definition, these time-values can be regarded
  415. essentially as magnitudes (results of measurements) capable of
  416. observation. If we take our stand on the ground of classical
  417. mechanics, we can satisfy this requirement for our illustration in the
  418. following manner. We imagine two clocks of identical construction ;
  419. the man at the railway-carriage window is holding one of them, and the
  420. man on the footpath the other. Each of the observers determines the
  421. position on his own reference-body occupied by the stone at each tick
  422. of the clock he is holding in his hand. In this connection we have not
  423. taken account of the inaccuracy involved by the finiteness of the
  424. velocity of propagation of light. With this and with a second
  425. difficulty prevailing here we shall have to deal in detail later.
  426.  
  427.  
  428. Notes
  429.  
  430. *) That is, a curve along which the body moves.
  431.  
  432.  
  433.  
  434. THE GALILEIAN SYSTEM OF CO-ORDINATES
  435.  
  436.  
  437. As is well known, the fundamental law of the mechanics of
  438. Galilei-Newton, which is known as the law of inertia, can be stated
  439. thus: A body removed sufficiently far from other bodies continues in a
  440. state of rest or of uniform motion in a straight line. This law not
  441. only says something about the motion of the bodies, but it also
  442. indicates the reference-bodies or systems of coordinates, permissible
  443. in mechanics, which can be used in mechanical description. The visible
  444. fixed stars are bodies for which the law of inertia certainly holds to
  445. a high degree of approximation. Now if we use a system of co-ordinates
  446. which is rigidly attached to the earth, then, relative to this system,
  447. every fixed star describes a circle of immense radius in the course of
  448. an astronomical day, a result which is opposed to the statement of the
  449. law of inertia. So that if we adhere to this law we must refer these
  450. motions only to systems of coordinates relative to which the fixed
  451. stars do not move in a circle. A system of co-ordinates of which the
  452. state of motion is such that the law of inertia holds relative to it
  453. is called a " Galileian system of co-ordinates." The laws of the
  454. mechanics of Galflei-Newton can be regarded as valid only for a
  455. Galileian system of co-ordinates.
  456.  
  457.  
  458.  
  459. THE PRINCIPLE OF RELATIVITY
  460. (IN THE RESTRICTED SENSE)
  461.  
  462.  
  463. In order to attain the greatest possible clearness, let us return to
  464. our example of the railway carriage supposed to be travelling
  465. uniformly. We call its motion a uniform translation ("uniform" because
  466. it is of constant velocity and direction, " translation " because
  467. although the carriage changes its position relative to the embankment
  468. yet it does not rotate in so doing). Let us imagine a raven flying
  469. through the air in such a manner that its motion, as observed from the
  470. embankment, is uniform and in a straight line. If we were to observe
  471. the flying raven from the moving railway carriage. we should find that
  472. the motion of the raven would be one of different velocity and
  473. direction, but that it would still be uniform and in a straight line.
  474. Expressed in an abstract manner we may say : If a mass m is moving
  475. uniformly in a straight line with respect to a co-ordinate system K,
  476. then it will also be moving uniformly and in a straight line relative
  477. to a second co-ordinate system K1 provided that the latter is
  478. executing a uniform translatory motion with respect to K. In
  479. accordance with the discussion contained in the preceding section, it
  480. follows that:
  481.  
  482. If K is a Galileian co-ordinate system. then every other co-ordinate
  483. system K' is a Galileian one, when, in relation to K, it is in a
  484. condition of uniform motion of translation. Relative to K1 the
  485. mechanical laws of Galilei-Newton hold good exactly as they do with
  486. respect to K.
  487.  
  488. We advance a step farther in our generalisation when we express the
  489. tenet thus: If, relative to K, K1 is a uniformly moving co-ordinate
  490. system devoid of rotation, then natural phenomena run their course
  491. with respect to K1 according to exactly the same general laws as with
  492. respect to K. This statement is called the principle of relativity (in
  493. the restricted sense).
  494.  
  495. As long as one was convinced that all natural phenomena were capable
  496. of representation with the help of classical mechanics, there was no
  497. need to doubt the validity of this principle of relativity. But in
  498. view of the more recent development of electrodynamics and optics it
  499. became more and more evident that classical mechanics affords an
  500. insufficient foundation for the physical description of all natural
  501. phenomena. At this juncture the question of the validity of the
  502. principle of relativity became ripe for discussion, and it did not
  503. appear impossible that the answer to this question might be in the
  504. negative.
  505.  
  506. Nevertheless, there are two general facts which at the outset speak
  507. very much in favour of the validity of the principle of relativity.
  508. Even though classical mechanics does not supply us with a sufficiently
  509. broad basis for the theoretical presentation of all physical
  510. phenomena, still we must grant it a considerable measure of " truth,"
  511. since it supplies us with the actual motions of the heavenly bodies
  512. with a delicacy of detail little short of wonderful. The principle of
  513. relativity must therefore apply with great accuracy in the domain of
  514. mechanics. But that a principle of such broad generality should hold
  515. with such exactness in one domain of phenomena, and yet should be
  516. invalid for another, is a priori not very probable.
  517.  
  518. We now proceed to the second argument, to which, moreover, we shall
  519. return later. If the principle of relativity (in the restricted sense)
  520. does not hold, then the Galileian co-ordinate systems K, K1, K2, etc.,
  521. which are moving uniformly relative to each other, will not be
  522. equivalent for the description of natural phenomena. In this case we
  523. should be constrained to believe that natural laws are capable of
  524. being formulated in a particularly simple manner, and of course only
  525. on condition that, from amongst all possible Galileian co-ordinate
  526. systems, we should have chosen one (K[0]) of a particular state of
  527. motion as our body of reference. We should then be justified (because
  528. of its merits for the description of natural phenomena) in calling
  529. this system " absolutely at rest," and all other Galileian systems K "
  530. in motion." If, for instance, our embankment were the system K[0] then
  531. our railway carriage would be a system K, relative to which less
  532. simple laws would hold than with respect to K[0]. This diminished
  533. simplicity would be due to the fact that the carriage K would be in
  534. motion (i.e."really")with respect to K[0]. In the general laws of
  535. nature which have been formulated with reference to K, the magnitude
  536. and direction of the velocity of the carriage would necessarily play a
  537. part. We should expect, for instance, that the note emitted by an
  538. organpipe placed with its axis parallel to the direction of travel
  539. would be different from that emitted if the axis of the pipe were
  540. placed perpendicular to this direction.
  541.  
  542. Now in virtue of its motion in an orbit round the sun, our earth is
  543. comparable with a railway carriage travelling with a velocity of about
  544. 30 kilometres per second. If the principle of relativity were not
  545. valid we should therefore expect that the direction of motion of the
  546. earth at any moment would enter into the laws of nature, and also that
  547. physical systems in their behaviour would be dependent on the
  548. orientation in space with respect to the earth. For owing to the
  549. alteration in direction of the velocity of revolution of the earth in
  550. the course of a year, the earth cannot be at rest relative to the
  551. hypothetical system K[0] throughout the whole year. However, the most
  552. careful observations have never revealed such anisotropic properties
  553. in terrestrial physical space, i.e. a physical non-equivalence of
  554. different directions. This is very powerful argument in favour of the
  555. principle of relativity.
  556.  
  557.  
  558.  
  559. THE THEOREM OF THE
  560. ADDITION OF VELOCITIES
  561. EMPLOYED IN CLASSICAL MECHANICS
  562.  
  563.  
  564. Let us suppose our old friend the railway carriage to be travelling
  565. along the rails with a constant velocity v, and that a man traverses
  566. the length of the carriage in the direction of travel with a velocity
  567. w. How quickly or, in other words, with what velocity W does the man
  568. advance relative to the embankment during the process ? The only
  569. possible answer seems to result from the following consideration: If
  570. the man were to stand still for a second, he would advance relative to
  571. the embankment through a distance v equal numerically to the velocity
  572. of the carriage. As a consequence of his walking, however, he
  573. traverses an additional distance w relative to the carriage, and hence
  574. also relative to the embankment, in this second, the distance w being
  575. numerically equal to the velocity with which he is walking. Thus in
  576. total be covers the distance W=v+w relative to the embankment in the
  577. second considered. We shall see later that this result, which
  578. expresses the theorem of the addition of velocities employed in
  579. classical mechanics, cannot be maintained ; in other words, the law
  580. that we have just written down does not hold in reality. For the time
  581. being, however, we shall assume its correctness.
  582.  
  583.  
  584.  
  585. THE APPARENT INCOMPATIBILITY OF THE
  586. LAW OF PROPAGATION OF LIGHT WITH THE
  587. PRINCIPLE OF RELATIVITY
  588.  
  589.  
  590. There is hardly a simpler law in physics than that according to which
  591. light is propagated in empty space. Every child at school knows, or
  592. believes he knows, that this propagation takes place in straight lines
  593. with a velocity c= 300,000 km./sec. At all events we know with great
  594. exactness that this velocity is the same for all colours, because if
  595. this were not the case, the minimum of emission would not be observed
  596. simultaneously for different colours during the eclipse of a fixed
  597. star by its dark neighbour. By means of similar considerations based
  598. on observa- tions of double stars, the Dutch astronomer De Sitter was
  599. also able to show that the velocity of propagation of light cannot
  600. depend on the velocity of motion of the body emitting the light. The
  601. assumption that this velocity of propagation is dependent on the
  602. direction "in space" is in itself improbable.
  603.  
  604. In short, let us assume that the simple law of the constancy of the
  605. velocity of light c (in vacuum) is justifiably believed by the child
  606. at school. Who would imagine that this simple law has plunged the
  607. conscientiously thoughtful physicist into the greatest intellectual
  608. difficulties? Let us consider how these difficulties arise.
  609.  
  610. Of course we must refer the process of the propagation of light (and
  611. indeed every other process) to a rigid reference-body (co-ordinate
  612. system). As such a system let us again choose our embankment. We shall
  613. imagine the air above it to have been removed. If a ray of light be
  614. sent along the embankment, we see from the above that the tip of the
  615. ray will be transmitted with the velocity c relative to the
  616. embankment. Now let us suppose that our railway carriage is again
  617. travelling along the railway lines with the velocity v, and that its
  618. direction is the same as that of the ray of light, but its velocity of
  619. course much less. Let us inquire about the velocity of propagation of
  620. the ray of light relative to the carriage. It is obvious that we can
  621. here apply the consideration of the previous section, since the ray of
  622. light plays the part of the man walking along relatively to the
  623. carriage. The velocity w of the man relative to the embankment is here
  624. replaced by the velocity of light relative to the embankment. w is the
  625. required velocity of light with respect to the carriage, and we have
  626.  
  627. w = c-v.
  628.  
  629. The velocity of propagation ot a ray of light relative to the carriage
  630. thus comes cut smaller than c.
  631.  
  632. But this result comes into conflict with the principle of relativity
  633. set forth in Section V. For, like every other general law of
  634. nature, the law of the transmission of light in vacuo [in vacuum]
  635. must, according to the principle of relativity, be the same for the
  636. railway carriage as reference-body as when the rails are the body of
  637. reference. But, from our above consideration, this would appear to be
  638. impossible. If every ray of light is propagated relative to the
  639. embankment with the velocity c, then for this reason it would appear
  640. that another law of propagation of light must necessarily hold with
  641. respect to the carriage -- a result contradictory to the principle of
  642. relativity.
  643.  
  644. In view of this dilemma there appears to be nothing else for it than
  645. to abandon either the principle of relativity or the simple law of the
  646. propagation of light in vacuo. Those of you who have carefully
  647. followed the preceding discussion are almost sure to expect that we
  648. should retain the principle of relativity, which appeals so
  649. convincingly to the intellect because it is so natural and simple. The
  650. law of the propagation of light in vacuo would then have to be
  651. replaced by a more complicated law conformable to the principle of
  652. relativity. The development of theoretical physics shows, however,
  653. that we cannot pursue this course. The epoch-making theoretical
  654. investigations of H. A. Lorentz on the electrodynamical and optical
  655. phenomena connected with moving bodies show that experience in this
  656. domain leads conclusively to a theory of electromagnetic phenomena, of
  657. which the law of the constancy of the velocity of light in vacuo is a
  658. necessary consequence. Prominent theoretical physicists were theref
  659. ore more inclined to reject the principle of relativity, in spite of
  660. the fact that no empirical data had been found which were
  661. contradictory to this principle.
  662.  
  663. At this juncture the theory of relativity entered the arena. As a
  664. result of an analysis of the physical conceptions of time and space,
  665. it became evident that in realily there is not the least
  666. incompatibilitiy between the principle of relativity and the law of
  667. propagation of light, and that by systematically holding fast to both
  668. these laws a logically rigid theory could be arrived at. This theory
  669. has been called the special theory of relativity to distinguish it
  670. from the extended theory, with which we shall deal later. In the
  671. following pages we shall present the fundamental ideas of the special
  672. theory of relativity.
  673.  
  674.  
  675.  
  676. ON THE IDEA OF TIME IN PHYSICS
  677.  
  678.  
  679. Lightning has struck the rails on our railway embankment at two places
  680. A and B far distant from each other. I make the additional assertion
  681. that these two lightning flashes occurred simultaneously. If I ask you
  682. whether there is sense in this statement, you will answer my question
  683. with a decided "Yes." But if I now approach you with the request to
  684. explain to me the sense of the statement more precisely, you find
  685. after some consideration that the answer to this question is not so
  686. easy as it appears at first sight.
  687.  
  688. After some time perhaps the following answer would occur to you: "The
  689. significance of the statement is clear in itself and needs no further
  690. explanation; of course it would require some consideration if I were
  691. to be commissioned to determine by observations whether in the actual
  692. case the two events took place simultaneously or not." I cannot be
  693. satisfied with this answer for the following reason. Supposing that as
  694. a result of ingenious considerations an able meteorologist were to
  695. discover that the lightning must always strike the places A and B
  696. simultaneously, then we should be faced with the task of testing
  697. whether or not this theoretical result is in accordance with the
  698. reality. We encounter the same difficulty with all physical statements
  699. in which the conception " simultaneous " plays a part. The concept
  700. does not exist for the physicist until he has the possibility of
  701. discovering whether or not it is fulfilled in an actual case. We thus
  702. require a definition of simultaneity such that this definition
  703. supplies us with the method by means of which, in the present case, he
  704. can decide by experiment whether or not both the lightning strokes
  705. occurred simultaneously. As long as this requirement is not satisfied,
  706. I allow myself to be deceived as a physicist (and of course the same
  707. applies if I am not a physicist), when I imagine that I am able to
  708. attach a meaning to the statement of simultaneity. (I would ask the
  709. reader not to proceed farther until he is fully convinced on this
  710. point.)
  711.  
  712. After thinking the matter over for some time you then offer the
  713. following suggestion with which to test simultaneity. By measuring
  714. along the rails, the connecting line AB should be measured up and an
  715. observer placed at the mid-point M of the distance AB. This observer
  716. should be supplied with an arrangement (e.g. two mirrors inclined at
  717. 90^0) which allows him visually to observe both places A and B at the
  718. same time. If the observer perceives the two flashes of lightning at
  719. the same time, then they are simultaneous.
  720.  
  721. I am very pleased with this suggestion, but for all that I cannot
  722. regard the matter as quite settled, because I feel constrained to
  723. raise the following objection:
  724.  
  725. "Your definition would certainly be right, if only I knew that the
  726. light by means of which the observer at M perceives the lightning
  727. flashes travels along the length A arrow M with the same velocity as
  728. along the length B arrow M. But an examination of this supposition
  729. would only be possible if we already had at our disposal the means of
  730. measuring time. It would thus appear as though we were moving here in
  731. a logical circle."
  732.  
  733. After further consideration you cast a somewhat disdainful glance at
  734. me -- and rightly so -- and you declare:
  735.  
  736. "I maintain my previous definition nevertheless, because in reality it
  737. assumes absolutely nothing about light. There is only one demand to be
  738. made of the definition of simultaneity, namely, that in every real
  739. case it must supply us with an empirical decision as to whether or not
  740. the conception that has to be defined is fulfilled. That my definition
  741. satisfies this demand is indisputable. That light requires the same
  742. time to traverse the path A arrow M as for the path B arrow M is in
  743. reality neither a supposition nor a hypothesis about the physical
  744. nature of light, but a stipulation which I can make of my own freewill
  745. in order to arrive at a definition of simultaneity."
  746.  
  747. It is clear that this definition can be used to give an exact meaning
  748. not only to two events, but to as many events as we care to choose,
  749. and independently of the positions of the scenes of the events with
  750. respect to the body of reference * (here the railway embankment).
  751. We are thus led also to a definition of " time " in physics. For this
  752. purpose we suppose that clocks of identical construction are placed at
  753. the points A, B and C of the railway line (co-ordinate system) and
  754. that they are set in such a manner that the positions of their
  755. pointers are simultaneously (in the above sense) the same. Under these
  756. conditions we understand by the " time " of an event the reading
  757. (position of the hands) of that one of these clocks which is in the
  758. immediate vicinity (in space) of the event. In this manner a
  759. time-value is associated with every event which is essentially capable
  760. of observation.
  761.  
  762. This stipulation contains a further physical hypothesis, the validity
  763. of which will hardly be doubted without empirical evidence to the
  764. contrary. It has been assumed that all these clocks go at the same
  765. rate if they are of identical construction. Stated more exactly: When
  766. two clocks arranged at rest in different places of a reference-body
  767. are set in such a manner that a particular position of the pointers of
  768. the one clock is simultaneous (in the above sense) with the same
  769. position, of the pointers of the other clock, then identical "
  770. settings " are always simultaneous (in the sense of the above
  771. definition).
  772.  
  773.  
  774. Notes
  775.  
  776. *) We suppose further, that, when three events A, B and C occur in
  777. different places in such a manner that A is simultaneous with B and B
  778. is simultaneous with C (simultaneous in the sense of the above
  779. definition), then the criterion for the simultaneity of the pair of
  780. events A, C is also satisfied. This assumption is a physical
  781. hypothesis about the the of propagation of light: it must certainly be
  782. fulfilled if we are to maintain the law of the constancy of the
  783. velocity of light in vacuo.
  784.  
  785.  
  786.  
  787. THE RELATIVITY OF SIMULATNEITY
  788.  
  789.  
  790. Up to now our considerations have been referred to a particular body
  791. of reference, which we have styled a " railway embankment." We suppose
  792. a very long train travelling along the rails with the constant
  793. velocity v and in the direction indicated in Fig 1. People travelling
  794. in this train will with a vantage view the train as a rigid
  795. reference-body (co-ordinate system); they regard all events in
  796.  
  797. Fig. 01: file fig01.gif
  798.  
  799.  
  800. reference to the train. Then every event which takes place along the
  801. line also takes place at a particular point of the train. Also the
  802. definition of simultaneity can be given relative to the train in
  803. exactly the same way as with respect to the embankment. As a natural
  804. consequence, however, the following question arises :
  805.  
  806. Are two events (e.g. the two strokes of lightning A and B) which are
  807. simultaneous with reference to the railway embankment also
  808. simultaneous relatively to the train? We shall show directly that the
  809. answer must be in the negative.
  810.  
  811. When we say that the lightning strokes A and B are simultaneous with
  812. respect to be embankment, we mean: the rays of light emitted at the
  813. places A and B, where the lightning occurs, meet each other at the
  814. mid-point M of the length A arrow B of the embankment. But the events
  815. A and B also correspond to positions A and B on the train. Let M1 be
  816. the mid-point of the distance A arrow B on the travelling train. Just
  817. when the flashes (as judged from the embankment) of lightning occur,
  818. this point M1 naturally coincides with the point M but it moves
  819. towards the right in the diagram with the velocity v of the train. If
  820. an observer sitting in the position M1 in the train did not possess
  821. this velocity, then he would remain permanently at M, and the light
  822. rays emitted by the flashes of lightning A and B would reach him
  823. simultaneously, i.e. they would meet just where he is situated. Now in
  824. reality (considered with reference to the railway embankment) he is
  825. hastening towards the beam of light coming from B, whilst he is riding
  826. on ahead of the beam of light coming from A. Hence the observer will
  827. see the beam of light emitted from B earlier than he will see that
  828. emitted from A. Observers who take the railway train as their
  829. reference-body must therefore come to the conclusion that the
  830. lightning flash B took place earlier than the lightning flash A. We
  831. thus arrive at the important result:
  832.  
  833. Events which are simultaneous with reference to the embankment are not
  834. simultaneous with respect to the train, and vice versa (relativity of
  835. simultaneity). Every reference-body (co-ordinate system) has its own
  836. particular time ; unless we are told the reference-body to which the
  837. statement of time refers, there is no meaning in a statement of the
  838. time of an event.
  839.  
  840. Now before the advent of the theory of relativity it had always
  841. tacitly been assumed in physics that the statement of time had an
  842. absolute significance, i.e. that it is independent of the state of
  843. motion of the body of reference. But we have just seen that this
  844. assumption is incompatible with the most natural definition of
  845. simultaneity; if we discard this assumption, then the conflict between
  846. the law of the propagation of light in vacuo and the principle of
  847. relativity (developed in Section 7) disappears.
  848.  
  849. We were led to that conflict by the considerations of Section 6,
  850. which are now no longer tenable. In that section we concluded that the
  851. man in the carriage, who traverses the distance w per second relative
  852. to the carriage, traverses the same distance also with respect to the
  853. embankment in each second of time. But, according to the foregoing
  854. considerations, the time required by a particular occurrence with
  855. respect to the carriage must not be considered equal to the duration
  856. of the same occurrence as judged from the embankment (as
  857. reference-body). Hence it cannot be contended that the man in walking
  858. travels the distance w relative to the railway line in a time which is
  859. equal to one second as judged from the embankment.
  860.  
  861. Moreover, the considerations of Section 6 are based on yet a second
  862. assumption, which, in the light of a strict consideration, appears to
  863. be arbitrary, although it was always tacitly made even before the
  864. introduction of the theory of relativity.
  865.  
  866.  
  867.  
  868. ON THE RELATIVITY OF THE CONCEPTION OF DISTANCE
  869.  
  870.  
  871. Let us consider two particular points on the train * travelling
  872. along the embankment with the velocity v, and inquire as to their
  873. distance apart. We already know that it is necessary to have a body of
  874. reference for the measurement of a distance, with respect to which
  875. body the distance can be measured up. It is the simplest plan to use
  876. the train itself as reference-body (co-ordinate system). An observer
  877. in the train measures the interval by marking off his measuring-rod in
  878. a straight line (e.g. along the floor of the carriage) as many times
  879. as is necessary to take him from the one marked point to the other.
  880. Then the number which tells us how often the rod has to be laid down
  881. is the required distance.
  882.  
  883. It is a different matter when the distance has to be judged from the
  884. railway line. Here the following method suggests itself. If we call
  885. A^1 and B^1 the two points on the train whose distance apart is
  886. required, then both of these points are moving with the velocity v
  887. along the embankment. In the first place we require to determine the
  888. points A and B of the embankment which are just being passed by the
  889. two points A^1 and B^1 at a particular time t -- judged from the
  890. embankment. These points A and B of the embankment can be determined
  891. by applying the definition of time given in Section 8. The distance
  892. between these points A and B is then measured by repeated application
  893. of thee measuring-rod along the embankment.
  894.  
  895. A priori it is by no means certain that this last measurement will
  896. supply us with the same result as the first. Thus the length of the
  897. train as measured from the embankment may be different from that
  898. obtained by measuring in the train itself. This circumstance leads us
  899. to a second objection which must be raised against the apparently
  900. obvious consideration of Section 6. Namely, if the man in the
  901. carriage covers the distance w in a unit of time -- measured from the
  902. train, -- then this distance -- as measured from the embankment -- is
  903. not necessarily also equal to w.
  904.  
  905.  
  906. Notes
  907.  
  908. *) e.g. the middle of the first and of the hundredth carriage.
  909.  
  910.  
  911.  
  912. THE LORENTZ TRANSFORMATION
  913.  
  914.  
  915. The results of the last three sections show that the apparent
  916. incompatibility of the law of propagation of light with the principle
  917. of relativity (Section 7) has been derived by means of a
  918. consideration which borrowed two unjustifiable hypotheses from
  919. classical mechanics; these are as follows:
  920.  
  921. (1) The time-interval (time) between two events is independent of the
  922. condition of motion of the body of reference.
  923.  
  924. (2) The space-interval (distance) between two points of a rigid body
  925. is independent of the condition of motion of the body of reference.
  926.  
  927. If we drop these hypotheses, then the dilemma of Section 7
  928. disappears, because the theorem of the addition of velocities derived
  929. in Section 6 becomes invalid. The possibility presents itself that
  930. the law of the propagation of light in vacuo may be compatible with
  931. the principle of relativity, and the question arises: How have we to
  932. modify the considerations of Section 6 in order to remove the
  933. apparent disagreement between these two fundamental results of
  934. experience? This question leads to a general one. In the discussion of
  935. Section 6 we have to do with places and times relative both to the
  936. train and to the embankment. How are we to find the place and time of
  937. an event in relation to the train, when we know the place and time of
  938. the event with respect to the railway embankment ? Is there a
  939. thinkable answer to this question of such a nature that the law of
  940. transmission of light in vacuo does not contradict the principle of
  941. relativity ? In other words : Can we conceive of a relation between
  942. place and time of the individual events relative to both
  943. reference-bodies, such that every ray of light possesses the velocity
  944. of transmission c relative to the embankment and relative to the train
  945. ? This question leads to a quite definite positive answer, and to a
  946. perfectly definite transformation law for the space-time magnitudes of
  947. an event when changing over from one body of reference to another.
  948.  
  949. Before we deal with this, we shall introduce the following incidental
  950. consideration. Up to the present we have only considered events taking
  951. place along the embankment, which had mathematically to assume the
  952. function of a straight line. In the manner indicated in Section 2
  953. we can imagine this reference-body supplemented laterally and in a
  954. vertical direction by means of a framework of rods, so that an event
  955. which takes place anywhere can be localised with reference to this
  956. framework. Fig. 2 Similarly, we can imagine the train travelling with
  957. the velocity v to be continued across the whole of space, so that
  958. every event, no matter how far off it may be, could also be localised
  959. with respect to the second framework. Without committing any
  960. fundamental error, we can disregard the fact that in reality these
  961. frameworks would continually interfere with each other, owing to the
  962. impenetrability of solid bodies. In every such framework we imagine
  963. three surfaces perpendicular to each other marked out, and designated
  964. as " co-ordinate planes " (" co-ordinate system "). A co-ordinate
  965. system K then corresponds to the embankment, and a co-ordinate system
  966. K' to the train. An event, wherever it may have taken place, would be
  967. fixed in space with respect to K by the three perpendiculars x, y, z
  968. on the co-ordinate planes, and with regard to time by a time value t.
  969. Relative to K1, the same event would be fixed in respect of space and
  970. time by corresponding values x1, y1, z1, t1, which of course are not
  971. identical with x, y, z, t. It has already been set forth in detail how
  972. these magnitudes are to be regarded as results of physical
  973. measurements.
  974.  
  975. Obviously our problem can be exactly formulated in the following
  976. manner. What are the values x1, y1, z1, t1, of an event with respect
  977. to K1, when the magnitudes x, y, z, t, of the same event with respect
  978. to K are given ? The relations must be so chosen that the law of the
  979. transmission of light in vacuo is satisfied for one and the same ray
  980. of light (and of course for every ray) with respect to K and K1. For
  981. the relative orientation in space of the co-ordinate systems indicated
  982. in the diagram ([7]Fig. 2), this problem is solved by means of the
  983. equations :
  984.  
  985. eq. 1: file eq01.gif
  986.  
  987. y1 = y
  988. z1 = z
  989.  
  990. eq. 2: file eq02.gif
  991.  
  992. This system of equations is known as the " Lorentz transformation." *
  993.  
  994. If in place of the law of transmission of light we had taken as our
  995. basis the tacit assumptions of the older mechanics as to the absolute
  996. character of times and lengths, then instead of the above we should
  997. have obtained the following equations:
  998.  
  999. x1 = x - vt
  1000. y1 = y
  1001. z1 = z
  1002. t1 = t
  1003.  
  1004. This system of equations is often termed the " Galilei
  1005. transformation." The Galilei transformation can be obtained from the
  1006. Lorentz transformation by substituting an infinitely large value for
  1007. the velocity of light c in the latter transformation.
  1008.  
  1009. Aided by the following illustration, we can readily see that, in
  1010. accordance with the Lorentz transformation, the law of the
  1011. transmission of light in vacuo is satisfied both for the
  1012. reference-body K and for the reference-body K1. A light-signal is sent
  1013. along the positive x-axis, and this light-stimulus advances in
  1014. accordance with the equation
  1015.  
  1016. x = ct,
  1017.  
  1018. i.e. with the velocity c. According to the equations of the Lorentz
  1019. transformation, this simple relation between x and t involves a
  1020. relation between x1 and t1. In point of fact, if we substitute for x
  1021. the value ct in the first and fourth equations of the Lorentz
  1022. transformation, we obtain:
  1023.  
  1024. eq. 3: file eq03.gif
  1025.  
  1026.  
  1027. eq. 4: file eq04.gif
  1028.  
  1029. from which, by division, the expression
  1030.  
  1031. x1 = ct1
  1032.  
  1033. immediately follows. If referred to the system K1, the propagation of
  1034. light takes place according to this equation. We thus see that the
  1035. velocity of transmission relative to the reference-body K1 is also
  1036. equal to c. The same result is obtained for rays of light advancing in
  1037. any other direction whatsoever. Of cause this is not surprising, since
  1038. the equations of the Lorentz transformation were derived conformably
  1039. to this point of view.
  1040.  
  1041.  
  1042. Notes
  1043.  
  1044. *) A simple derivation of the Lorentz transformation is given in
  1045. Appendix I.
  1046.  
  1047.  
  1048.  
  1049. THE BEHAVIOUR OF MEASURING-RODS AND CLOCKS IN MOTION
  1050.  
  1051.  
  1052. Place a metre-rod in the x1-axis of K1 in such a manner that one end
  1053. (the beginning) coincides with the point x1=0 whilst the other end
  1054. (the end of the rod) coincides with the point x1=I. What is the length
  1055. of the metre-rod relatively to the system K? In order to learn this,
  1056. we need only ask where the beginning of the rod and the end of the rod
  1057. lie with respect to K at a particular time t of the system K. By means
  1058. of the first equation of the Lorentz transformation the values of
  1059. these two points at the time t = 0 can be shown to be
  1060.  
  1061. eq. 05a: file eq05a.gif
  1062.  
  1063.  
  1064. eq. 05b: file eq05b.gif
  1065.  
  1066.  
  1067. the distance between the points being eq. 06 .
  1068.  
  1069. But the metre-rod is moving with the velocity v relative to K. It
  1070. therefore follows that the length of a rigid metre-rod moving in the
  1071. direction of its length with a velocity v is eq. 06 of a metre.
  1072.  
  1073. The rigid rod is thus shorter when in motion than when at rest, and
  1074. the more quickly it is moving, the shorter is the rod. For the
  1075. velocity v=c we should have eq. 06a ,
  1076.  
  1077. and for stiII greater velocities the square-root becomes imaginary.
  1078. From this we conclude that in the theory of relativity the velocity c
  1079. plays the part of a limiting velocity, which can neither be reached
  1080. nor exceeded by any real body.
  1081.  
  1082. Of course this feature of the velocity c as a limiting velocity also
  1083. clearly follows from the equations of the Lorentz transformation, for
  1084. these became meaningless if we choose values of v greater than c.
  1085.  
  1086. If, on the contrary, we had considered a metre-rod at rest in the
  1087. x-axis with respect to K, then we should have found that the length of
  1088. the rod as judged from K1 would have been eq. 06 ;
  1089.  
  1090. this is quite in accordance with the principle of relativity which
  1091. forms the basis of our considerations.
  1092.  
  1093. A Priori it is quite clear that we must be able to learn something
  1094. about the physical behaviour of measuring-rods and clocks from the
  1095. equations of transformation, for the magnitudes z, y, x, t, are
  1096. nothing more nor less than the results of measurements obtainable by
  1097. means of measuring-rods and clocks. If we had based our considerations
  1098. on the Galileian transformation we should not have obtained a
  1099. contraction of the rod as a consequence of its motion.
  1100.  
  1101. Let us now consider a seconds-clock which is permanently situated at
  1102. the origin (x1=0) of K1. t1=0 and t1=I are two successive ticks of
  1103. this clock. The first and fourth equations of the Lorentz
  1104. transformation give for these two ticks :
  1105.  
  1106. t = 0
  1107.  
  1108. and
  1109.  
  1110. eq. 07: file eq07.gif
  1111.  
  1112. As judged from K, the clock is moving with the velocity v; as judged
  1113. from this reference-body, the time which elapses between two strokes
  1114. of the clock is not one second, but
  1115.  
  1116. eq. 08: file eq08.gif
  1117.  
  1118. seconds, i.e. a somewhat larger time. As a consequence of its motion
  1119. the clock goes more slowly than when at rest. Here also the velocity c
  1120. plays the part of an unattainable limiting velocity.
  1121.  
  1122.  
  1123.  
  1124. THEOREM OF THE ADDITION OF VELOCITIES.
  1125. THE EXPERIMENT OF FIZEAU
  1126.  
  1127.  
  1128. Now in practice we can move clocks and measuring-rods only with
  1129. velocities that are small compared with the velocity of light; hence
  1130. we shall hardly be able to compare the results of the previous section
  1131. directly with the reality. But, on the other hand, these results must
  1132. strike you as being very singular, and for that reason I shall now
  1133. draw another conclusion from the theory, one which can easily be
  1134. derived from the foregoing considerations, and which has been most
  1135. elegantly confirmed by experiment.
  1136.  
  1137. In Section 6 we derived the theorem of the addition of velocities
  1138. in one direction in the form which also results from the hypotheses of
  1139. classical mechanics- This theorem can also be deduced readily horn the
  1140. Galilei transformation (Section 11). In place of the man walking
  1141. inside the carriage, we introduce a point moving relatively to the
  1142. co-ordinate system K1 in accordance with the equation
  1143.  
  1144. x1 = wt1
  1145.  
  1146. By means of the first and fourth equations of the Galilei
  1147. transformation we can express x1 and t1 in terms of x and t, and we
  1148. then obtain
  1149.  
  1150. x = (v + w)t
  1151.  
  1152. This equation expresses nothing else than the law of motion of the
  1153. point with reference to the system K (of the man with reference to the
  1154. embankment). We denote this velocity by the symbol W, and we then
  1155. obtain, as in Section 6,
  1156.  
  1157. W=v+w A)
  1158.  
  1159. But we can carry out this consideration just as well on the basis of
  1160. the theory of relativity. In the equation
  1161.  
  1162. x1 = wt1 B)
  1163.  
  1164. we must then express x1and t1 in terms of x and t, making use of the
  1165. first and fourth equations of the Lorentz transformation. Instead of
  1166. the equation (A) we then obtain the equation
  1167.  
  1168. eq. 09: file eq09.gif
  1169.  
  1170.  
  1171. which corresponds to the theorem of addition for velocities in one
  1172. direction according to the theory of relativity. The question now
  1173. arises as to which of these two theorems is the better in accord with
  1174. experience. On this point we axe enlightened by a most important
  1175. experiment which the brilliant physicist Fizeau performed more than
  1176. half a century ago, and which has been repeated since then by some of
  1177. the best experimental physicists, so that there can be no doubt about
  1178. its result. The experiment is concerned with the following question.
  1179. Light travels in a motionless liquid with a particular velocity w. How
  1180. quickly does it travel in the direction of the arrow in the tube T
  1181. (see the accompanying diagram, Fig. 3) when the liquid above
  1182. mentioned is flowing through the tube with a velocity v ?
  1183.  
  1184. In accordance with the principle of relativity we shall certainly have
  1185. to take for granted that the propagation of light always takes place
  1186. with the same velocity w with respect to the liquid, whether the
  1187. latter is in motion with reference to other bodies or not. The
  1188. velocity of light relative to the liquid and the velocity of the
  1189. latter relative to the tube are thus known, and we require the
  1190. velocity of light relative to the tube.
  1191.  
  1192. It is clear that we have the problem of Section 6 again before us. The
  1193. tube plays the part of the railway embankment or of the co-ordinate
  1194. system K, the liquid plays the part of the carriage or of the
  1195. co-ordinate system K1, and finally, the light plays the part of the
  1196.  
  1197. Figure 03: file fig03.gif
  1198.  
  1199.  
  1200. man walking along the carriage, or of the moving point in the present
  1201. section. If we denote the velocity of the light relative to the tube
  1202. by W, then this is given by the equation (A) or (B), according as the
  1203. Galilei transformation or the Lorentz transformation corresponds to
  1204. the facts. Experiment * decides in favour of equation (B) derived
  1205. from the theory of relativity, and the agreement is, indeed, very
  1206. exact. According to recent and most excellent measurements by Zeeman,
  1207. the influence of the velocity of flow v on the propagation of light is
  1208. represented by formula (B) to within one per cent.
  1209.  
  1210. Nevertheless we must now draw attention to the fact that a theory of
  1211. this phenomenon was given by H. A. Lorentz long before the statement
  1212. of the theory of relativity. This theory was of a purely
  1213. electrodynamical nature, and was obtained by the use of particular
  1214. hypotheses as to the electromagnetic structure of matter. This
  1215. circumstance, however, does not in the least diminish the
  1216. conclusiveness of the experiment as a crucial test in favour of the
  1217. theory of relativity, for the electrodynamics of Maxwell-Lorentz, on
  1218. which the original theory was based, in no way opposes the theory of
  1219. relativity. Rather has the latter been developed trom electrodynamics
  1220. as an astoundingly simple combination and generalisation of the
  1221. hypotheses, formerly independent of each other, on which
  1222. electrodynamics was built.
  1223.  
  1224.  
  1225. Notes
  1226.  
  1227. *) Fizeau found eq. 10 , where eq. 11
  1228.  
  1229. is the index of refraction of the liquid. On the other hand, owing to
  1230. the smallness of eq. 12 as compared with I,
  1231.  
  1232. we can replace (B) in the first place by eq. 13 , or to the same order
  1233. of approximation by
  1234.  
  1235. eq. 14 , which agrees with Fizeau's result.
  1236.  
  1237.  
  1238.  
  1239. THE HEURISTIC VALUE OF THE THEORY OF RELATIVITY
  1240.  
  1241.  
  1242. Our train of thought in the foregoing pages can be epitomised in the
  1243. following manner. Experience has led to the conviction that, on the
  1244. one hand, the principle of relativity holds true and that on the other
  1245. hand the velocity of transmission of light in vacuo has to be
  1246. considered equal to a constant c. By uniting these two postulates we
  1247. obtained the law of transformation for the rectangular co-ordinates x,
  1248. y, z and the time t of the events which constitute the processes of
  1249. nature. In this connection we did not obtain the Galilei
  1250. transformation, but, differing from classical mechanics, the Lorentz
  1251. transformation.
  1252.  
  1253. The law of transmission of light, the acceptance of which is justified
  1254. by our actual knowledge, played an important part in this process of
  1255. thought. Once in possession of the Lorentz transformation, however, we
  1256. can combine this with the principle of relativity, and sum up the
  1257. theory thus:
  1258.  
  1259. Every general law of nature must be so constituted that it is
  1260. transformed into a law of exactly the same form when, instead of the
  1261. space-time variables x, y, z, t of the original coordinate system K,
  1262. we introduce new space-time variables x1, y1, z1, t1 of a co-ordinate
  1263. system K1. In this connection the relation between the ordinary and
  1264. the accented magnitudes is given by the Lorentz transformation. Or in
  1265. brief : General laws of nature are co-variant with respect to Lorentz
  1266. transformations.
  1267.  
  1268. This is a definite mathematical condition that the theory of
  1269. relativity demands of a natural law, and in virtue of this, the theory
  1270. becomes a valuable heuristic aid in the search for general laws of
  1271. nature. If a general law of nature were to be found which did not
  1272. satisfy this condition, then at least one of the two fundamental
  1273. assumptions of the theory would have been disproved. Let us now
  1274. examine what general results the latter theory has hitherto evinced.
  1275.  
  1276.  
  1277.  
  1278. GENERAL RESULTS OF THE THEORY
  1279.  
  1280.  
  1281. It is clear from our previous considerations that the (special) theory
  1282. of relativity has grown out of electrodynamics and optics. In these
  1283. fields it has not appreciably altered the predictions of theory, but
  1284. it has considerably simplified the theoretical structure, i.e. the
  1285. derivation of laws, and -- what is incomparably more important -- it
  1286. has considerably reduced the number of independent hypothese forming
  1287. the basis of theory. The special theory of relativity has rendered the
  1288. Maxwell-Lorentz theory so plausible, that the latter would have been
  1289. generally accepted by physicists even if experiment had decided less
  1290. unequivocally in its favour.
  1291.  
  1292. Classical mechanics required to be modified before it could come into
  1293. line with the demands of the special theory of relativity. For the
  1294. main part, however, this modification affects only the laws for rapid
  1295. motions, in which the velocities of matter v are not very small as
  1296. compared with the velocity of light. We have experience of such rapid
  1297. motions only in the case of electrons and ions; for other motions the
  1298. variations from the laws of classical mechanics are too small to make
  1299. themselves evident in practice. We shall not consider the motion of
  1300. stars until we come to speak of the general theory of relativity. In
  1301. accordance with the theory of relativity the kinetic energy of a
  1302. material point of mass m is no longer given by the well-known
  1303. expression
  1304.  
  1305. eq. 15: file eq15.gif
  1306.  
  1307. but by the expression
  1308.  
  1309. eq. 16: file eq16.gif
  1310.  
  1311.  
  1312. This expression approaches infinity as the velocity v approaches the
  1313. velocity of light c. The velocity must therefore always remain less
  1314. than c, however great may be the energies used to produce the
  1315. acceleration. If we develop the expression for the kinetic energy in
  1316. the form of a series, we obtain
  1317.  
  1318. eq. 17: file eq17.gif
  1319.  
  1320.  
  1321. When eq. 18 is small compared with unity, the third of these terms is
  1322. always small in comparison with the second,
  1323.  
  1324. which last is alone considered in classical mechanics. The first term
  1325. mc^2 does not contain the velocity, and requires no consideration if
  1326. we are only dealing with the question as to how the energy of a
  1327. point-mass; depends on the velocity. We shall speak of its essential
  1328. significance later.
  1329.  
  1330. The most important result of a general character to which the special
  1331. theory of relativity has led is concerned with the conception of mass.
  1332. Before the advent of relativity, physics recognised two conservation
  1333. laws of fundamental importance, namely, the law of the canservation of
  1334. energy and the law of the conservation of mass these two fundamental
  1335. laws appeared to be quite independent of each other. By means of the
  1336. theory of relativity they have been united into one law. We shall now
  1337. briefly consider how this unification came about, and what meaning is
  1338. to be attached to it.
  1339.  
  1340. The principle of relativity requires that the law of the concervation
  1341. of energy should hold not only with reference to a co-ordinate system
  1342. K, but also with respect to every co-ordinate system K1 which is in a
  1343. state of uniform motion of translation relative to K, or, briefly,
  1344. relative to every " Galileian " system of co-ordinates. In contrast to
  1345. classical mechanics; the Lorentz transformation is the deciding factor
  1346. in the transition from one such system to another.
  1347.  
  1348. By means of comparatively simple considerations we are led to draw the
  1349. following conclusion from these premises, in conjunction with the
  1350. fundamental equations of the electrodynamics of Maxwell: A body moving
  1351. with the velocity v, which absorbs * an amount of energy E[0] in
  1352. the form of radiation without suffering an alteration in velocity in
  1353. the process, has, as a consequence, its energy increased by an amount
  1354.  
  1355. eq. 19: file eq19.gif
  1356.  
  1357. In consideration of the expression given above for the kinetic energy
  1358. of the body, the required energy of the body comes out to be
  1359.  
  1360. eq. 20: file eq20.gif
  1361.  
  1362.  
  1363. Thus the body has the same energy as a body of mass
  1364.  
  1365. eq.21: file eq21.gif
  1366.  
  1367. moving with the velocity v. Hence we can say: If a body takes up an
  1368. amount of energy E[0], then its inertial mass increases by an amount
  1369.  
  1370. eq. 22: file eq22.gif
  1371.  
  1372.  
  1373. the inertial mass of a body is not a constant but varies according to
  1374. the change in the energy of the body. The inertial mass of a system of
  1375. bodies can even be regarded as a measure of its energy. The law of the
  1376. conservation of the mass of a system becomes identical with the law of
  1377. the conservation of energy, and is only valid provided that the system
  1378. neither takes up nor sends out energy. Writing the expression for the
  1379. energy in the form
  1380.  
  1381. eq. 23: file eq23.gif
  1382.  
  1383. we see that the term mc^2, which has hitherto attracted our attention,
  1384. is nothing else than the energy possessed by the body ** before it
  1385. absorbed the energy E[0].
  1386.  
  1387. A direct comparison of this relation with experiment is not possible
  1388. at the present time (1920; see *** Note, p. 48), owing to the fact that
  1389. the changes in energy E[0] to which we can Subject a system are not
  1390. large enough to make themselves perceptible as a change in the
  1391. inertial mass of the system.
  1392.  
  1393. eq. 22: file eq22.gif
  1394.  
  1395.  
  1396. is too small in comparison with the mass m, which was present before
  1397. the alteration of the energy. It is owing to this circumstance that
  1398. classical mechanics was able to establish successfully the
  1399. conservation of mass as a law of independent validity.
  1400.  
  1401. Let me add a final remark of a fundamental nature. The success of the
  1402. Faraday-Maxwell interpretation of electromagnetic action at a distance
  1403. resulted in physicists becoming convinced that there are no such
  1404. things as instantaneous actions at a distance (not involving an
  1405. intermediary medium) of the type of Newton's law of gravitation.
  1406. According to the theory of relativity, action at a distance with the
  1407. velocity of light always takes the place of instantaneous action at a
  1408. distance or of action at a distance with an infinite velocity of
  1409. transmission. This is connected with the fact that the velocity c
  1410. plays a fundamental role in this theory. In Part II we shall see in
  1411. what way this result becomes modified in the general theory of
  1412. relativity.
  1413.  
  1414.  
  1415. Notes
  1416.  
  1417. *) E[0] is the energy taken up, as judged from a co-ordinate system
  1418. moving with the body.
  1419.  
  1420. **) As judged from a co-ordinate system moving with the body.
  1421.  
  1422. ***[Note] The equation E = mc^2 has been thoroughly proved time and
  1423. again since this time.
  1424.  
  1425.  
  1426.  
  1427. EXPERIENCE AND THE SPECIAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY
  1428.  
  1429.  
  1430. To what extent is the special theory of relativity supported by
  1431. experience? This question is not easily answered for the reason
  1432. already mentioned in connection with the fundamental experiment of
  1433. Fizeau. The special theory of relativity has crystallised out from the
  1434. Maxwell-Lorentz theory of electromagnetic phenomena. Thus all facts of
  1435. experience which support the electromagnetic theory also support the
  1436. theory of relativity. As being of particular importance, I mention
  1437. here the fact that the theory of relativity enables us to predict the
  1438. effects produced on the light reaching us from the fixed stars. These
  1439. results are obtained in an exceedingly simple manner, and the effects
  1440. indicated, which are due to the relative motion of the earth with
  1441. reference to those fixed stars are found to be in accord with
  1442. experience. We refer to the yearly movement of the apparent position
  1443. of the fixed stars resulting from the motion of the earth round the
  1444. sun (aberration), and to the influence of the radial components of the
  1445. relative motions of the fixed stars with respect to the earth on the
  1446. colour of the light reaching us from them. The latter effect manifests
  1447. itself in a slight displacement of the spectral lines of the light
  1448. transmitted to us from a fixed star, as compared with the position of
  1449. the same spectral lines when they are produced by a terrestrial source
  1450. of light (Doppler principle). The experimental arguments in favour of
  1451. the Maxwell-Lorentz theory, which are at the same time arguments in
  1452. favour of the theory of relativity, are too numerous to be set forth
  1453. here. In reality they limit the theoretical possibilities to such an
  1454. extent, that no other theory than that of Maxwell and Lorentz has been
  1455. able to hold its own when tested by experience.
  1456.  
  1457. But there are two classes of experimental facts hitherto obtained
  1458. which can be represented in the Maxwell-Lorentz theory only by the
  1459. introduction of an auxiliary hypothesis, which in itself -- i.e.
  1460. without making use of the theory of relativity -- appears extraneous.
  1461.  
  1462. It is known that cathode rays and the so-called b-rays emitted by
  1463. radioactive substances consist of negatively electrified particles
  1464. (electrons) of very small inertia and large velocity. By examining the
  1465. deflection of these rays under the influence of electric and magnetic
  1466. fields, we can study the law of motion of these particles very
  1467. exactly.
  1468.  
  1469. In the theoretical treatment of these electrons, we are faced with the
  1470. difficulty that electrodynamic theory of itself is unable to give an
  1471. account of their nature. For since electrical masses of one sign repel
  1472. each other, the negative electrical masses constituting the electron
  1473. would necessarily be scattered under the influence of their mutual
  1474. repulsions, unless there are forces of another kind operating between
  1475. them, the nature of which has hitherto remained obscure to us.* If
  1476. we now assume that the relative distances between the electrical
  1477. masses constituting the electron remain unchanged during the motion of
  1478. the electron (rigid connection in the sense of classical mechanics),
  1479. we arrive at a law of motion of the electron which does not agree with
  1480. experience. Guided by purely formal points of view, H. A. Lorentz was
  1481. the first to introduce the hypothesis that the form of the electron
  1482. experiences a contraction in the direction of motion in consequence of
  1483. that motion. the contracted length being proportional to the
  1484. expression
  1485.  
  1486. eq. 05: file eq05.gif
  1487.  
  1488. This, hypothesis, which is not justifiable by any electrodynamical
  1489. facts, supplies us then with that particular law of motion which has
  1490. been confirmed with great precision in recent years.
  1491.  
  1492. The theory of relativity leads to the same law of motion, without
  1493. requiring any special hypothesis whatsoever as to the structure and
  1494. the behaviour of the electron. We arrived at a similar conclusion in
  1495. Section 13 in connection with the experiment of Fizeau, the result
  1496. of which is foretold by the theory of relativity without the necessity
  1497. of drawing on hypotheses as to the physical nature of the liquid.
  1498.  
  1499. The second class of facts to which we have alluded has reference to
  1500. the question whether or not the motion of the earth in space can be
  1501. made perceptible in terrestrial experiments. We have already remarked
  1502. in Section 5 that all attempts of this nature led to a negative
  1503. result. Before the theory of relativity was put forward, it was
  1504. difficult to become reconciled to this negative result, for reasons
  1505. now to be discussed. The inherited prejudices about time and space did
  1506. not allow any doubt to arise as to the prime importance of the
  1507. Galileian transformation for changing over from one body of reference
  1508. to another. Now assuming that the Maxwell-Lorentz equations hold for a
  1509. reference-body K, we then find that they do not hold for a
  1510. reference-body K1 moving uniformly with respect to K, if we assume
  1511. that the relations of the Galileian transformstion exist between the
  1512. co-ordinates of K and K1. It thus appears that, of all Galileian
  1513. co-ordinate systems, one (K) corresponding to a particular state of
  1514. motion is physically unique. This result was interpreted physically by
  1515. regarding K as at rest with respect to a hypothetical æther of space.
  1516. On the other hand, all coordinate systems K1 moving relatively to K
  1517. were to be regarded as in motion with respect to the æther. To this
  1518. motion of K1 against the æther ("æther-drift " relative to K1) were
  1519. attributed the more complicated laws which were supposed to hold
  1520. relative to K1. Strictly speaking, such an æther-drift ought also to
  1521. be assumed relative to the earth, and for a long time the efforts of
  1522. physicists were devoted to attempts to detect the existence of an
  1523. æther-drift at the earth's surface.
  1524.  
  1525. In one of the most notable of these attempts Michelson devised a
  1526. method which appears as though it must be decisive. Imagine two
  1527. mirrors so arranged on a rigid body that the reflecting surfaces face
  1528. each other. A ray of light requires a perfectly definite time T to
  1529. pass from one mirror to the other and back again, if the whole system
  1530. be at rest with respect to the æther. It is found by calculation,
  1531. however, that a slightly different time T1 is required for this
  1532. process, if the body, together with the mirrors, be moving relatively
  1533. to the æther. And yet another point: it is shown by calculation that
  1534. for a given velocity v with reference to the æther, this time T1 is
  1535. different when the body is moving perpendicularly to the planes of the
  1536. mirrors from that resulting when the motion is parallel to these
  1537. planes. Although the estimated difference between these two times is
  1538. exceedingly small, Michelson and Morley performed an experiment
  1539. involving interference in which this difference should have been
  1540. clearly detectable. But the experiment gave a negative result -- a
  1541. fact very perplexing to physicists. Lorentz and FitzGerald rescued the
  1542. theory from this difficulty by assuming that the motion of the body
  1543. relative to the æther produces a contraction of the body in the
  1544. direction of motion, the amount of contraction being just sufficient
  1545. to compensate for the differeace in time mentioned above. Comparison
  1546. with the discussion in Section 11 shows that also from the
  1547. standpoint of the theory of relativity this solution of the difficulty
  1548. was the right one. But on the basis of the theory of relativity the
  1549. method of interpretation is incomparably more satisfactory. According
  1550. to this theory there is no such thing as a " specially favoured "
  1551. (unique) co-ordinate system to occasion the introduction of the
  1552. æther-idea, and hence there can be no æther-drift, nor any experiment
  1553. with which to demonstrate it. Here the contraction of moving bodies
  1554. follows from the two fundamental principles of the theory, without the
  1555. introduction of particular hypotheses ; and as the prime factor
  1556. involved in this contraction we find, not the motion in itself, to
  1557. which we cannot attach any meaning, but the motion with respect to the
  1558. body of reference chosen in the particular case in point. Thus for a
  1559. co-ordinate system moving with the earth the mirror system of
  1560. Michelson and Morley is not shortened, but it is shortened for a
  1561. co-ordinate system which is at rest relatively to the sun.
  1562.  
  1563.  
  1564. Notes
  1565.  
  1566. *) The general theory of relativity renders it likely that the
  1567. electrical masses of an electron are held together by gravitational
  1568. forces.
  1569.  
  1570.  
  1571.  
  1572. MINKOWSKI'S FOUR-DIMENSIONAL SPACE
  1573.  
  1574.  
  1575. The non-mathematician is seized by a mysterious shuddering when he
  1576. hears of "four-dimensional" things, by a feeling not unlike that
  1577. awakened by thoughts of the occult. And yet there is no more
  1578. common-place statement than that the world in which we live is a
  1579. four-dimensional space-time continuum.
  1580.  
  1581. Space is a three-dimensional continuum. By this we mean that it is
  1582. possible to describe the position of a point (at rest) by means of
  1583. three numbers (co-ordinales) x, y, z, and that there is an indefinite
  1584. number of points in the neighbourhood of this one, the position of
  1585. which can be described by co-ordinates such as x[1], y[1], z[1], which
  1586. may be as near as we choose to the respective values of the
  1587. co-ordinates x, y, z, of the first point. In virtue of the latter
  1588. property we speak of a " continuum," and owing to the fact that there
  1589. are three co-ordinates we speak of it as being " three-dimensional."
  1590.  
  1591. Similarly, the world of physical phenomena which was briefly called "
  1592. world " by Minkowski is naturally four dimensional in the space-time
  1593. sense. For it is composed of individual events, each of which is
  1594. described by four numbers, namely, three space co-ordinates x, y, z,
  1595. and a time co-ordinate, the time value t. The" world" is in this sense
  1596. also a continuum; for to every event there are as many "neighbouring"
  1597. events (realised or at least thinkable) as we care to choose, the
  1598. co-ordinates x[1], y[1], z[1], t[1] of which differ by an indefinitely
  1599. small amount from those of the event x, y, z, t originally considered.
  1600. That we have not been accustomed to regard the world in this sense as
  1601. a four-dimensional continuum is due to the fact that in physics,
  1602. before the advent of the theory of relativity, time played a different
  1603. and more independent role, as compared with the space coordinates. It
  1604. is for this reason that we have been in the habit of treating time as
  1605. an independent continuum. As a matter of fact, according to classical
  1606. mechanics, time is absolute, i.e. it is independent of the position
  1607. and the condition of motion of the system of co-ordinates. We see this
  1608. expressed in the last equation of the Galileian transformation (t1 =
  1609. t)
  1610.  
  1611. The four-dimensional mode of consideration of the "world" is natural
  1612. on the theory of relativity, since according to this theory time is
  1613. robbed of its independence. This is shown by the fourth equation of
  1614. the Lorentz transformation:
  1615.  
  1616. eq. 24: file eq24.gif
  1617.  
  1618.  
  1619. Moreover, according to this equation the time difference Dt1 of two
  1620. events with respect to K1 does not in general vanish, even when the
  1621. time difference Dt1 of the same events with reference to K vanishes.
  1622. Pure " space-distance " of two events with respect to K results in "
  1623. time-distance " of the same events with respect to K. But the
  1624. discovery of Minkowski, which was of importance for the formal
  1625. development of the theory of relativity, does not lie here. It is to
  1626. be found rather in the fact of his recognition that the
  1627. four-dimensional space-time continuum of the theory of relativity, in
  1628. its most essential formal properties, shows a pronounced relationship
  1629. to the three-dimensional continuum of Euclidean geometrical
  1630. space.* In order to give due prominence to this relationship,
  1631. however, we must replace the usual time co-ordinate t by an imaginary
  1632. magnitude eq. 25 proportional to it. Under these conditions, the
  1633. natural laws satisfying the demands of the (special) theory of
  1634. relativity assume mathematical forms, in which the time co-ordinate
  1635. plays exactly the same role as the three space co-ordinates. Formally,
  1636. these four co-ordinates correspond exactly to the three space
  1637. co-ordinates in Euclidean geometry. It must be clear even to the
  1638. non-mathematician that, as a consequence of this purely formal
  1639. addition to our knowledge, the theory perforce gained clearness in no
  1640. mean measure.
  1641.  
  1642. These inadequate remarks can give the reader only a vague notion of
  1643. the important idea contributed by Minkowski. Without it the general
  1644. theory of relativity, of which the fundamental ideas are developed in
  1645. the following pages, would perhaps have got no farther than its long
  1646. clothes. Minkowski's work is doubtless difficult of access to anyone
  1647. inexperienced in mathematics, but since it is not necessary to have a
  1648. very exact grasp of this work in order to understand the fundamental
  1649. ideas of either the special or the general theory of relativity, I
  1650. shall leave it here at present, and revert to it only towards the end
  1651. of Part 2.
  1652.  
  1653.  
  1654. Notes
  1655.  
  1656. *) Cf. the somewhat more detailed discussion in Appendix II.
  1657.  
  1658.  
  1659.  
  1660.  
  1661. PART II
  1662.  
  1663. THE GENERAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY
  1664.  
  1665.  
  1666. SPECIAL AND GENERAL PRINCIPLE OF RELATIVITY
  1667.  
  1668.  
  1669. The basal principle, which was the pivot of all our previous
  1670. considerations, was the special principle of relativity, i.e. the
  1671. principle of the physical relativity of all uniform motion. Let as
  1672. once more analyse its meaning carefully.
  1673.  
  1674. It was at all times clear that, from the point of view of the idea it
  1675. conveys to us, every motion must be considered only as a relative
  1676. motion. Returning to the illustration we have frequently used of the
  1677. embankment and the railway carriage, we can express the fact of the
  1678. motion here taking place in the following two forms, both of which are
  1679. equally justifiable :
  1680.  
  1681. (a) The carriage is in motion relative to the embankment,
  1682. (b) The embankment is in motion relative to the carriage.
  1683.  
  1684. In (a) the embankment, in (b) the carriage, serves as the body of
  1685. reference in our statement of the motion taking place. If it is simply
  1686. a question of detecting or of describing the motion involved, it is in
  1687. principle immaterial to what reference-body we refer the motion. As
  1688. already mentioned, this is self-evident, but it must not be confused
  1689. with the much more comprehensive statement called "the principle of
  1690. relativity," which we have taken as the basis of our investigations.
  1691.  
  1692. The principle we have made use of not only maintains that we may
  1693. equally well choose the carriage or the embankment as our
  1694. reference-body for the description of any event (for this, too, is
  1695. self-evident). Our principle rather asserts what follows : If we
  1696. formulate the general laws of nature as they are obtained from
  1697. experience, by making use of
  1698.  
  1699. (a) the embankment as reference-body,
  1700. (b) the railway carriage as reference-body,
  1701.  
  1702. then these general laws of nature (e.g. the laws of mechanics or the
  1703. law of the propagation of light in vacuo) have exactly the same form
  1704. in both cases. This can also be expressed as follows : For the
  1705. physical description of natural processes, neither of the reference
  1706. bodies K, K1 is unique (lit. " specially marked out ") as compared
  1707. with the other. Unlike the first, this latter statement need not of
  1708. necessity hold a priori; it is not contained in the conceptions of "
  1709. motion" and " reference-body " and derivable from them; only
  1710. experience can decide as to its correctness or incorrectness.
  1711.  
  1712. Up to the present, however, we have by no means maintained the
  1713. equivalence of all bodies of reference K in connection with the
  1714. formulation of natural laws. Our course was more on the following
  1715. Iines. In the first place, we started out from the assumption that
  1716. there exists a reference-body K, whose condition of motion is such
  1717. that the Galileian law holds with respect to it : A particle left to
  1718. itself and sufficiently far removed from all other particles moves
  1719. uniformly in a straight line. With reference to K (Galileian
  1720. reference-body) the laws of nature were to be as simple as possible.
  1721. But in addition to K, all bodies of reference K1 should be given
  1722. preference in this sense, and they should be exactly equivalent to K
  1723. for the formulation of natural laws, provided that they are in a state
  1724. of uniform rectilinear and non-rotary motion with respect to K ; all
  1725. these bodies of reference are to be regarded as Galileian
  1726. reference-bodies. The validity of the principle of relativity was
  1727. assumed only for these reference-bodies, but not for others (e.g.
  1728. those possessing motion of a different kind). In this sense we speak
  1729. of the special principle of relativity, or special theory of
  1730. relativity.
  1731.  
  1732. In contrast to this we wish to understand by the "general principle of
  1733. relativity" the following statement : All bodies of reference K, K1,
  1734. etc., are equivalent for the description of natural phenomena
  1735. (formulation of the general laws of nature), whatever may be their
  1736. state of motion. But before proceeding farther, it ought to be pointed
  1737. out that this formulation must be replaced later by a more abstract
  1738. one, for reasons which will become evident at a later stage.
  1739.  
  1740. Since the introduction of the special principle of relativity has been
  1741. justified, every intellect which strives after generalisation must
  1742. feel the temptation to venture the step towards the general principle
  1743. of relativity. But a simple and apparently quite reliable
  1744. consideration seems to suggest that, for the present at any rate,
  1745. there is little hope of success in such an attempt; Let us imagine
  1746. ourselves transferred to our old friend the railway carriage, which is
  1747. travelling at a uniform rate. As long as it is moving unifromly, the
  1748. occupant of the carriage is not sensible of its motion, and it is for
  1749. this reason that he can without reluctance interpret the facts of the
  1750. case as indicating that the carriage is at rest, but the embankment in
  1751. motion. Moreover, according to the special principle of relativity,
  1752. this interpretation is quite justified also from a physical point of
  1753. view.
  1754.  
  1755. If the motion of the carriage is now changed into a non-uniform
  1756. motion, as for instance by a powerful application of the brakes, then
  1757. the occupant of the carriage experiences a correspondingly powerful
  1758. jerk forwards. The retarded motion is manifested in the mechanical
  1759. behaviour of bodies relative to the person in the railway carriage.
  1760. The mechanical behaviour is different from that of the case previously
  1761. considered, and for this reason it would appear to be impossible that
  1762. the same mechanical laws hold relatively to the non-uniformly moving
  1763. carriage, as hold with reference to the carriage when at rest or in
  1764. uniform motion. At all events it is clear that the Galileian law does
  1765. not hold with respect to the non-uniformly moving carriage. Because of
  1766. this, we feel compelled at the present juncture to grant a kind of
  1767. absolute physical reality to non-uniform motion, in opposition to the
  1768. general principle of relatvity. But in what follows we shall soon see
  1769. that this conclusion cannot be maintained.
  1770.  
  1771.  
  1772.  
  1773. THE GRAVITATIONAL FIELD
  1774.  
  1775.  
  1776. "If we pick up a stone and then let it go, why does it fall to the
  1777. ground ?" The usual answer to this question is: "Because it is
  1778. attracted by the earth." Modern physics formulates the answer rather
  1779. differently for the following reason. As a result of the more careful
  1780. study of electromagnetic phenomena, we have come to regard action at a
  1781. distance as a process impossible without the intervention of some
  1782. intermediary medium. If, for instance, a magnet attracts a piece of
  1783. iron, we cannot be content to regard this as meaning that the magnet
  1784. acts directly on the iron through the intermediate empty space, but we
  1785. are constrained to imagine -- after the manner of Faraday -- that the
  1786. magnet always calls into being something physically real in the space
  1787. around it, that something being what we call a "magnetic field." In
  1788. its turn this magnetic field operates on the piece of iron, so that
  1789. the latter strives to move towards the magnet. We shall not discuss
  1790. here the justification for this incidental conception, which is indeed
  1791. a somewhat arbitrary one. We shall only mention that with its aid
  1792. electromagnetic phenomena can be theoretically represented much more
  1793. satisfactorily than without it, and this applies particularly to the
  1794. transmission of electromagnetic waves. The effects of gravitation also
  1795. are regarded in an analogous manner.
  1796.  
  1797. The action of the earth on the stone takes place indirectly. The earth
  1798. produces in its surrounding a gravitational field, which acts on the
  1799. stone and produces its motion of fall. As we know from experience, the
  1800. intensity of the action on a body dimishes according to a quite
  1801. definite law, as we proceed farther and farther away from the earth.
  1802. From our point of view this means : The law governing the properties
  1803. of the gravitational field in space must be a perfectly definite one,
  1804. in order correctly to represent the diminution of gravitational action
  1805. with the distance from operative bodies. It is something like this:
  1806. The body (e.g. the earth) produces a field in its immediate
  1807. neighbourhood directly; the intensity and direction of the field at
  1808. points farther removed from the body are thence determined by the law
  1809. which governs the properties in space of the gravitational fields
  1810. themselves.
  1811.  
  1812. In contrast to electric and magnetic fields, the gravitational field
  1813. exhibits a most remarkable property, which is of fundamental
  1814. importance for what follows. Bodies which are moving under the sole
  1815. influence of a gravitational field receive an acceleration, which does
  1816. not in the least depend either on the material or on the physical
  1817. state of the body. For instance, a piece of lead and a piece of wood
  1818. fall in exactly the same manner in a gravitational field (in vacuo),
  1819. when they start off from rest or with the same initial velocity. This
  1820. law, which holds most accurately, can be expressed in a different form
  1821. in the light of the following consideration.
  1822.  
  1823. According to Newton's law of motion, we have
  1824.  
  1825. (Force) = (inertial mass) x (acceleration),
  1826.  
  1827. where the "inertial mass" is a characteristic constant of the
  1828. accelerated body. If now gravitation is the cause of the acceleration,
  1829. we then have
  1830.  
  1831. (Force) = (gravitational mass) x (intensity of the gravitational
  1832. field),
  1833.  
  1834. where the "gravitational mass" is likewise a characteristic constant
  1835. for the body. From these two relations follows:
  1836.  
  1837. eq. 26: file eq26.gif
  1838.  
  1839.  
  1840. If now, as we find from experience, the acceleration is to be
  1841. independent of the nature and the condition of the body and always the
  1842. same for a given gravitational field, then the ratio of the
  1843. gravitational to the inertial mass must likewise be the same for all
  1844. bodies. By a suitable choice of units we can thus make this ratio
  1845. equal to unity. We then have the following law: The gravitational mass
  1846. of a body is equal to its inertial law.
  1847.  
  1848. It is true that this important law had hitherto been recorded in
  1849. mechanics, but it had not been interpreted. A satisfactory
  1850. interpretation can be obtained only if we recognise the following fact
  1851. : The same quality of a body manifests itself according to
  1852. circumstances as " inertia " or as " weight " (lit. " heaviness '). In
  1853. the following section we shall show to what extent this is actually
  1854. the case, and how this question is connected with the general
  1855. postulate of relativity.
  1856.  
  1857.  
  1858.  
  1859.  
  1860. THE EQUALITY OF INERTIAL AND GRAVITATIONAL MASS
  1861. AS AN ARGUMENT FOR THE GENERAL POSTULE OF RELATIVITY
  1862.  
  1863.  
  1864. We imagine a large portion of empty space, so far removed from stars
  1865. and other appreciable masses, that we have before us approximately the
  1866. conditions required by the fundamental law of Galilei. It is then
  1867. possible to choose a Galileian reference-body for this part of space
  1868. (world), relative to which points at rest remain at rest and points in
  1869. motion continue permanently in uniform rectilinear motion. As
  1870. reference-body let us imagine a spacious chest resembling a room with
  1871. an observer inside who is equipped with apparatus. Gravitation
  1872. naturally does not exist for this observer. He must fasten himself
  1873. with strings to the floor, otherwise the slightest impact against the
  1874. floor will cause him to rise slowly towards the ceiling of the room.
  1875.  
  1876. To the middle of the lid of the chest is fixed externally a hook with
  1877. rope attached, and now a " being " (what kind of a being is immaterial
  1878. to us) begins pulling at this with a constant force. The chest
  1879. together with the observer then begin to move "upwards" with a
  1880. uniformly accelerated motion. In course of time their velocity will
  1881. reach unheard-of values -- provided that we are viewing all this from
  1882. another reference-body which is not being pulled with a rope.
  1883.  
  1884. But how does the man in the chest regard the Process ? The
  1885. acceleration of the chest will be transmitted to him by the reaction
  1886. of the floor of the chest. He must therefore take up this pressure by
  1887. means of his legs if he does not wish to be laid out full length on
  1888. the floor. He is then standing in the chest in exactly the same way as
  1889. anyone stands in a room of a home on our earth. If he releases a body
  1890. which he previously had in his land, the accelertion of the chest will
  1891. no longer be transmitted to this body, and for this reason the body
  1892. will approach the floor of the chest with an accelerated relative
  1893. motion. The observer will further convince himself that the
  1894. acceleration of the body towards the floor of the chest is always of
  1895. the same magnitude, whatever kind of body he may happen to use for the
  1896. experiment.
  1897.  
  1898. Relying on his knowledge of the gravitational field (as it was
  1899. discussed in the preceding section), the man in the chest will thus
  1900. come to the conclusion that he and the chest are in a gravitational
  1901. field which is constant with regard to time. Of course he will be
  1902. puzzled for a moment as to why the chest does not fall in this
  1903. gravitational field. just then, however, he discovers the hook in the
  1904. middle of the lid of the chest and the rope which is attached to it,
  1905. and he consequently comes to the conclusion that the chest is
  1906. suspended at rest in the gravitational field.
  1907.  
  1908. Ought we to smile at the man and say that he errs in his conclusion ?
  1909. I do not believe we ought to if we wish to remain consistent ; we must
  1910. rather admit that his mode of grasping the situation violates neither
  1911. reason nor known mechanical laws. Even though it is being accelerated
  1912. with respect to the "Galileian space" first considered, we can
  1913. nevertheless regard the chest as being at rest. We have thus good
  1914. grounds for extending the principle of relativity to include bodies of
  1915. reference which are accelerated with respect to each other, and as a
  1916. result we have gained a powerful argument for a generalised postulate
  1917. of relativity.
  1918.  
  1919. We must note carefully that the possibility of this mode of
  1920. interpretation rests on the fundamental property of the gravitational
  1921. field of giving all bodies the same acceleration, or, what comes to
  1922. the same thing, on the law of the equality of inertial and
  1923. gravitational mass. If this natural law did not exist, the man in the
  1924. accelerated chest would not be able to interpret the behaviour of the
  1925. bodies around him on the supposition of a gravitational field, and he
  1926. would not be justified on the grounds of experience in supposing his
  1927. reference-body to be " at rest."
  1928.  
  1929. Suppose that the man in the chest fixes a rope to the inner side of
  1930. the lid, and that he attaches a body to the free end of the rope. The
  1931. result of this will be to strech the rope so that it will hang "
  1932. vertically " downwards. If we ask for an opinion of the cause of
  1933. tension in the rope, the man in the chest will say: "The suspended
  1934. body experiences a downward force in the gravitational field, and this
  1935. is neutralised by the tension of the rope ; what determines the
  1936. magnitude of the tension of the rope is the gravitational mass of the
  1937. suspended body." On the other hand, an observer who is poised freely
  1938. in space will interpret the condition of things thus : " The rope must
  1939. perforce take part in the accelerated motion of the chest, and it
  1940. transmits this motion to the body attached to it. The tension of the
  1941. rope is just large enough to effect the acceleration of the body. That
  1942. which determines the magnitude of the tension of the rope is the
  1943. inertial mass of the body." Guided by this example, we see that our
  1944. extension of the principle of relativity implies the necessity of the
  1945. law of the equality of inertial and gravitational mass. Thus we have
  1946. obtained a physical interpretation of this law.
  1947.  
  1948. From our consideration of the accelerated chest we see that a general
  1949. theory of relativity must yield important results on the laws of
  1950. gravitation. In point of fact, the systematic pursuit of the general
  1951. idea of relativity has supplied the laws satisfied by the
  1952. gravitational field. Before proceeding farther, however, I must warn
  1953. the reader against a misconception suggested by these considerations.
  1954. A gravitational field exists for the man in the chest, despite the
  1955. fact that there was no such field for the co-ordinate system first
  1956. chosen. Now we might easily suppose that the existence of a
  1957. gravitational field is always only an apparent one. We might also
  1958. think that, regardless of the kind of gravitational field which may be
  1959. present, we could always choose another reference-body such that no
  1960. gravitational field exists with reference to it. This is by no means
  1961. true for all gravitational fields, but only for those of quite special
  1962. form. It is, for instance, impossible to choose a body of reference
  1963. such that, as judged from it, the gravitational field of the earth (in
  1964. its entirety) vanishes.
  1965.  
  1966. We can now appreciate why that argument is not convincing, which we
  1967. brought forward against the general principle of relativity at theend
  1968. of Section 18. It is certainly true that the observer in the
  1969. railway carriage experiences a jerk forwards as a result of the
  1970. application of the brake, and that he recognises, in this the
  1971. non-uniformity of motion (retardation) of the carriage. But he is
  1972. compelled by nobody to refer this jerk to a " real " acceleration
  1973. (retardation) of the carriage. He might also interpret his experience
  1974. thus: " My body of reference (the carriage) remains permanently at
  1975. rest. With reference to it, however, there exists (during the period
  1976. of application of the brakes) a gravitational field which is directed
  1977. forwards and which is variable with respect to time. Under the
  1978. influence of this field, the embankment together with the earth moves
  1979. non-uniformly in such a manner that their original velocity in the
  1980. backwards direction is continuously reduced."
  1981.  
  1982.  
  1983.  
  1984. IN WHAT RESPECTS ARE THE FOUNDATIONS OF CLASSICAL MECHANICS AND OF THE
  1985. SPECIAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY UNSATISFACTORY?
  1986.  
  1987.  
  1988. We have already stated several times that classical mechanics starts
  1989. out from the following law: Material particles sufficiently far
  1990. removed from other material particles continue to move uniformly in a
  1991. straight line or continue in a state of rest. We have also repeatedly
  1992. emphasised that this fundamental law can only be valid for bodies of
  1993. reference K which possess certain unique states of motion, and which
  1994. are in uniform translational motion relative to each other. Relative
  1995. to other reference-bodies K the law is not valid. Both in classical
  1996. mechanics and in the special theory of relativity we therefore
  1997. differentiate between reference-bodies K relative to which the
  1998. recognised " laws of nature " can be said to hold, and
  1999. reference-bodies K relative to which these laws do not hold.
  2000.  
  2001. But no person whose mode of thought is logical can rest satisfied with
  2002. this condition of things. He asks : " How does it come that certain
  2003. reference-bodies (or their states of motion) are given priority over
  2004. other reference-bodies (or their states of motion) ? What is the
  2005. reason for this Preference? In order to show clearly what I mean by
  2006. this question, I shall make use of a comparison.
  2007.  
  2008. I am standing in front of a gas range. Standing alongside of each
  2009. other on the range are two pans so much alike that one may be mistaken
  2010. for the other. Both are half full of water. I notice that steam is
  2011. being emitted continuously from the one pan, but not from the other. I
  2012. am surprised at this, even if I have never seen either a gas range or
  2013. a pan before. But if I now notice a luminous something of bluish
  2014. colour under the first pan but not under the other, I cease to be
  2015. astonished, even if I have never before seen a gas flame. For I can
  2016. only say that this bluish something will cause the emission of the
  2017. steam, or at least possibly it may do so. If, however, I notice the
  2018. bluish something in neither case, and if I observe that the one
  2019. continuously emits steam whilst the other does not, then I shall
  2020. remain astonished and dissatisfied until I have discovered some
  2021. circumstance to which I can attribute the different behaviour of the
  2022. two pans.
  2023.  
  2024. Analogously, I seek in vain for a real something in classical
  2025. mechanics (or in the special theory of relativity) to which I can
  2026. attribute the different behaviour of bodies considered with respect to
  2027. the reference systems K and K1.* Newton saw this objection and
  2028. attempted to invalidate it, but without success. But E. Mach recognsed
  2029. it most clearly of all, and because of this objection he claimed that
  2030. mechanics must be placed on a new basis. It can only be got rid of by
  2031. means of a physics which is conformable to the general principle of
  2032. relativity, since the equations of such a theory hold for every body
  2033. of reference, whatever may be its state of motion.
  2034.  
  2035.  
  2036. Notes
  2037.  
  2038. *) The objection is of importance more especially when the state of
  2039. motion of the reference-body is of such a nature that it does not
  2040. require any external agency for its maintenance, e.g. in the case when
  2041. the reference-body is rotating uniformly.
  2042.  
  2043.  
  2044.  
  2045. A FEW INFERENCES FROM THE GENERAL PRINCIPLE OF RELATIVITY
  2046.  
  2047.  
  2048. The considerations of Section 20 show that the general principle of
  2049. relativity puts us in a position to derive properties of the
  2050. gravitational field in a purely theoretical manner. Let us suppose,
  2051. for instance, that we know the space-time " course " for any natural
  2052. process whatsoever, as regards the manner in which it takes place in
  2053. the Galileian domain relative to a Galileian body of reference K. By
  2054. means of purely theoretical operations (i.e. simply by calculation) we
  2055. are then able to find how this known natural process appears, as seen
  2056. from a reference-body K1 which is accelerated relatively to K. But
  2057. since a gravitational field exists with respect to this new body of
  2058. reference K1, our consideration also teaches us how the gravitational
  2059. field influences the process studied.
  2060.  
  2061. For example, we learn that a body which is in a state of uniform
  2062. rectilinear motion with respect to K (in accordance with the law of
  2063. Galilei) is executing an accelerated and in general curvilinear motion
  2064. with respect to the accelerated reference-body K1 (chest). This
  2065. acceleration or curvature corresponds to the influence on the moving
  2066. body of the gravitational field prevailing relatively to K. It is
  2067. known that a gravitational field influences the movement of bodies in
  2068. this way, so that our consideration supplies us with nothing
  2069. essentially new.
  2070.  
  2071. However, we obtain a new result of fundamental importance when we
  2072. carry out the analogous consideration for a ray of light. With respect
  2073. to the Galileian reference-body K, such a ray of light is transmitted
  2074. rectilinearly with the velocity c. It can easily be shown that the
  2075. path of the same ray of light is no longer a straight line when we
  2076. consider it with reference to the accelerated chest (reference-body
  2077. K1). From this we conclude, that, in general, rays of light are
  2078. propagated curvilinearly in gravitational fields. In two respects this
  2079. result is of great importance.
  2080.  
  2081. In the first place, it can be compared with the reality. Although a
  2082. detailed examination of the question shows that the curvature of light
  2083. rays required by the general theory of relativity is only exceedingly
  2084. small for the gravitational fields at our disposal in practice, its
  2085. estimated magnitude for light rays passing the sun at grazing
  2086. incidence is nevertheless 1.7 seconds of arc. This ought to manifest
  2087. itself in the following way. As seen from the earth, certain fixed
  2088. stars appear to be in the neighbourhood of the sun, and are thus
  2089. capable of observation during a total eclipse of the sun. At such
  2090. times, these stars ought to appear to be displaced outwards from the
  2091. sun by an amount indicated above, as compared with their apparent
  2092. position in the sky when the sun is situated at another part of the
  2093. heavens. The examination of the correctness or otherwise of this
  2094. deduction is a problem of the greatest importance, the early solution
  2095. of which is to be expected of astronomers.[2]*
  2096.  
  2097. In the second place our result shows that, according to the general
  2098. theory of relativity, the law of the constancy of the velocity of
  2099. light in vacuo, which constitutes one of the two fundamental
  2100. assumptions in the special theory of relativity and to which we have
  2101. already frequently referred, cannot claim any unlimited validity. A
  2102. curvature of rays of light can only take place when the velocity of
  2103. propagation of light varies with position. Now we might think that as
  2104. a consequence of this, the special theory of relativity and with it
  2105. the whole theory of relativity would be laid in the dust. But in
  2106. reality this is not the case. We can only conclude that the special
  2107. theory of relativity cannot claim an unlinlited domain of validity ;
  2108. its results hold only so long as we are able to disregard the
  2109. influences of gravitational fields on the phenomena (e.g. of light).
  2110.  
  2111. Since it has often been contended by opponents of the theory of
  2112. relativity that the special theory of relativity is overthrown by the
  2113. general theory of relativity, it is perhaps advisable to make the
  2114. facts of the case clearer by means of an appropriate comparison.
  2115. Before the development of electrodynamics the laws of electrostatics
  2116. were looked upon as the laws of electricity. At the present time we
  2117. know that electric fields can be derived correctly from electrostatic
  2118. considerations only for the case, which is never strictly realised, in
  2119. which the electrical masses are quite at rest relatively to each
  2120. other, and to the co-ordinate system. Should we be justified in saying
  2121. that for this reason electrostatics is overthrown by the
  2122. field-equations of Maxwell in electrodynamics ? Not in the least.
  2123. Electrostatics is contained in electrodynamics as a limiting case ;
  2124. the laws of the latter lead directly to those of the former for the
  2125. case in which the fields are invariable with regard to time. No fairer
  2126. destiny could be allotted to any physical theory, than that it should
  2127. of itself point out the way to the introduction of a more
  2128. comprehensive theory, in which it lives on as a limiting case.
  2129.  
  2130. In the example of the transmission of light just dealt with, we have
  2131. seen that the general theory of relativity enables us to derive
  2132. theoretically the influence of a gravitational field on the course of
  2133. natural processes, the Iaws of which are already known when a
  2134. gravitational field is absent. But the most attractive problem, to the
  2135. solution of which the general theory of relativity supplies the key,
  2136. concerns the investigation of the laws satisfied by the gravitational
  2137. field itself. Let us consider this for a moment.
  2138.  
  2139. We are acquainted with space-time domains which behave (approximately)
  2140. in a " Galileian " fashion under suitable choice of reference-body,
  2141. i.e. domains in which gravitational fields are absent. If we now refer
  2142. such a domain to a reference-body K1 possessing any kind of motion,
  2143. then relative to K1 there exists a gravitational field which is
  2144. variable with respect to space and time.[3]** The character of this
  2145. field will of course depend on the motion chosen for K1. According to
  2146. the general theory of relativity, the general law of the gravitational
  2147. field must be satisfied for all gravitational fields obtainable in
  2148. this way. Even though by no means all gravitationial fields can be
  2149. produced in this way, yet we may entertain the hope that the general
  2150. law of gravitation will be derivable from such gravitational fields of
  2151. a special kind. This hope has been realised in the most beautiful
  2152. manner. But between the clear vision of this goal and its actual
  2153. realisation it was necessary to surmount a serious difficulty, and as
  2154. this lies deep at the root of things, I dare not withhold it from the
  2155. reader. We require to extend our ideas of the space-time continuum
  2156. still farther.
  2157.  
  2158.  
  2159. Notes
  2160.  
  2161. *) By means of the star photographs of two expeditions equipped by
  2162. a Joint Committee of the Royal and Royal Astronomical Societies, the
  2163. existence of the deflection of light demanded by theory was first
  2164. confirmed during the solar eclipse of 29th May, 1919. (Cf. Appendix
  2165. III.)
  2166.  
  2167. **) This follows from a generalisation of the discussion in
  2168. Section 20
  2169.  
  2170.  
  2171.  
  2172. BEHAVIOUR OF CLOCKS AND MEASURING-RODS ON A ROTATING BODY OF REFERENCE
  2173.  
  2174.  
  2175. Hitherto I have purposely refrained from speaking about the physical
  2176. interpretation of space- and time-data in the case of the general
  2177. theory of relativity. As a consequence, I am guilty of a certain
  2178. slovenliness of treatment, which, as we know from the special theory
  2179. of relativity, is far from being unimportant and pardonable. It is now
  2180. high time that we remedy this defect; but I would mention at the
  2181. outset, that this matter lays no small claims on the patience and on
  2182. the power of abstraction of the reader.
  2183.  
  2184. We start off again from quite special cases, which we have frequently
  2185. used before. Let us consider a space time domain in which no
  2186. gravitational field exists relative to a reference-body K whose state
  2187. of motion has been suitably chosen. K is then a Galileian
  2188. reference-body as regards the domain considered, and the results of
  2189. the special theory of relativity hold relative to K. Let us supposse
  2190. the same domain referred to a second body of reference K1, which is
  2191. rotating uniformly with respect to K. In order to fix our ideas, we
  2192. shall imagine K1 to be in the form of a plane circular disc, which
  2193. rotates uniformly in its own plane about its centre. An observer who
  2194. is sitting eccentrically on the disc K1 is sensible of a force which
  2195. acts outwards in a radial direction, and which would be interpreted as
  2196. an effect of inertia (centrifugal force) by an observer who was at
  2197. rest with respect to the original reference-body K. But the observer
  2198. on the disc may regard his disc as a reference-body which is " at rest
  2199. " ; on the basis of the general principle of relativity he is
  2200. justified in doing this. The force acting on himself, and in fact on
  2201. all other bodies which are at rest relative to the disc, he regards as
  2202. the effect of a gravitational field. Nevertheless, the
  2203. space-distribution of this gravitational field is of a kind that would
  2204. not be possible on Newton's theory of gravitation.* But since the
  2205. observer believes in the general theory of relativity, this does not
  2206. disturb him; he is quite in the right when he believes that a general
  2207. law of gravitation can be formulated- a law which not only explains
  2208. the motion of the stars correctly, but also the field of force
  2209. experienced by himself.
  2210.  
  2211. The observer performs experiments on his circular disc with clocks and
  2212. measuring-rods. In doing so, it is his intention to arrive at exact
  2213. definitions for the signification of time- and space-data with
  2214. reference to the circular disc K1, these definitions being based on
  2215. his observations. What will be his experience in this enterprise ?
  2216.  
  2217. To start with, he places one of two identically constructed clocks at
  2218. the centre of the circular disc, and the other on the edge of the
  2219. disc, so that they are at rest relative to it. We now ask ourselves
  2220. whether both clocks go at the same rate from the standpoint of the
  2221. non-rotating Galileian reference-body K. As judged from this body, the
  2222. clock at the centre of the disc has no velocity, whereas the clock at
  2223. the edge of the disc is in motion relative to K in consequence of the
  2224. rotation. According to a result obtained in Section 12, it follows
  2225. that the latter clock goes at a rate permanently slower than that of
  2226. the clock at the centre of the circular disc, i.e. as observed from K.
  2227. It is obvious that the same effect would be noted by an observer whom
  2228. we will imagine sitting alongside his clock at the centre of the
  2229. circular disc. Thus on our circular disc, or, to make the case more
  2230. general, in every gravitational field, a clock will go more quickly or
  2231. less quickly, according to the position in which the clock is situated
  2232. (at rest). For this reason it is not possible to obtain a reasonable
  2233. definition of time with the aid of clocks which are arranged at rest
  2234. with respect to the body of reference. A similar difficulty presents
  2235. itself when we attempt to apply our earlier definition of simultaneity
  2236. in such a case, but I do not wish to go any farther into this
  2237. question.
  2238.  
  2239. Moreover, at this stage the definition of the space co-ordinates also
  2240. presents insurmountable difficulties. If the observer applies his
  2241. standard measuring-rod (a rod which is short as compared with the
  2242. radius of the disc) tangentially to the edge of the disc, then, as
  2243. judged from the Galileian system, the length of this rod will be less
  2244. than I, since, according to Section 12, moving bodies suffer a
  2245. shortening in the direction of the motion. On the other hand, the
  2246. measaring-rod will not experience a shortening in length, as judged
  2247. from K, if it is applied to the disc in the direction of the radius.
  2248. If, then, the observer first measures the circumference of the disc
  2249. with his measuring-rod and then the diameter of the disc, on dividing
  2250. the one by the other, he will not obtain as quotient the familiar
  2251. number p = 3.14 . . ., but a larger number,[4]** whereas of course,
  2252. for a disc which is at rest with respect to K, this operation would
  2253. yield p exactly. This proves that the propositions of Euclidean
  2254. geometry cannot hold exactly on the rotating disc, nor in general in a
  2255. gravitational field, at least if we attribute the length I to the rod
  2256. in all positions and in every orientation. Hence the idea of a
  2257. straight line also loses its meaning. We are therefore not in a
  2258. position to define exactly the co-ordinates x, y, z relative to the
  2259. disc by means of the method used in discussing the special theory, and
  2260. as long as the co- ordinates and times of events have not been
  2261. defined, we cannot assign an exact meaning to the natural laws in
  2262. which these occur.
  2263.  
  2264. Thus all our previous conclusions based on general relativity would
  2265. appear to be called in question. In reality we must make a subtle
  2266. detour in order to be able to apply the postulate of general
  2267. relativity exactly. I shall prepare the reader for this in the
  2268. following paragraphs.
  2269.  
  2270.  
  2271. Notes
  2272.  
  2273. *) The field disappears at the centre of the disc and increases
  2274. proportionally to the distance from the centre as we proceed outwards.
  2275.  
  2276. **) Throughout this consideration we have to use the Galileian
  2277. (non-rotating) system K as reference-body, since we may only assume
  2278. the validity of the results of the special theory of relativity
  2279. relative to K (relative to K1 a gravitational field prevails).
  2280.  
  2281.  
  2282.  
  2283. EUCLIDEAN AND NON-EUCLIDEAN CONTINUUM
  2284.  
  2285.  
  2286. The surface of a marble table is spread out in front of me. I can get
  2287. from any one point on this table to any other point by passing
  2288. continuously from one point to a " neighbouring " one, and repeating
  2289. this process a (large) number of times, or, in other words, by going
  2290. from point to point without executing "jumps." I am sure the reader
  2291. will appreciate with sufficient clearness what I mean here by "
  2292. neighbouring " and by " jumps " (if he is not too pedantic). We
  2293. express this property of the surface by describing the latter as a
  2294. continuum.
  2295.  
  2296. Let us now imagine that a large number of little rods of equal length
  2297. have been made, their lengths being small compared with the dimensions
  2298. of the marble slab. When I say they are of equal length, I mean that
  2299. one can be laid on any other without the ends overlapping. We next lay
  2300. four of these little rods on the marble slab so that they constitute a
  2301. quadrilateral figure (a square), the diagonals of which are equally
  2302. long. To ensure the equality of the diagonals, we make use of a little
  2303. testing-rod. To this square we add similar ones, each of which has one
  2304. rod in common with the first. We proceed in like manner with each of
  2305. these squares until finally the whole marble slab is laid out with
  2306. squares. The arrangement is such, that each side of a square belongs
  2307. to two squares and each corner to four squares.
  2308.  
  2309. It is a veritable wonder that we can carry out this business without
  2310. getting into the greatest difficulties. We only need to think of the
  2311. following. If at any moment three squares meet at a corner, then two
  2312. sides of the fourth square are already laid, and, as a consequence,
  2313. the arrangement of the remaining two sides of the square is already
  2314. completely determined. But I am now no longer able to adjust the
  2315. quadrilateral so that its diagonals may be equal. If they are equal of
  2316. their own accord, then this is an especial favour of the marble slab
  2317. and of the little rods, about which I can only be thankfully
  2318. surprised. We must experience many such surprises if the construction
  2319. is to be successful.
  2320.  
  2321. If everything has really gone smoothly, then I say that the points of
  2322. the marble slab constitute a Euclidean continuum with respect to the
  2323. little rod, which has been used as a " distance " (line-interval). By
  2324. choosing one corner of a square as " origin" I can characterise every
  2325. other corner of a square with reference to this origin by means of two
  2326. numbers. I only need state how many rods I must pass over when,
  2327. starting from the origin, I proceed towards the " right " and then "
  2328. upwards," in order to arrive at the corner of the square under
  2329. consideration. These two numbers are then the " Cartesian co-ordinates
  2330. " of this corner with reference to the " Cartesian co-ordinate system"
  2331. which is determined by the arrangement of little rods.
  2332.  
  2333. By making use of the following modification of this abstract
  2334. experiment, we recognise that there must also be cases in which the
  2335. experiment would be unsuccessful. We shall suppose that the rods "
  2336. expand " by in amount proportional to the increase of temperature. We
  2337. heat the central part of the marble slab, but not the periphery, in
  2338. which case two of our little rods can still be brought into
  2339. coincidence at every position on the table. But our construction of
  2340. squares must necessarily come into disorder during the heating,
  2341. because the little rods on the central region of the table expand,
  2342. whereas those on the outer part do not.
  2343.  
  2344. With reference to our little rods -- defined as unit lengths -- the
  2345. marble slab is no longer a Euclidean continuum, and we are also no
  2346. longer in the position of defining Cartesian co-ordinates directly
  2347. with their aid, since the above construction can no longer be carried
  2348. out. But since there are other things which are not influenced in a
  2349. similar manner to the little rods (or perhaps not at all) by the
  2350. temperature of the table, it is possible quite naturally to maintain
  2351. the point of view that the marble slab is a " Euclidean continuum."
  2352. This can be done in a satisfactory manner by making a more subtle
  2353. stipulation about the measurement or the comparison of lengths.
  2354.  
  2355. But if rods of every kind (i.e. of every material) were to behave in
  2356. the same way as regards the influence of temperature when they are on
  2357. the variably heated marble slab, and if we had no other means of
  2358. detecting the effect of temperature than the geometrical behaviour of
  2359. our rods in experiments analogous to the one described above, then our
  2360. best plan would be to assign the distance one to two points on the
  2361. slab, provided that the ends of one of our rods could be made to
  2362. coincide with these two points ; for how else should we define the
  2363. distance without our proceeding being in the highest measure grossly
  2364. arbitrary ? The method of Cartesian coordinates must then be
  2365. discarded, and replaced by another which does not assume the validity
  2366. of Euclidean geometry for rigid bodies.* The reader will notice
  2367. that the situation depicted here corresponds to the one brought about
  2368. by the general postitlate of relativity (Section 23).
  2369.  
  2370.  
  2371. Notes
  2372.  
  2373. *) Mathematicians have been confronted with our problem in the
  2374. following form. If we are given a surface (e.g. an ellipsoid) in
  2375. Euclidean three-dimensional space, then there exists for this surface
  2376. a two-dimensional geometry, just as much as for a plane surface. Gauss
  2377. undertook the task of treating this two-dimensional geometry from
  2378. first principles, without making use of the fact that the surface
  2379. belongs to a Euclidean continuum of three dimensions. If we imagine
  2380. constructions to be made with rigid rods in the surface (similar to
  2381. that above with the marble slab), we should find that different laws
  2382. hold for these from those resulting on the basis of Euclidean plane
  2383. geometry. The surface is not a Euclidean continuum with respect to the
  2384. rods, and we cannot define Cartesian co-ordinates in the surface.
  2385. Gauss indicated the principles according to which we can treat the
  2386. geometrical relationships in the surface, and thus pointed out the way
  2387. to the method of Riemman of treating multi-dimensional, non-Euclidean
  2388. continuum. Thus it is that mathematicians long ago solved the formal
  2389. problems to which we are led by the general postulate of relativity.
  2390.  
  2391.  
  2392.  
  2393. GAUSSIAN CO-ORDINATES
  2394.  
  2395.  
  2396. According to Gauss, this combined analytical and geometrical mode of
  2397. handling the problem can be arrived at in the following way. We
  2398. imagine a system of arbitrary curves (see Fig. 4) drawn on the surface
  2399. of the table. These we designate as u-curves, and we indicate each of
  2400. them by means of a number. The Curves u= 1, u= 2 and u= 3 are drawn in
  2401. the diagram. Between the curves u= 1 and u= 2 we must imagine an
  2402. infinitely large number to be drawn, all of which correspond to real
  2403. numbers lying between 1 and 2. fig. 04 We have then a system of
  2404. u-curves, and this "infinitely dense" system covers the whole surface
  2405. of the table. These u-curves must not intersect each other, and
  2406. through each point of the surface one and only one curve must pass.
  2407. Thus a perfectly definite value of u belongs to every point on the
  2408. surface of the marble slab. In like manner we imagine a system of
  2409. v-curves drawn on the surface. These satisfy the same conditions as
  2410. the u-curves, they are provided with numbers in a corresponding
  2411. manner, and they may likewise be of arbitrary shape. It follows that a
  2412. value of u and a value of v belong to every point on the surface of
  2413. the table. We call these two numbers the co-ordinates of the surface
  2414. of the table (Gaussian co-ordinates). For example, the point P in the
  2415. diagram has the Gaussian co-ordinates u= 3, v= 1. Two neighbouring
  2416. points P and P1 on the surface then correspond to the co-ordinates
  2417.  
  2418. P: u,v
  2419.  
  2420. P1: u + du, v + dv,
  2421.  
  2422. where du and dv signify very small numbers. In a similar manner we may
  2423. indicate the distance (line-interval) between P and P1, as measured
  2424. with a little rod, by means of the very small number ds. Then
  2425. according to Gauss we have
  2426.  
  2427. ds2 = g[11]du2 + 2g[12]dudv = g[22]dv2
  2428.  
  2429. where g[11], g[12], g[22], are magnitudes which depend in a perfectly
  2430. definite way on u and v. The magnitudes g[11], g[12] and g[22],
  2431. determine the behaviour of the rods relative to the u-curves and
  2432. v-curves, and thus also relative to the surface of the table. For the
  2433. case in which the points of the surface considered form a Euclidean
  2434. continuum with reference to the measuring-rods, but only in this case,
  2435. it is possible to draw the u-curves and v-curves and to attach numbers
  2436. to them, in such a manner, that we simply have :
  2437.  
  2438. ds2 = du2 + dv2
  2439.  
  2440. Under these conditions, the u-curves and v-curves are straight lines
  2441. in the sense of Euclidean geometry, and they are perpendicular to each
  2442. other. Here the Gaussian coordinates are samply Cartesian ones. It is
  2443. clear that Gauss co-ordinates are nothing more than an association of
  2444. two sets of numbers with the points of the surface considered, of such
  2445. a nature that numerical values differing very slightly from each other
  2446. are associated with neighbouring points " in space."
  2447.  
  2448. So far, these considerations hold for a continuum of two dimensions.
  2449. But the Gaussian method can be applied also to a continuum of three,
  2450. four or more dimensions. If, for instance, a continuum of four
  2451. dimensions be supposed available, we may represent it in the following
  2452. way. With every point of the continuum, we associate arbitrarily four
  2453. numbers, x[1], x[2], x[3], x[4], which are known as " co-ordinates."
  2454. Adjacent points correspond to adjacent values of the coordinates. If a
  2455. distance ds is associated with the adjacent points P and P1, this
  2456. distance being measurable and well defined from a physical point of
  2457. view, then the following formula holds:
  2458.  
  2459. ds2 = g[11]dx[1]^2 + 2g[12]dx[1]dx[2] . . . . g[44]dx[4]^2,
  2460.  
  2461. where the magnitudes g[11], etc., have values which vary with the
  2462. position in the continuum. Only when the continuum is a Euclidean one
  2463. is it possible to associate the co-ordinates x[1] . . x[4]. with the
  2464. points of the continuum so that we have simply
  2465.  
  2466. ds2 = dx[1]^2 + dx[2]^2 + dx[3]^2 + dx[4]^2.
  2467.  
  2468. In this case relations hold in the four-dimensional continuum which
  2469. are analogous to those holding in our three-dimensional measurements.
  2470.  
  2471. However, the Gauss treatment for ds2 which we have given above is not
  2472. always possible. It is only possible when sufficiently small regions
  2473. of the continuum under consideration may be regarded as Euclidean
  2474. continua. For example, this obviously holds in the case of the marble
  2475. slab of the table and local variation of temperature. The temperature
  2476. is practically constant for a small part of the slab, and thus the
  2477. geometrical behaviour of the rods is almost as it ought to be
  2478. according to the rules of Euclidean geometry. Hence the imperfections
  2479. of the construction of squares in the previous section do not show
  2480. themselves clearly until this construction is extended over a
  2481. considerable portion of the surface of the table.
  2482.  
  2483. We can sum this up as follows: Gauss invented a method for the
  2484. mathematical treatment of continua in general, in which "
  2485. size-relations " (" distances " between neighbouring points) are
  2486. defined. To every point of a continuum are assigned as many numbers
  2487. (Gaussian coordinates) as the continuum has dimensions. This is done
  2488. in such a way, that only one meaning can be attached to the
  2489. assignment, and that numbers (Gaussian coordinates) which differ by an
  2490. indefinitely small amount are assigned to adjacent points. The
  2491. Gaussian coordinate system is a logical generalisation of the
  2492. Cartesian co-ordinate system. It is also applicable to non-Euclidean
  2493. continua, but only when, with respect to the defined "size" or
  2494. "distance," small parts of the continuum under consideration behave
  2495. more nearly like a Euclidean system, the smaller the part of the
  2496. continuum under our notice.
  2497.  
  2498.  
  2499.  
  2500. THE SPACE-TIME CONTINUUM OF THE SPEICAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY CONSIDERED AS A
  2501. EUCLIDEAN CONTINUUM
  2502.  
  2503.  
  2504. We are now in a position to formulate more exactly the idea of
  2505. Minkowski, which was only vaguely indicated in Section 17. In
  2506. accordance with the special theory of relativity, certain co-ordinate
  2507. systems are given preference for the description of the
  2508. four-dimensional, space-time continuum. We called these " Galileian
  2509. co-ordinate systems." For these systems, the four co-ordinates x, y,
  2510. z, t, which determine an event or -- in other words, a point of the
  2511. four-dimensional continuum -- are defined physically in a simple
  2512. manner, as set forth in detail in the first part of this book. For the
  2513. transition from one Galileian system to another, which is moving
  2514. uniformly with reference to the first, the equations of the Lorentz
  2515. transformation are valid. These last form the basis for the derivation
  2516. of deductions from the special theory of relativity, and in themselves
  2517. they are nothing more than the expression of the universal validity of
  2518. the law of transmission of light for all Galileian systems of
  2519. reference.
  2520.  
  2521. Minkowski found that the Lorentz transformations satisfy the following
  2522. simple conditions. Let us consider two neighbouring events, the
  2523. relative position of which in the four-dimensional continuum is given
  2524. with respect to a Galileian reference-body K by the space co-ordinate
  2525. differences dx, dy, dz and the time-difference dt. With reference to a
  2526. second Galileian system we shall suppose that the corresponding
  2527. differences for these two events are dx1, dy1, dz1, dt1. Then these
  2528. magnitudes always fulfil the condition*
  2529.  
  2530. dx2 + dy2 + dz2 - c^2dt2 = dx1 2 + dy1 2 + dz1 2 - c^2dt1 2.
  2531.  
  2532. The validity of the Lorentz transformation follows from this
  2533. condition. We can express this as follows: The magnitude
  2534.  
  2535. ds2 = dx2 + dy2 + dz2 - c^2dt2,
  2536.  
  2537. which belongs to two adjacent points of the four-dimensional
  2538. space-time continuum, has the same value for all selected (Galileian)
  2539. reference-bodies. If we replace x, y, z, sq. rt. -I . ct , by x[1],
  2540. x[2], x[3], x[4], we also obtaill the result that
  2541.  
  2542. ds2 = dx[1]^2 + dx[2]^2 + dx[3]^2 + dx[4]^2.
  2543.  
  2544. is independent of the choice of the body of reference. We call the
  2545. magnitude ds the " distance " apart of the two events or
  2546. four-dimensional points.
  2547.  
  2548. Thus, if we choose as time-variable the imaginary variable sq. rt. -I
  2549. . ct instead of the real quantity t, we can regard the space-time
  2550. contintium -- accordance with the special theory of relativity -- as a
  2551. ", Euclidean " four-dimensional continuum, a result which follows from
  2552. the considerations of the preceding section.
  2553.  
  2554.  
  2555. Notes
  2556.  
  2557. *) Cf. Appendixes I and 2. The relations which are derived
  2558. there for the co-ordlnates themselves are valid also for co-ordinate
  2559. differences, and thus also for co-ordinate differentials (indefinitely
  2560. small differences).
  2561.  
  2562.  
  2563.  
  2564. THE SPACE-TIME CONTINUUM OF THE GENERAL THEORY OF REALTIIVTY IS NOT A
  2565. ECULIDEAN CONTINUUM
  2566.  
  2567.  
  2568. In the first part of this book we were able to make use of space-time
  2569. co-ordinates which allowed of a simple and direct physical
  2570. interpretation, and which, according to Section 26, can be regarded
  2571. as four-dimensional Cartesian co-ordinates. This was possible on the
  2572. basis of the law of the constancy of the velocity of tight. But
  2573. according to Section 21 the general theory of relativity cannot
  2574. retain this law. On the contrary, we arrived at the result that
  2575. according to this latter theory the velocity of light must always
  2576. depend on the co-ordinates when a gravitational field is present. In
  2577. connection with a specific illustration in Section 23, we found
  2578. that the presence of a gravitational field invalidates the definition
  2579. of the coordinates and the ifine, which led us to our objective in the
  2580. special theory of relativity.
  2581.  
  2582. In view of the resuIts of these considerations we are led to the
  2583. conviction that, according to the general principle of relativity, the
  2584. space-time continuum cannot be regarded as a Euclidean one, but that
  2585. here we have the general case, corresponding to the marble slab with
  2586. local variations of temperature, and with which we made acquaintance
  2587. as an example of a two-dimensional continuum. Just as it was there
  2588. impossible to construct a Cartesian co-ordinate system from equal
  2589. rods, so here it is impossible to build up a system (reference-body)
  2590. from rigid bodies and clocks, which shall be of such a nature that
  2591. measuring-rods and clocks, arranged rigidly with respect to one
  2592. another, shaIll indicate position and time directly. Such was the
  2593. essence of the difficulty with which we were confronted in Section
  2594. 23.
  2595.  
  2596. But the considerations of Sections 25 and 26 show us the way to
  2597. surmount this difficulty. We refer the fourdimensional space-time
  2598. continuum in an arbitrary manner to Gauss co-ordinates. We assign to
  2599. every point of the continuum (event) four numbers, x[1], x[2], x[3],
  2600. x[4] (co-ordinates), which have not the least direct physical
  2601. significance, but only serve the purpose of numbering the points of
  2602. the continuum in a definite but arbitrary manner. This arrangement
  2603. does not even need to be of such a kind that we must regard x[1],
  2604. x[2], x[3], as "space" co-ordinates and x[4], as a " time "
  2605. co-ordinate.
  2606.  
  2607. The reader may think that such a description of the world would be
  2608. quite inadequate. What does it mean to assign to an event the
  2609. particular co-ordinates x[1], x[2], x[3], x[4], if in themselves these
  2610. co-ordinates have no significance ? More careful consideration shows,
  2611. however, that this anxiety is unfounded. Let us consider, for
  2612. instance, a material point with any kind of motion. If this point had
  2613. only a momentary existence without duration, then it would to
  2614. described in space-time by a single system of values x[1], x[2], x[3],
  2615. x[4]. Thus its permanent existence must be characterised by an
  2616. infinitely large number of such systems of values, the co-ordinate
  2617. values of which are so close together as to give continuity;
  2618. corresponding to the material point, we thus have a (uni-dimensional)
  2619. line in the four-dimensional continuum. In the same way, any such
  2620. lines in our continuum correspond to many points in motion. The only
  2621. statements having regard to these points which can claim a physical
  2622. existence are in reality the statements about their encounters. In our
  2623. mathematical treatment, such an encounter is expressed in the fact
  2624. that the two lines which represent the motions of the points in
  2625. question have a particular system of co-ordinate values, x[1], x[2],
  2626. x[3], x[4], in common. After mature consideration the reader will
  2627. doubtless admit that in reality such encounters constitute the only
  2628. actual evidence of a time-space nature with which we meet in physical
  2629. statements.
  2630.  
  2631. When we were describing the motion of a material point relative to a
  2632. body of reference, we stated nothing more than the encounters of this
  2633. point with particular points of the reference-body. We can also
  2634. determine the corresponding values of the time by the observation of
  2635. encounters of the body with clocks, in conjunction with the
  2636. observation of the encounter of the hands of clocks with particular
  2637. points on the dials. It is just the same in the case of
  2638. space-measurements by means of measuring-rods, as a litttle
  2639. consideration will show.
  2640.  
  2641. The following statements hold generally : Every physical description
  2642. resolves itself into a number of statements, each of which refers to
  2643. the space-time coincidence of two events A and B. In terms of Gaussian
  2644. co-ordinates, every such statement is expressed by the agreement of
  2645. their four co-ordinates x[1], x[2], x[3], x[4]. Thus in reality, the
  2646. description of the time-space continuum by means of Gauss co-ordinates
  2647. completely replaces the description with the aid of a body of
  2648. reference, without suffering from the defects of the latter mode of
  2649. description; it is not tied down to the Euclidean character of the
  2650. continuum which has to be represented.
  2651.  
  2652.  
  2653.  
  2654. EXACT FORMULATION OF THE GENERAL PRINCIPLE OF RELATIVITY
  2655.  
  2656.  
  2657. We are now in a position to replace the pro. visional formulation of
  2658. the general principle of relativity given in Section 18 by an exact
  2659. formulation. The form there used, "All bodies of reference K, K1,
  2660. etc., are equivalent for the description of natural phenomena
  2661. (formulation of the general laws of nature), whatever may be their
  2662. state of motion," cannot be maintained, because the use of rigid
  2663. reference-bodies, in the sense of the method followed in the special
  2664. theory of relativity, is in general not possible in space-time
  2665. description. The Gauss co-ordinate system has to take the place of the
  2666. body of reference. The following statement corresponds to the
  2667. fundamental idea of the general principle of relativity: "All Gaussian
  2668. co-ordinate systems are essentially equivalent for the formulation of
  2669. the general laws of nature."
  2670.  
  2671. We can state this general principle of relativity in still another
  2672. form, which renders it yet more clearly intelligible than it is when
  2673. in the form of the natural extension of the special principle of
  2674. relativity. According to the special theory of relativity, the
  2675. equations which express the general laws of nature pass over into
  2676. equations of the same form when, by making use of the Lorentz
  2677. transformation, we replace the space-time variables x, y, z, t, of a
  2678. (Galileian) reference-body K by the space-time variables x1, y1, z1,
  2679. t1, of a new reference-body K1. According to the general theory of
  2680. relativity, on the other hand, by application of arbitrary
  2681. substitutions of the Gauss variables x[1], x[2], x[3], x[4], the
  2682. equations must pass over into equations of the same form; for every
  2683. transformation (not only the Lorentz transformation) corresponds to
  2684. the transition of one Gauss co-ordinate system into another.
  2685.  
  2686. If we desire to adhere to our "old-time" three-dimensional view of
  2687. things, then we can characterise the development which is being
  2688. undergone by the fundamental idea of the general theory of relativity
  2689. as follows : The special theory of relativity has reference to
  2690. Galileian domains, i.e. to those in which no gravitational field
  2691. exists. In this connection a Galileian reference-body serves as body
  2692. of reference, i.e. a rigid body the state of motion of which is so
  2693. chosen that the Galileian law of the uniform rectilinear motion of
  2694. "isolated" material points holds relatively to it.
  2695.  
  2696. Certain considerations suggest that we should refer the same Galileian
  2697. domains to non-Galileian reference-bodies also. A gravitational field
  2698. of a special kind is then present with respect to these bodies (cf.
  2699. Sections 20 and 23).
  2700.  
  2701. In gravitational fields there are no such things as rigid bodies with
  2702. Euclidean properties; thus the fictitious rigid body of reference is
  2703. of no avail in the general theory of relativity. The motion of clocks
  2704. is also influenced by gravitational fields, and in such a way that a
  2705. physical definition of time which is made directly with the aid of
  2706. clocks has by no means the same degree of plausibility as in the
  2707. special theory of relativity.
  2708.  
  2709. For this reason non-rigid reference-bodies are used, which are as a
  2710. whole not only moving in any way whatsoever, but which also suffer
  2711. alterations in form ad lib. during their motion. Clocks, for which the
  2712. law of motion is of any kind, however irregular, serve for the
  2713. definition of time. We have to imagine each of these clocks fixed at a
  2714. point on the non-rigid reference-body. These clocks satisfy only the
  2715. one condition, that the "readings" which are observed simultaneously
  2716. on adjacent clocks (in space) differ from each other by an
  2717. indefinitely small amount. This non-rigid reference-body, which might
  2718. appropriately be termed a "reference-mollusc", is in the main
  2719. equivalent to a Gaussian four-dimensional co-ordinate system chosen
  2720. arbitrarily. That which gives the "mollusc" a certain
  2721. comprehensibility as compared with the Gauss co-ordinate system is the
  2722. (really unjustified) formal retention of the separate existence of the
  2723. space co-ordinates as opposed to the time co-ordinate. Every point on
  2724. the mollusc is treated as a space-point, and every material point
  2725. which is at rest relatively to it as at rest, so long as the mollusc
  2726. is considered as reference-body. The general principle of relativity
  2727. requires that all these molluscs can be used as reference-bodies with
  2728. equal right and equal success in the formulation of the general laws
  2729. of nature; the laws themselves must be quite independent of the choice
  2730. of mollusc.
  2731.  
  2732. The great power possessed by the general principle of relativity lies
  2733. in the comprehensive limitation which is imposed on the laws of nature
  2734. in consequence of what we have seen above.
  2735.  
  2736.  
  2737.  
  2738. THE SOLUTION OF THE PROBLEM OF GRAVITATION ON THE BASIS OF THE GENERAL
  2739. PRINCIPLE OF RELATIVITY
  2740.  
  2741.  
  2742. If the reader has followed all our previous considerations, he will
  2743. have no further difficulty in understanding the methods leading to the
  2744. solution of the problem of gravitation.
  2745.  
  2746. We start off on a consideration of a Galileian domain, i.e. a domain
  2747. in which there is no gravitational field relative to the Galileian
  2748. reference-body K. The behaviour of measuring-rods and clocks with
  2749. reference to K is known from the special theory of relativity,
  2750. likewise the behaviour of "isolated" material points; the latter move
  2751. uniformly and in straight lines.
  2752.  
  2753. Now let us refer this domain to a random Gauss coordinate system or to
  2754. a "mollusc" as reference-body K1. Then with respect to K1 there is a
  2755. gravitational field G (of a particular kind). We learn the behaviour
  2756. of measuring-rods and clocks and also of freely-moving material points
  2757. with reference to K1 simply by mathematical transformation. We
  2758. interpret this behaviour as the behaviour of measuring-rods, docks and
  2759. material points tinder the influence of the gravitational field G.
  2760. Hereupon we introduce a hypothesis: that the influence of the
  2761. gravitational field on measuringrods, clocks and freely-moving
  2762. material points continues to take place according to the same laws,
  2763. even in the case where the prevailing gravitational field is not
  2764. derivable from the Galfleian special care, simply by means of a
  2765. transformation of co-ordinates.
  2766.  
  2767. The next step is to investigate the space-time behaviour of the
  2768. gravitational field G, which was derived from the Galileian special
  2769. case simply by transformation of the coordinates. This behaviour is
  2770. formulated in a law, which is always valid, no matter how the
  2771. reference-body (mollusc) used in the description may be chosen.
  2772.  
  2773. This law is not yet the general law of the gravitational field, since
  2774. the gravitational field under consideration is of a special kind. In
  2775. order to find out the general law-of-field of gravitation we still
  2776. require to obtain a generalisation of the law as found above. This can
  2777. be obtained without caprice, however, by taking into consideration the
  2778. following demands:
  2779.  
  2780. (a) The required generalisation must likewise satisfy the general
  2781. postulate of relativity.
  2782.  
  2783. (b) If there is any matter in the domain under consideration, only its
  2784. inertial mass, and thus according to Section 15 only its energy is
  2785. of importance for its etfect in exciting a field.
  2786.  
  2787. (c) Gravitational field and matter together must satisfy the law of
  2788. the conservation of energy (and of impulse).
  2789.  
  2790. Finally, the general principle of relativity permits us to determine
  2791. the influence of the gravitational field on the course of all those
  2792. processes which take place according to known laws when a
  2793. gravitational field is absent i.e. which have already been fitted into
  2794. the frame of the special theory of relativity. In this connection we
  2795. proceed in principle according to the method which has already been
  2796. explained for measuring-rods, clocks and freely moving material
  2797. points.
  2798.  
  2799. The theory of gravitation derived in this way from the general
  2800. postulate of relativity excels not only in its beauty ; nor in
  2801. removing the defect attaching to classical mechanics which was brought
  2802. to light in Section 21; nor in interpreting the empirical law of
  2803. the equality of inertial and gravitational mass ; but it has also
  2804. already explained a result of observation in astronomy, against which
  2805. classical mechanics is powerless.
  2806.  
  2807. If we confine the application of the theory to the case where the
  2808. gravitational fields can be regarded as being weak, and in which all
  2809. masses move with respect to the coordinate system with velocities
  2810. which are small compared with the velocity of light, we then obtain as
  2811. a first approximation the Newtonian theory. Thus the latter theory is
  2812. obtained here without any particular assumption, whereas Newton had to
  2813. introduce the hypothesis that the force of attraction between mutually
  2814. attracting material points is inversely proportional to the square of
  2815. the distance between them. If we increase the accuracy of the
  2816. calculation, deviations from the theory of Newton make their
  2817. appearance, practically all of which must nevertheless escape the test
  2818. of observation owing to their smallness.
  2819.  
  2820. We must draw attention here to one of these deviations. According to
  2821. Newton's theory, a planet moves round the sun in an ellipse, which
  2822. would permanently maintain its position with respect to the fixed
  2823. stars, if we could disregard the motion of the fixed stars themselves
  2824. and the action of the other planets under consideration. Thus, if we
  2825. correct the observed motion of the planets for these two influences,
  2826. and if Newton's theory be strictly correct, we ought to obtain for the
  2827. orbit of the planet an ellipse, which is fixed with reference to the
  2828. fixed stars. This deduction, which can be tested with great accuracy,
  2829. has been confirmed for all the planets save one, with the precision
  2830. that is capable of being obtained by the delicacy of observation
  2831. attainable at the present time. The sole exception is Mercury, the
  2832. planet which lies nearest the sun. Since the time of Leverrier, it has
  2833. been known that the ellipse corresponding to the orbit of Mercury,
  2834. after it has been corrected for the influences mentioned above, is not
  2835. stationary with respect to the fixed stars, but that it rotates
  2836. exceedingly slowly in the plane of the orbit and in the sense of the
  2837. orbital motion. The value obtained for this rotary movement of the
  2838. orbital ellipse was 43 seconds of arc per century, an amount ensured
  2839. to be correct to within a few seconds of arc. This effect can be
  2840. explained by means of classical mechanics only on the assumption of
  2841. hypotheses which have little probability, and which were devised
  2842. solely for this purponse.
  2843.  
  2844. On the basis of the general theory of relativity, it is found that the
  2845. ellipse of every planet round the sun must necessarily rotate in the
  2846. manner indicated above ; that for all the planets, with the exception
  2847. of Mercury, this rotation is too small to be detected with the
  2848. delicacy of observation possible at the present time ; but that in the
  2849. case of Mercury it must amount to 43 seconds of arc per century, a
  2850. result which is strictly in agreement with observation.
  2851.  
  2852. Apart from this one, it has hitherto been possible to make only two
  2853. deductions from the theory which admit of being tested by observation,
  2854. to wit, the curvature of light rays by the gravitational field of the
  2855. sun,*x and a displacement of the spectral lines of light reaching
  2856. us from large stars, as compared with the corresponding lines for
  2857. light produced in an analogous manner terrestrially (i.e. by the same
  2858. kind of atom).** These two deductions from the theory have both
  2859. been confirmed.
  2860.  
  2861.  
  2862. Notes
  2863.  
  2864. *) First observed by Eddington and others in 1919. (Cf. Appendix
  2865. III, pp. 126-129).
  2866.  
  2867. **) Established by Adams in 1924. (Cf. p. 132)
  2868.  
  2869.  
  2870.  
  2871.  
  2872. PART III
  2873.  
  2874. CONSIDERATIONS ON THE UNIVERSE AS A WHOLE
  2875.  
  2876.  
  2877. COSMOLOGICAL DIFFICULTIES OF NEWTON'S THEORY
  2878.  
  2879.  
  2880. Part from the difficulty discussed in Section 21, there is a second
  2881. fundamental difficulty attending classical celestial mechanics, which,
  2882. to the best of my knowledge, was first discussed in detail by the
  2883. astronomer Seeliger. If we ponder over the question as to how the
  2884. universe, considered as a whole, is to be regarded, the first answer
  2885. that suggests itself to us is surely this: As regards space (and time)
  2886. the universe is infinite. There are stars everywhere, so that the
  2887. density of matter, although very variable in detail, is nevertheless
  2888. on the average everywhere the same. In other words: However far we
  2889. might travel through space, we should find everywhere an attenuated
  2890. swarm of fixed stars of approrimately the same kind and density.
  2891.  
  2892. This view is not in harmony with the theory of Newton. The latter
  2893. theory rather requires that the universe should have a kind of centre
  2894. in which the density of the stars is a maximum, and that as we proceed
  2895. outwards from this centre the group-density of the stars should
  2896. diminish, until finally, at great distances, it is succeeded by an
  2897. infinite region of emptiness. The stellar universe ought to be a
  2898. finite island in the infinite ocean of space.*
  2899.  
  2900. This conception is in itself not very satisfactory. It is still less
  2901. satisfactory because it leads to the result that the light emitted by
  2902. the stars and also individual stars of the stellar system are
  2903. perpetually passing out into infinite space, never to return, and
  2904. without ever again coming into interaction with other objects of
  2905. nature. Such a finite material universe would be destined to become
  2906. gradually but systematically impoverished.
  2907.  
  2908. In order to escape this dilemma, Seeliger suggested a modification of
  2909. Newton's law, in which he assumes that for great distances the force
  2910. of attraction between two masses diminishes more rapidly than would
  2911. result from the inverse square law. In this way it is possible for the
  2912. mean density of matter to be constant everywhere, even to infinity,
  2913. without infinitely large gravitational fields being produced. We thus
  2914. free ourselves from the distasteful conception that the material
  2915. universe ought to possess something of the nature of a centre. Of
  2916. course we purchase our emancipation from the fundamental difficulties
  2917. mentioned, at the cost of a modification and complication of Newton's
  2918. law which has neither empirical nor theoretical foundation. We can
  2919. imagine innumerable laws which would serve the same purpose, without
  2920. our being able to state a reason why one of them is to be preferred to
  2921. the others ; for any one of these laws would be founded just as little
  2922. on more general theoretical principles as is the law of Newton.
  2923.  
  2924.  
  2925. Notes
  2926.  
  2927. *) Proof -- According to the theory of Newton, the number of "lines
  2928. of force" which come from infinity and terminate in a mass m is
  2929. proportional to the mass m. If, on the average, the Mass density p[0]
  2930. is constant throughout tithe universe, then a sphere of volume V will
  2931. enclose the average man p[0]V. Thus the number of lines of force
  2932. passing through the surface F of the sphere into its interior is
  2933. proportional to p[0] V. For unit area of the surface of the sphere the
  2934. number of lines of force which enters the sphere is thus proportional
  2935. to p[0] V/F or to p[0]R. Hence the intensity of the field at the
  2936. surface would ultimately become infinite with increasing radius R of
  2937. the sphere, which is impossible.
  2938.  
  2939.  
  2940.  
  2941. THE POSSIBILITY OF A "FINITE" AND YET "UNBOUNDED" UNIVERSE
  2942.  
  2943.  
  2944. But speculations on the structure of the universe also move in quite
  2945. another direction. The development of non-Euclidean geometry led to
  2946. the recognition of the fact, that we can cast doubt on the
  2947. infiniteness of our space without coming into conflict with the laws
  2948. of thought or with experience (Riemann, Helmholtz). These questions
  2949. have already been treated in detail and with unsurpassable lucidity by
  2950. Helmholtz and Poincaré, whereas I can only touch on them briefly here.
  2951.  
  2952. In the first place, we imagine an existence in two dimensional space.
  2953. Flat beings with flat implements, and in particular flat rigid
  2954. measuring-rods, are free to move in a plane. For them nothing exists
  2955. outside of this plane: that which they observe to happen to themselves
  2956. and to their flat " things " is the all-inclusive reality of their
  2957. plane. In particular, the constructions of plane Euclidean geometry
  2958. can be carried out by means of the rods e.g. the lattice construction,
  2959. considered in Section 24. In contrast to ours, the universe of
  2960. these beings is two-dimensional; but, like ours, it extends to
  2961. infinity. In their universe there is room for an infinite number of
  2962. identical squares made up of rods, i.e. its volume (surface) is
  2963. infinite. If these beings say their universe is " plane," there is
  2964. sense in the statement, because they mean that they can perform the
  2965. constructions of plane Euclidean geometry with their rods. In this
  2966. connection the individual rods always represent the same distance,
  2967. independently of their position.
  2968.  
  2969. Let us consider now a second two-dimensional existence, but this time
  2970. on a spherical surface instead of on a plane. The flat beings with
  2971. their measuring-rods and other objects fit exactly on this surface and
  2972. they are unable to leave it. Their whole universe of observation
  2973. extends exclusively over the surface of the sphere. Are these beings
  2974. able to regard the geometry of their universe as being plane geometry
  2975. and their rods withal as the realisation of " distance " ? They cannot
  2976. do this. For if they attempt to realise a straight line, they will
  2977. obtain a curve, which we " three-dimensional beings " designate as a
  2978. great circle, i.e. a self-contained line of definite finite length,
  2979. which can be measured up by means of a measuring-rod. Similarly, this
  2980. universe has a finite area that can be compared with the area, of a
  2981. square constructed with rods. The great charm resulting from this
  2982. consideration lies in the recognition of the fact that the universe of
  2983. these beings is finite and yet has no limits.
  2984.  
  2985. But the spherical-surface beings do not need to go on a world-tour in
  2986. order to perceive that they are not living in a Euclidean universe.
  2987. They can convince themselves of this on every part of their " world,"
  2988. provided they do not use too small a piece of it. Starting from a
  2989. point, they draw " straight lines " (arcs of circles as judged in
  2990. three dimensional space) of equal length in all directions. They will
  2991. call the line joining the free ends of these lines a " circle." For a
  2992. plane surface, the ratio of the circumference of a circle to its
  2993. diameter, both lengths being measured with the same rod, is, according
  2994. to Euclidean geometry of the plane, equal to a constant value p, which
  2995. is independent of the diameter of the circle. On their spherical
  2996. surface our flat beings would find for this ratio the value
  2997.  
  2998. eq. 27: file eq27.gif
  2999.  
  3000. i.e. a smaller value than p, the difference being the more
  3001. considerable, the greater is the radius of the circle in comparison
  3002. with the radius R of the " world-sphere." By means of this relation
  3003. the spherical beings can determine the radius of their universe ("
  3004. world "), even when only a relatively small part of their worldsphere
  3005. is available for their measurements. But if this part is very small
  3006. indeed, they will no longer be able to demonstrate that they are on a
  3007. spherical " world " and not on a Euclidean plane, for a small part of
  3008. a spherical surface differs only slightly from a piece of a plane of
  3009. the same size.
  3010.  
  3011. Thus if the spherical surface beings are living on a planet of which
  3012. the solar system occupies only a negligibly small part of the
  3013. spherical universe, they have no means of determining whether they are
  3014. living in a finite or in an infinite universe, because the " piece of
  3015. universe " to which they have access is in both cases practically
  3016. plane, or Euclidean. It follows directly from this discussion, that
  3017. for our sphere-beings the circumference of a circle first increases
  3018. with the radius until the " circumference of the universe " is
  3019. reached, and that it thenceforward gradually decreases to zero for
  3020. still further increasing values of the radius. During this process the
  3021. area of the circle continues to increase more and more, until finally
  3022. it becomes equal to the total area of the whole " world-sphere."
  3023.  
  3024. Perhaps the reader will wonder why we have placed our " beings " on a
  3025. sphere rather than on another closed surface. But this choice has its
  3026. justification in the fact that, of all closed surfaces, the sphere is
  3027. unique in possessing the property that all points on it are
  3028. equivalent. I admit that the ratio of the circumference c of a circle
  3029. to its radius r depends on r, but for a given value of r it is the
  3030. same for all points of the " worldsphere "; in other words, the "
  3031. world-sphere " is a " surface of constant curvature."
  3032.  
  3033. To this two-dimensional sphere-universe there is a three-dimensional
  3034. analogy, namely, the three-dimensional spherical space which was
  3035. discovered by Riemann. its points are likewise all equivalent. It
  3036. possesses a finite volume, which is determined by its "radius"
  3037. (2p2R3). Is it possible to imagine a spherical space? To imagine a
  3038. space means nothing else than that we imagine an epitome of our "
  3039. space " experience, i.e. of experience that we can have in the
  3040. movement of " rigid " bodies. In this sense we can imagine a spherical
  3041. space.
  3042.  
  3043. Suppose we draw lines or stretch strings in all directions from a
  3044. point, and mark off from each of these the distance r with a
  3045. measuring-rod. All the free end-points of these lengths lie on a
  3046. spherical surface. We can specially measure up the area (F) of this
  3047. surface by means of a square made up of measuring-rods. If the
  3048. universe is Euclidean, then F = 4pR2 ; if it is spherical, then F is
  3049. always less than 4pR2. With increasing values of r, F increases from
  3050. zero up to a maximum value which is determined by the " world-radius,"
  3051. but for still further increasing values of r, the area gradually
  3052. diminishes to zero. At first, the straight lines which radiate from
  3053. the starting point diverge farther and farther from one another, but
  3054. later they approach each other, and finally they run together again at
  3055. a "counter-point" to the starting point. Under such conditions they
  3056. have traversed the whole spherical space. It is easily seen that the
  3057. three-dimensional spherical space is quite analogous to the
  3058. two-dimensional spherical surface. It is finite (i.e. of finite
  3059. volume), and has no bounds.
  3060.  
  3061. It may be mentioned that there is yet another kind of curved space: "
  3062. elliptical space." It can be regarded as a curved space in which the
  3063. two " counter-points " are identical (indistinguishable from each
  3064. other). An elliptical universe can thus be considered to some extent
  3065. as a curved universe possessing central symmetry.
  3066.  
  3067. It follows from what has been said, that closed spaces without limits
  3068. are conceivable. From amongst these, the spherical space (and the
  3069. elliptical) excels in its simplicity, since all points on it are
  3070. equivalent. As a result of this discussion, a most interesting
  3071. question arises for astronomers and physicists, and that is whether
  3072. the universe in which we live is infinite, or whether it is finite in
  3073. the manner of the spherical universe. Our experience is far from being
  3074. sufficient to enable us to answer this question. But the general
  3075. theory of relativity permits of our answering it with a moduate degree
  3076. of certainty, and in this connection the difficulty mentioned in
  3077. Section 30 finds its solution.
  3078.  
  3079.  
  3080.  
  3081. THE STRUCTURE OF SPACE ACCORDING TO THE GENERAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY
  3082.  
  3083.  
  3084. According to the general theory of relativity, the geometrical
  3085. properties of space are not independent, but they are determined by
  3086. matter. Thus we can draw conclusions about the geometrical structure
  3087. of the universe only if we base our considerations on the state of the
  3088. matter as being something that is known. We know from experience that,
  3089. for a suitably chosen co-ordinate system, the velocities of the stars
  3090. are small as compared with the velocity of transmission of light. We
  3091. can thus as a rough approximation arrive at a conclusion as to the
  3092. nature of the universe as a whole, if we treat the matter as being at
  3093. rest.
  3094.  
  3095. We already know from our previous discussion that the behaviour of
  3096. measuring-rods and clocks is influenced by gravitational fields, i.e.
  3097. by the distribution of matter. This in itself is sufficient to exclude
  3098. the possibility of the exact validity of Euclidean geometry in our
  3099. universe. But it is conceivable that our universe differs only
  3100. slightly from a Euclidean one, and this notion seems all the more
  3101. probable, since calculations show that the metrics of surrounding
  3102. space is influenced only to an exceedingly small extent by masses even
  3103. of the magnitude of our sun. We might imagine that, as regards
  3104. geometry, our universe behaves analogously to a surface which is
  3105. irregularly curved in its individual parts, but which nowhere departs
  3106. appreciably from a plane: something like the rippled surface of a
  3107. lake. Such a universe might fittingly be called a quasi-Euclidean
  3108. universe. As regards its space it would be infinite. But calculation
  3109. shows that in a quasi-Euclidean universe the average density of matter
  3110. would necessarily be nil. Thus such a universe could not be inhabited
  3111. by matter everywhere ; it would present to us that unsatisfactory
  3112. picture which we portrayed in Section 30.
  3113.  
  3114. If we are to have in the universe an average density of matter which
  3115. differs from zero, however small may be that difference, then the
  3116. universe cannot be quasi-Euclidean. On the contrary, the results of
  3117. calculation indicate that if matter be distributed uniformly, the
  3118. universe would necessarily be spherical (or elliptical). Since in
  3119. reality the detailed distribution of matter is not uniform, the real
  3120. universe will deviate in individual parts from the spherical, i.e. the
  3121. universe will be quasi-spherical. But it will be necessarily finite.
  3122. In fact, the theory supplies us with a simple connection * between
  3123. the space-expanse of the universe and the average density of matter in
  3124. it.
  3125.  
  3126.  
  3127. Notes
  3128.  
  3129. *) For the radius R of the universe we obtain the equation
  3130.  
  3131. eq. 28: file eq28.gif
  3132.  
  3133. The use of the C.G.S. system in this equation gives 2/k = 1^.08.10^27;
  3134. p is the average density of the matter and k is a constant connected
  3135. with the Newtonian constant of gravitation.
  3136.  
  3137.  
  3138.  
  3139. APPENDIX I
  3140.  
  3141. SIMPLE DERIVATION OF THE LORENTZ TRANSFORMATION
  3142. (SUPPLEMENTARY TO SECTION 11)
  3143.  
  3144.  
  3145. For the relative orientation of the co-ordinate systems indicated in
  3146. Fig. 2, the x-axes of both systems pernumently coincide. In the
  3147. present case we can divide the problem into parts by considering first
  3148. only events which are localised on the x-axis. Any such event is
  3149. represented with respect to the co-ordinate system K by the abscissa x
  3150. and the time t, and with respect to the system K1 by the abscissa x'
  3151. and the time t'. We require to find x' and t' when x and t are given.
  3152.  
  3153. A light-signal, which is proceeding along the positive axis of x, is
  3154. transmitted according to the equation
  3155.  
  3156. x = ct
  3157.  
  3158. or
  3159.  
  3160. x - ct = 0 . . . (1).
  3161.  
  3162. Since the same light-signal has to be transmitted relative to K1 with
  3163. the velocity c, the propagation relative to the system K1 will be
  3164. represented by the analogous formula
  3165.  
  3166. x' - ct' = O . . . (2)
  3167.  
  3168. Those space-time points (events) which satisfy (x) must also satisfy
  3169. (2). Obviously this will be the case when the relation
  3170.  
  3171. (x' - ct') = l (x - ct) . . . (3).
  3172.  
  3173. is fulfilled in general, where l indicates a constant ; for, according
  3174. to (3), the disappearance of (x - ct) involves the disappearance of
  3175. (x' - ct').
  3176.  
  3177. If we apply quite similar considerations to light rays which are being
  3178. transmitted along the negative x-axis, we obtain the condition
  3179.  
  3180. (x' + ct') = µ(x + ct) . . . (4).
  3181.  
  3182. By adding (or subtracting) equations (3) and (4), and introducing for
  3183. convenience the constants a and b in place of the constants l and µ,
  3184. where
  3185.  
  3186. eq. 29: file eq29.gif
  3187.  
  3188. and
  3189.  
  3190. eq. 30: file eq30.gif
  3191.  
  3192. we obtain the equations
  3193.  
  3194. eq. 31: file eq31.gif
  3195.  
  3196. We should thus have the solution of our problem, if the constants a
  3197. and b were known. These result from the following discussion.
  3198.  
  3199. For the origin of K1 we have permanently x' = 0, and hence according
  3200. to the first of the equations (5)
  3201.  
  3202. eq. 32: file eq32.gif
  3203.  
  3204. If we call v the velocity with which the origin of K1 is moving
  3205. relative to K, we then have
  3206.  
  3207. eq. 33: file eq33.gif
  3208.  
  3209. The same value v can be obtained from equations (5), if we calculate
  3210. the velocity of another point of K1 relative to K, or the velocity
  3211. (directed towards the negative x-axis) of a point of K with respect to
  3212. K'. In short, we can designate v as the relative velocity of the two
  3213. systems.
  3214.  
  3215. Furthermore, the principle of relativity teaches us that, as judged
  3216. from K, the length of a unit measuring-rod which is at rest with
  3217. reference to K1 must be exactly the same as the length, as judged from
  3218. K', of a unit measuring-rod which is at rest relative to K. In order
  3219. to see how the points of the x-axis appear as viewed from K, we only
  3220. require to take a " snapshot " of K1 from K; this means that we have
  3221. to insert a particular value of t (time of K), e.g. t = 0. For this
  3222. value of t we then obtain from the first of the equations (5)
  3223.  
  3224. x' = ax
  3225.  
  3226. Two points of the x'-axis which are separated by the distance Dx' = I
  3227. when measured in the K1 system are thus separated in our instantaneous
  3228. photograph by the distance
  3229.  
  3230. eq. 34: file eq34.gif
  3231.  
  3232. But if the snapshot be taken from K'(t' = 0), and if we eliminate t
  3233. from the equations (5), taking into account the expression (6), we
  3234. obtain
  3235.  
  3236. eq. 35: file eq35.gif
  3237.  
  3238. From this we conclude that two points on the x-axis separated by the
  3239. distance I (relative to K) will be represented on our snapshot by the
  3240. distance
  3241.  
  3242. eq. 36: file eq36.gif
  3243.  
  3244. But from what has been said, the two snapshots must be identical;
  3245. hence Dx in (7) must be equal to Dx' in (7a), so that we obtain
  3246.  
  3247. eq. 37: file eq37.gif
  3248.  
  3249. The equations (6) and (7b) determine the constants a and b. By
  3250. inserting the values of these constants in (5), we obtain the first
  3251. and the fourth of the equations given in Section 11.
  3252.  
  3253. eq. 38: file eq38.gif
  3254.  
  3255. Thus we have obtained the Lorentz transformation for events on the
  3256. x-axis. It satisfies the condition
  3257.  
  3258. x'2 - c^2t'2 = x2 - c^2t2 . . . (8a).
  3259.  
  3260. The extension of this result, to include events which take place
  3261. outside the x-axis, is obtained by retaining equations (8) and
  3262. supplementing them by the relations
  3263.  
  3264. eq. 39: file eq39.gif
  3265.  
  3266. In this way we satisfy the postulate of the constancy of the velocity
  3267. of light in vacuo for rays of light of arbitrary direction, both for
  3268. the system K and for the system K'. This may be shown in the following
  3269. manner.
  3270.  
  3271. We suppose a light-signal sent out from the origin of K at the time t
  3272. = 0. It will be propagated according to the equation
  3273.  
  3274. eq. 40: file eq40.gif
  3275.  
  3276. or, if we square this equation, according to the equation
  3277.  
  3278. x2 + y2 + z2 = c^2t2 = 0 . . . (10).
  3279.  
  3280. It is required by the law of propagation of light, in conjunction with
  3281. the postulate of relativity, that the transmission of the signal in
  3282. question should take place -- as judged from K1 -- in accordance with
  3283. the corresponding formula
  3284.  
  3285. r' = ct'
  3286.  
  3287. or,
  3288.  
  3289. x'2 + y'2 + z'2 - c^2t'2 = 0 . . . (10a).
  3290.  
  3291. In order that equation (10a) may be a consequence of equation (10), we
  3292. must have
  3293.  
  3294. x'2 + y'2 + z'2 - c^2t'2 = s (x2 + y2 + z2 - c^2t2) (11).
  3295.  
  3296. Since equation (8a) must hold for points on the x-axis, we thus have s
  3297. = I. It is easily seen that the Lorentz transformation really
  3298. satisfies equation (11) for s = I; for (11) is a consequence of (8a)
  3299. and (9), and hence also of (8) and (9). We have thus derived the
  3300. Lorentz transformation.
  3301.  
  3302. The Lorentz transformation represented by (8) and (9) still requires
  3303. to be generalised. Obviously it is immaterial whether the axes of K1
  3304. be chosen so that they are spatially parallel to those of K. It is
  3305. also not essential that the velocity of translation of K1 with respect
  3306. to K should be in the direction of the x-axis. A simple consideration
  3307. shows that we are able to construct the Lorentz transformation in this
  3308. general sense from two kinds of transformations, viz. from Lorentz
  3309. transformations in the special sense and from purely spatial
  3310. transformations. which corresponds to the replacement of the
  3311. rectangular co-ordinate system by a new system with its axes pointing
  3312. in other directions.
  3313.  
  3314. Mathematically, we can characterise the generalised Lorentz
  3315. transformation thus :
  3316.  
  3317. It expresses x', y', x', t', in terms of linear homogeneous functions
  3318. of x, y, x, t, of such a kind that the relation
  3319.  
  3320. x'2 + y'2 + z'2 - c^2t'2 = x2 + y2 + z2 - c^2t2 (11a).
  3321.  
  3322. is satisficd identically. That is to say: If we substitute their
  3323. expressions in x, y, x, t, in place of x', y', x', t', on the
  3324. left-hand side, then the left-hand side of (11a) agrees with the
  3325. right-hand side.
  3326.  
  3327.  
  3328.  
  3329. APPENDIX II
  3330.  
  3331. MINKOWSKI'S FOUR-DIMENSIONAL SPACE ("WORLD")
  3332. (SUPPLEMENTARY TO SECTION 17)
  3333.  
  3334.  
  3335. We can characterise the Lorentz transformation still more simply if we
  3336. introduce the imaginary eq. 25 in place of t, as time-variable. If, in
  3337. accordance with this, we insert
  3338.  
  3339. x[1] = x
  3340. x[2] = y
  3341. x[3] = z
  3342. x[4] = eq. 25
  3343.  
  3344. and similarly for the accented system K1, then the condition which is
  3345. identically satisfied by the transformation can be expressed thus :
  3346.  
  3347. x[1]'2 + x[2]'2 + x[3]'2 + x[4]'2 = x[1]^2 + x[2]^2 + x[3]^2 + x[4]^2
  3348. (12).
  3349.  
  3350. That is, by the afore-mentioned choice of " coordinates," (11a) [see
  3351. the end of Appendix II] is transformed into this equation.
  3352.  
  3353. We see from (12) that the imaginary time co-ordinate x[4], enters into
  3354. the condition of transformation in exactly the same way as the space
  3355. co-ordinates x[1], x[2], x[3]. It is due to this fact that, according
  3356. to the theory of relativity, the " time "x[4], enters into natural
  3357. laws in the same form as the space co ordinates x[1], x[2], x[3].
  3358.  
  3359. A four-dimensional continuum described by the "co-ordinates" x[1],
  3360. x[2], x[3], x[4], was called "world" by Minkowski, who also termed a
  3361. point-event a " world-point." From a "happening" in three-dimensional
  3362. space, physics becomes, as it were, an " existence " in the
  3363. four-dimensional " world."
  3364.  
  3365. This four-dimensional " world " bears a close similarity to the
  3366. three-dimensional " space " of (Euclidean) analytical geometry. If we
  3367. introduce into the latter a new Cartesian co-ordinate system (x'[1],
  3368. x'[2], x'[3]) with the same origin, then x'[1], x'[2], x'[3], are
  3369. linear homogeneous functions of x[1], x[2], x[3] which identically
  3370. satisfy the equation
  3371.  
  3372. x'[1]^2 + x'[2]^2 + x'[3]^2 = x[1]^2 + x[2]^2 + x[3]^2
  3373.  
  3374. The analogy with (12) is a complete one. We can regard Minkowski's "
  3375. world " in a formal manner as a four-dimensional Euclidean space (with
  3376. an imaginary time coordinate) ; the Lorentz transformation corresponds
  3377. to a " rotation " of the co-ordinate system in the fourdimensional "
  3378. world."
  3379.  
  3380.  
  3381.  
  3382. APPENDIX III
  3383.  
  3384. THE EXPERIMENTAL CONFIRMATION OF THE GENERAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY
  3385.  
  3386.  
  3387. From a systematic theoretical point of view, we may imagine the
  3388. process of evolution of an empirical science to be a continuous
  3389. process of induction. Theories are evolved and are expressed in short
  3390. compass as statements of a large number of individual observations in
  3391. the form of empirical laws, from which the general laws can be
  3392. ascertained by comparison. Regarded in this way, the development of a
  3393. science bears some resemblance to the compilation of a classified
  3394. catalogue. It is, as it were, a purely empirical enterprise.
  3395.  
  3396. But this point of view by no means embraces the whole of the actual
  3397. process ; for it slurs over the important part played by intuition and
  3398. deductive thought in the development of an exact science. As soon as a
  3399. science has emerged from its initial stages, theoretical advances are
  3400. no longer achieved merely by a process of arrangement. Guided by
  3401. empirical data, the investigator rather develops a system of thought
  3402. which, in general, is built up logically from a small number of
  3403. fundamental assumptions, the so-called axioms. We call such a system
  3404. of thought a theory. The theory finds the justification for its
  3405. existence in the fact that it correlates a large number of single
  3406. observations, and it is just here that the " truth " of the theory
  3407. lies.
  3408.  
  3409. Corresponding to the same complex of empirical data, there may be
  3410. several theories, which differ from one another to a considerable
  3411. extent. But as regards the deductions from the theories which are
  3412. capable of being tested, the agreement between the theories may be so
  3413. complete that it becomes difficult to find any deductions in which the
  3414. two theories differ from each other. As an example, a case of general
  3415. interest is available in the province of biology, in the Darwinian
  3416. theory of the development of species by selection in the struggle for
  3417. existence, and in the theory of development which is based on the
  3418. hypothesis of the hereditary transmission of acquired characters.
  3419.  
  3420. We have another instance of far-reaching agreement between the
  3421. deductions from two theories in Newtonian mechanics on the one hand,
  3422. and the general theory of relativity on the other. This agreement goes
  3423. so far, that up to the preseat we have been able to find only a few
  3424. deductions from the general theory of relativity which are capable of
  3425. investigation, and to which the physics of pre-relativity days does
  3426. not also lead, and this despite the profound difference in the
  3427. fundamental assumptions of the two theories. In what follows, we shall
  3428. again consider these important deductions, and we shall also discuss
  3429. the empirical evidence appertaining to them which has hitherto been
  3430. obtained.
  3431.  
  3432. (a) Motion of the Perihelion of Mercury
  3433.  
  3434. According to Newtonian mechanics and Newton's law of gravitation, a
  3435. planet which is revolving round the sun would describe an ellipse
  3436. round the latter, or, more correctly, round the common centre of
  3437. gravity of the sun and the planet. In such a system, the sun, or the
  3438. common centre of gravity, lies in one of the foci of the orbital
  3439. ellipse in such a manner that, in the course of a planet-year, the
  3440. distance sun-planet grows from a minimum to a maximum, and then
  3441. decreases again to a minimum. If instead of Newton's law we insert a
  3442. somewhat different law of attraction into the calculation, we find
  3443. that, according to this new law, the motion would still take place in
  3444. such a manner that the distance sun-planet exhibits periodic
  3445. variations; but in this case the angle described by the line joining
  3446. sun and planet during such a period (from perihelion--closest
  3447. proximity to the sun--to perihelion) would differ from 360^0. The line
  3448. of the orbit would not then be a closed one but in the course of time
  3449. it would fill up an annular part of the orbital plane, viz. between
  3450. the circle of least and the circle of greatest distance of the planet
  3451. from the sun.
  3452.  
  3453. According also to the general theory of relativity, which differs of
  3454. course from the theory of Newton, a small variation from the
  3455. Newton-Kepler motion of a planet in its orbit should take place, and
  3456. in such away, that the angle described by the radius sun-planet
  3457. between one perhelion and the next should exceed that corresponding to
  3458. one complete revolution by an amount given by
  3459.  
  3460. eq. 41: file eq41.gif
  3461.  
  3462. (N.B. -- One complete revolution corresponds to the angle 2p in the
  3463. absolute angular measure customary in physics, and the above
  3464. expression giver the amount by which the radius sun-planet exceeds
  3465. this angle during the interval between one perihelion and the next.)
  3466. In this expression a represents the major semi-axis of the ellipse, e
  3467. its eccentricity, c the velocity of light, and T the period of
  3468. revolution of the planet. Our result may also be stated as follows :
  3469. According to the general theory of relativity, the major axis of the
  3470. ellipse rotates round the sun in the same sense as the orbital motion
  3471. of the planet. Theory requires that this rotation should amount to 43
  3472. seconds of arc per century for the planet Mercury, but for the other
  3473. Planets of our solar system its magnitude should be so small that it
  3474. would necessarily escape detection. *
  3475.  
  3476. In point of fact, astronomers have found that the theory of Newton
  3477. does not suffice to calculate the observed motion of Mercury with an
  3478. exactness corresponding to that of the delicacy of observation
  3479. attainable at the present time. After taking account of all the
  3480. disturbing influences exerted on Mercury by the remaining planets, it
  3481. was found (Leverrier: 1859; and Newcomb: 1895) that an unexplained
  3482. perihelial movement of the orbit of Mercury remained over, the amount
  3483. of which does not differ sensibly from the above mentioned +43 seconds
  3484. of arc per century. The uncertainty of the empirical result amounts to
  3485. a few seconds only.
  3486.  
  3487. (b) Deflection of Light by a Gravitational Field
  3488.  
  3489. In Section 22 it has been already mentioned that according to the
  3490. general theory of relativity, a ray of light will experience a
  3491. curvature of its path when passing through a gravitational field, this
  3492. curvature being similar to that experienced by the path of a body
  3493. which is projected through a gravitational field. As a result of this
  3494. theory, we should expect that a ray of light which is passing close to
  3495. a heavenly body would be deviated towards the latter. For a ray of
  3496. light which passes the sun at a distance of D sun-radii from its
  3497. centre, the angle of deflection (a) should amount to
  3498.  
  3499. eq. 42: file eq42.gif
  3500.  
  3501. It may be added that, according to the theory, half of Figure 05 this
  3502. deflection is produced by the Newtonian field of attraction of the
  3503. sun, and the other half by the geometrical modification (" curvature
  3504. ") of space caused by the sun.
  3505.  
  3506. This result admits of an experimental test by means of the
  3507. photographic registration of stars during a total eclipse of the sun.
  3508. The only reason why we must wait for a total eclipse is because at
  3509. every other time the atmosphere is so strongly illuminated by the
  3510. light from the sun that the stars situated near the sun's disc are
  3511. invisible. The predicted effect can be seen clearly from the
  3512. accompanying diagram. If the sun (S) were not present, a star which is
  3513. practically infinitely distant would be seen in the direction D[1], as
  3514. observed front the earth. But as a consequence of the deflection of
  3515. light from the star by the sun, the star will be seen in the direction
  3516. D[2], i.e. at a somewhat greater distance from the centre of the sun
  3517. than corresponds to its real position.
  3518.  
  3519. In practice, the question is tested in the following way. The stars in
  3520. the neighbourhood of the sun are photographed during a solar eclipse.
  3521. In addition, a second photograph of the same stars is taken when the
  3522. sun is situated at another position in the sky, i.e. a few months
  3523. earlier or later. As compared whh the standard photograph, the
  3524. positions of the stars on the eclipse-photograph ought to appear
  3525. displaced radially outwards (away from the centre of the sun) by an
  3526. amount corresponding to the angle a.
  3527.  
  3528. We are indebted to the [British] Royal Society and to the Royal
  3529. Astronomical Society for the investigation of this important
  3530. deduction. Undaunted by the [first world] war and by difficulties of
  3531. both a material and a psychological nature aroused by the war, these
  3532. societies equipped two expeditions -- to Sobral (Brazil), and to the
  3533. island of Principe (West Africa) -- and sent several of Britain's most
  3534. celebrated astronomers (Eddington, Cottingham, Crommelin, Davidson),
  3535. in order to obtain photographs of the solar eclipse of 29th May, 1919.
  3536. The relative discrepancies to be expected between the stellar
  3537. photographs obtained during the eclipse and the comparison photographs
  3538. amounted to a few hundredths of a millimetre only. Thus great accuracy
  3539. was necessary in making the adjustments required for the taking of the
  3540. photographs, and in their subsequent measurement.
  3541.  
  3542. The results of the measurements confirmed the theory in a thoroughly
  3543. satisfactory manner. The rectangular components of the observed and of
  3544. the calculated deviations of the stars (in seconds of arc) are set
  3545. forth in the following table of results :
  3546.  
  3547. Table 01: file table01.gif
  3548.  
  3549. (c) Displacement of Spectral Lines Towards the Red
  3550.  
  3551. In Section 23 it has been shown that in a system K1 which is in
  3552. rotation with regard to a Galileian system K, clocks of identical
  3553. construction, and which are considered at rest with respect to the
  3554. rotating reference-body, go at rates which are dependent on the
  3555. positions of the clocks. We shall now examine this dependence
  3556. quantitatively. A clock, which is situated at a distance r from the
  3557. centre of the disc, has a velocity relative to K which is given by
  3558.  
  3559. V = wr
  3560.  
  3561. where w represents the angular velocity of rotation of the disc K1
  3562. with respect to K. If v[0], represents the number of ticks of the
  3563. clock per unit time (" rate " of the clock) relative to K when the
  3564. clock is at rest, then the " rate " of the clock (v) when it is moving
  3565. relative to K with a velocity V, but at rest with respect to the disc,
  3566. will, in accordance with Section 12, be given by
  3567.  
  3568. eq. 43: file eq43.gif
  3569.  
  3570. or with sufficient accuracy by
  3571.  
  3572. eq. 44: file eq44.gif
  3573.  
  3574. This expression may also be stated in the following form:
  3575.  
  3576. eq. 45: file eq45.gif
  3577.  
  3578. If we represent the difference of potential of the centrifugal force
  3579. between the position of the clock and the centre of the disc by f,
  3580. i.e. the work, considered negatively, which must be performed on the
  3581. unit of mass against the centrifugal force in order to transport it
  3582. from the position of the clock on the rotating disc to the centre of
  3583. the disc, then we have
  3584.  
  3585. eq. 46: file eq46.gif
  3586.  
  3587. From this it follows that
  3588.  
  3589. eq. 47: file eq47.gif
  3590.  
  3591. In the first place, we see from this expression that two clocks of
  3592. identical construction will go at different rates when situated at
  3593. different distances from the centre of the disc. This result is aiso
  3594. valid from the standpoint of an observer who is rotating with the
  3595. disc.
  3596.  
  3597. Now, as judged from the disc, the latter is in a gravititional field
  3598. of potential f, hence the result we have obtained will hold quite
  3599. generally for gravitational fields. Furthermore, we can regard an atom
  3600. which is emitting spectral lines as a clock, so that the following
  3601. statement will hold:
  3602.  
  3603. An atom absorbs or emits light of a frequency which is dependent on
  3604. the potential of the gravitational field in which it is situated.
  3605.  
  3606. The frequency of an atom situated on the surface of a heavenly body
  3607. will be somewhat less than the frequency of an atom of the same
  3608. element which is situated in free space (or on the surface of a
  3609. smaller celestial body).
  3610.  
  3611. Now f = - K (M/r), where K is Newton's constant of gravitation, and M
  3612. is the mass of the heavenly body. Thus a displacement towards the red
  3613. ought to take place for spectral lines produced at the surface of
  3614. stars as compared with the spectral lines of the same element produced
  3615. at the surface of the earth, the amount of this displacement being
  3616.  
  3617. eq. 48: file eq48.gif
  3618.  
  3619. For the sun, the displacement towards the red predicted by theory
  3620. amounts to about two millionths of the wave-length. A trustworthy
  3621. calculation is not possible in the case of the stars, because in
  3622. general neither the mass M nor the radius r are known.
  3623.  
  3624. It is an open question whether or not this effect exists, and at the
  3625. present time (1920) astronomers are working with great zeal towards
  3626. the solution. Owing to the smallness of the effect in the case of the
  3627. sun, it is difficult to form an opinion as to its existence. Whereas
  3628. Grebe and Bachem (Bonn), as a result of their own measurements and
  3629. those of Evershed and Schwarzschild on the cyanogen bands, have placed
  3630. the existence of the effect almost beyond doubt, while other
  3631. investigators, particularly St. John, have been led to the opposite
  3632. opinion in consequence of their measurements.
  3633.  
  3634. Mean displacements of lines towards the less refrangible end of the
  3635. spectrum are certainly revealed by statistical investigations of the
  3636. fixed stars ; but up to the present the examination of the available
  3637. data does not allow of any definite decision being arrived at, as to
  3638. whether or not these displacements are to be referred in reality to
  3639. the effect of gravitation. The results of observation have been
  3640. collected together, and discussed in detail from the standpoint of the
  3641. question which has been engaging our attention here, in a paper by E.
  3642. Freundlich entitled "Zur Prüfung der allgemeinen
  3643. Relativit&umlaut;ts-Theorie" (Die Naturwissenschaften, 1919, No. 35,
  3644. p. 520: Julius Springer, Berlin).
  3645.  
  3646. At all events, a definite decision will be reached during the next few
  3647. years. If the displacement of spectral lines towards the red by the
  3648. gravitational potential does not exist, then the general theory of
  3649. relativity will be untenable. On the other hand, if the cause of the
  3650. displacement of spectral lines be definitely traced to the
  3651. gravitational potential, then the study of this displacement will
  3652. furnish us with important information as to the mass of the heavenly
  3653. bodies. [5][A]
  3654.  
  3655.  
  3656. Notes
  3657.  
  3658. *) Especially since the next planet Venus has an orbit that is
  3659. almost an exact circle, which makes it more difficult to locate the
  3660. perihelion with precision.
  3661.  
  3662. The displacentent of spectral lines towards the red end of the
  3663. spectrum was definitely established by Adams in 1924, by observations
  3664. on the dense companion of Sirius, for which the effect is about thirty
  3665. times greater than for the Sun. R.W.L. -- translator
  3666.  
  3667.  
  3668.  
  3669. APPENDIX IV
  3670.  
  3671. THE STRUCTURE OF SPACE ACCORDING TO THE GENERAL THEORY OF RELATIVITY
  3672. (SUPPLEMENTARY TO SECTION 32)
  3673.  
  3674.  
  3675. Since the publication of the first edition of this little book, our
  3676. knowledge about the structure of space in the large (" cosmological
  3677. problem ") has had an important development, which ought to be
  3678. mentioned even in a popular presentation of the subject.
  3679.  
  3680. My original considerations on the subject were based on two
  3681. hypotheses:
  3682.  
  3683. (1) There exists an average density of matter in the whole of space
  3684. which is everywhere the same and different from zero.
  3685.  
  3686. (2) The magnitude (" radius ") of space is independent of time.
  3687.  
  3688. Both these hypotheses proved to be consistent, according to the
  3689. general theory of relativity, but only after a hypothetical term was
  3690. added to the field equations, a term which was not required by the
  3691. theory as such nor did it seem natural from a theoretical point of
  3692. view (" cosmological term of the field equations ").
  3693.  
  3694. Hypothesis (2) appeared unavoidable to me at the time, since I thought
  3695. that one would get into bottomless speculations if one departed from
  3696. it.
  3697.  
  3698. However, already in the 'twenties, the Russian mathematician Friedman
  3699. showed that a different hypothesis was natural from a purely
  3700. theoretical point of view. He realized that it was possible to
  3701. preserve hypothesis (1) without introducing the less natural
  3702. cosmological term into the field equations of gravitation, if one was
  3703. ready to drop hypothesis (2). Namely, the original field equations
  3704. admit a solution in which the " world radius " depends on time
  3705. (expanding space). In that sense one can say, according to Friedman,
  3706. that the theory demands an expansion of space.
  3707.  
  3708. A few years later Hubble showed, by a special investigation of the
  3709. extra-galactic nebulae (" milky ways "), that the spectral lines
  3710. emitted showed a red shift which increased regularly with the distance
  3711. of the nebulae. This can be interpreted in regard to our present
  3712. knowledge only in the sense of Doppler's principle, as an expansive
  3713. motion of the system of stars in the large -- as required, according
  3714. to Friedman, by the field equations of gravitation. Hubble's discovery
  3715. can, therefore, be considered to some extent as a confirmation of the
  3716. theory.
  3717.  
  3718. There does arise, however, a strange difficulty. The interpretation of
  3719. the galactic line-shift discovered by Hubble as an expansion (which
  3720. can hardly be doubted from a theoretical point of view), leads to an
  3721. origin of this expansion which lies " only " about 10^9 years ago,
  3722. while physical astronomy makes it appear likely that the development
  3723. of individual stars and systems of stars takes considerably longer. It
  3724. is in no way known how this incongruity is to be overcome.
  3725.  
  3726. I further want to rernark that the theory of expanding space, together
  3727. with the empirical data of astronomy, permit no decision to be reached
  3728. about the finite or infinite character of (three-dimensional) space,
  3729. while the original " static " hypothesis of space yielded the closure
  3730. (finiteness) of space.
  3731.  
  3732.  
  3733. K = co-ordinate system
  3734. x, y = two-dimensional co-ordinates
  3735. x, y, z = three-dimensional co-ordinates
  3736. x, y, z, t = four-dimensional co-ordinates
  3737.  
  3738. t = time
  3739. I = distance
  3740. v = velocity
  3741.  
  3742. F = force
  3743. G = gravitational field
  3744.  
  3745.  
  3746.  
  3747.  
  3748.  
  3749. *** END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK, RELATIVITY ***
  3750.  
  3751. This file should be named relat10.zip and contains numerous
  3752. image files for equations.
  3753.  
  3754. Corrected EDITIONS of our eBooks get a new NUMBER, relat11.txt
  3755. VERSIONS based on separate sources get new LETTER, relat10a.txt
  3756.  
  3757. Project Gutenberg eBooks are often created from several printed
  3758. editions, all of which are confirmed as Public Domain in the US
  3759. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we usually do not
  3760. keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper edition.
  3761.  
  3762. We are now trying to release all our eBooks one year in advance
  3763. of the official release dates, leaving time for better editing.
  3764. Please be encouraged to tell us about any error or corrections,
  3765. even years after the official publication date.
  3766.  
  3767. Please note neither this listing nor its contents are final til
  3768. midnight of the last day of the month of any such announcement.
  3769. The official release date of all Project Gutenberg eBooks is at
  3770. Midnight, Central Time, of the last day of the stated month. A
  3771. preliminary version may often be posted for suggestion, comment
  3772. and editing by those who wish to do so.
  3773.  
  3774. Most people start at our Web sites at:
  3775. http://gutenberg.net or
  3776. http://promo.net/pg
  3777.  
  3778. These Web sites include award-winning information about Project
  3779. Gutenberg, including how to donate, how to help produce our new
  3780. eBooks, and how to subscribe to our email newsletter (free!).
  3781.  
  3782.  
  3783. Those of you who want to download any eBook before announcement
  3784. can get to them as follows, and just download by date. This is
  3785. also a good way to get them instantly upon announcement, as the
  3786. indexes our cataloguers produce obviously take a while after an
  3787. announcement goes out in the Project Gutenberg Newsletter.
  3788.  
  3789. http://www.ibiblio.org/gutenberg/etext03 or
  3790. ftp://ftp.ibiblio.org/pub/docs/books/gutenberg/etext03
  3791.  
  3792. Or /etext02, 01, 00, 99, 98, 97, 96, 95, 94, 93, 92, 92, 91 or 90
  3793.  
  3794. Just search by the first five letters of the filename you want,
  3795. as it appears in our Newsletters.
  3796.  
  3797.  
  3798. Information about Project Gutenberg (one page)
  3799.  
  3800. We produce about two million dollars for each hour we work. The
  3801. time it takes us, a rather conservative estimate, is fifty hours
  3802. to get any eBook selected, entered, proofread, edited, copyright
  3803. searched and analyzed, the copyright letters written, etc. Our
  3804. projected audience is one hundred million readers. If the value
  3805. per text is nominally estimated at one dollar then we produce $2
  3806. million dollars per hour in 2002 as we release over 100 new text
  3807. files per month: 1240 more eBooks in 2001 for a total of 4000+
  3808. We are already on our way to trying for 2000 more eBooks in 2002
  3809. If they reach just 1-2% of the world's population then the total
  3810. will reach over half a trillion eBooks given away by year's end.
  3811.  
  3812. The Goal of Project Gutenberg is to Give Away 1 Trillion eBooks!
  3813. This is ten thousand titles each to one hundred million readers,
  3814. which is only about 4% of the present number of computer users.
  3815.  
  3816. Here is the briefest record of our progress (* means estimated):
  3817.  
  3818. eBooks Year Month
  3819.  
  3820. 1 1971 July
  3821. 10 1991 January
  3822. 100 1994 January
  3823. 1000 1997 August
  3824. 1500 1998 October
  3825. 2000 1999 December
  3826. 2500 2000 December
  3827. 3000 2001 November
  3828. 4000 2001 October/November
  3829. 6000 2002 December*
  3830. 9000 2003 November*
  3831. 10000 2004 January*
  3832.  
  3833.  
  3834. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation has been created
  3835. to secure a future for Project Gutenberg into the next millennium.
  3836.  
  3837. We need your donations more than ever!
  3838.  
  3839. As of February, 2002, contributions are being solicited from people
  3840. and organizations in: Alabama, Alaska, Arkansas, Connecticut,
  3841. Delaware, District of Columbia, Florida, Georgia, Hawaii, Illinois,
  3842. Indiana, Iowa, Kansas, Kentucky, Louisiana, Maine, Massachusetts,
  3843. Michigan, Mississippi, Missouri, Montana, Nebraska, Nevada, New
  3844. Hampshire, New Jersey, New Mexico, New York, North Carolina, Ohio,
  3845. Oklahoma, Oregon, Pennsylvania, Rhode Island, South Carolina, South
  3846. Dakota, Tennessee, Texas, Utah, Vermont, Virginia, Washington, West
  3847. Virginia, Wisconsin, and Wyoming.
  3848.  
  3849. We have filed in all 50 states now, but these are the only ones
  3850. that have responded.
  3851.  
  3852. As the requirements for other states are met, additions to this list
  3853. will be made and fund raising will begin in the additional states.
  3854. Please feel free to ask to check the status of your state.
  3855.  
  3856. In answer to various questions we have received on this:
  3857.  
  3858. We are constantly working on finishing the paperwork to legally
  3859. request donations in all 50 states. If your state is not listed and
  3860. you would like to know if we have added it since the list you have,
  3861. just ask.
  3862.  
  3863. While we cannot solicit donations from people in states where we are
  3864. not yet registered, we know of no prohibition against accepting
  3865. donations from donors in these states who approach us with an offer to
  3866. donate.
  3867.  
  3868. International donations are accepted, but we don't know ANYTHING about
  3869. how to make them tax-deductible, or even if they CAN be made
  3870. deductible, and don't have the staff to handle it even if there are
  3871. ways.
  3872.  
  3873. Donations by check or money order may be sent to:
  3874.  
  3875. Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
  3876. PMB 113
  3877. 1739 University Ave.
  3878. Oxford, MS 38655-4109
  3879.  
  3880. Contact us if you want to arrange for a wire transfer or payment
  3881. method other than by check or money order.
  3882.  
  3883. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation has been approved by
  3884. the US Internal Revenue Service as a 501(c)(3) organization with EIN
  3885. [Employee Identification Number] 64-622154. Donations are
  3886. tax-deductible to the maximum extent permitted by law. As fund-raising
  3887. requirements for other states are met, additions to this list will be
  3888. made and fund-raising will begin in the additional states.
  3889.  
  3890. We need your donations more than ever!
  3891.  
  3892. You can get up to date donation information online at:
  3893.  
  3894. http://www.gutenberg.net/donation.html
  3895.  
  3896.  
  3897. ***
  3898.  
  3899. If you can't reach Project Gutenberg,
  3900. you can always email directly to:
  3901.  
  3902. Michael S. Hart <hart@pobox.com>
  3903.  
  3904. Prof. Hart will answer or forward your message.
  3905.  
  3906. We would prefer to send you information by email.
  3907.  
  3908.  
  3909. **The Legal Small Print**
  3910.  
  3911.  
  3912. (Three Pages)
  3913.  
  3914. ***START**THE SMALL PRINT!**FOR PUBLIC DOMAIN EBOOKS**START***
  3915. Why is this "Small Print!" statement here? You know: lawyers.
  3916. They tell us you might sue us if there is something wrong with
  3917. your copy of this eBook, even if you got it for free from
  3918. someone other than us, and even if what's wrong is not our
  3919. fault. So, among other things, this "Small Print!" statement
  3920. disclaims most of our liability to you. It also tells you how
  3921. you may distribute copies of this eBook if you want to.
  3922.  
  3923. *BEFORE!* YOU USE OR READ THIS EBOOK
  3924. By using or reading any part of this PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm
  3925. eBook, you indicate that you understand, agree to and accept
  3926. this "Small Print!" statement. If you do not, you can receive
  3927. a refund of the money (if any) you paid for this eBook by
  3928. sending a request within 30 days of receiving it to the person
  3929. you got it from. If you received this eBook on a physical
  3930. medium (such as a disk), you must return it with your request.
  3931.  
  3932. ABOUT PROJECT GUTENBERG-TM EBOOKS
  3933. This PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm eBook, like most PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm eBooks,
  3934. is a "public domain" work distributed by Professor Michael S. Hart
  3935. through the Project Gutenberg Association (the "Project").
  3936. Among other things, this means that no one owns a United States copyright
  3937. on or for this work, so the Project (and you!) can copy and
  3938. distribute it in the United States without permission and
  3939. without paying copyright royalties. Special rules, set forth
  3940. below, apply if you wish to copy and distribute this eBook
  3941. under the "PROJECT GUTENBERG" trademark.
  3942.  
  3943. Please do not use the "PROJECT GUTENBERG" trademark to market
  3944. any commercial products without permission.
  3945.  
  3946. To create these eBooks, the Project expends considerable
  3947. efforts to identify, transcribe and proofread public domain
  3948. works. Despite these efforts, the Project's eBooks and any
  3949. medium they may be on may contain "Defects". Among other
  3950. things, Defects may take the form of incomplete, inaccurate or
  3951. corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other
  3952. intellectual property infringement, a defective or damaged
  3953. disk or other eBook medium, a computer virus, or computer
  3954. codes that damage or cannot be read by your equipment.
  3955.  
  3956. LIMITED WARRANTY; DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES
  3957. But for the "Right of Replacement or Refund" described below,
  3958. [1] Michael Hart and the Foundation (and any other party you may
  3959. receive this eBook from as a PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm eBook) disclaims
  3960. all liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including
  3961. legal fees, and [2] YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE OR
  3962. UNDER STRICT LIABILITY, OR FOR BREACH OF WARRANTY OR CONTRACT,
  3963. INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE
  3964. OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES, EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE
  3965. POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGES.
  3966.  
  3967. If you discover a Defect in this eBook within 90 days of
  3968. receiving it, you can receive a refund of the money (if any)
  3969. you paid for it by sending an explanatory note within that
  3970. time to the person you received it from. If you received it
  3971. on a physical medium, you must return it with your note, and
  3972. such person may choose to alternatively give you a replacement
  3973. copy. If you received it electronically, such person may
  3974. choose to alternatively give you a second opportunity to
  3975. receive it electronically.
  3976.  
  3977. THIS EBOOK IS OTHERWISE PROVIDED TO YOU "AS-IS". NO OTHER
  3978. WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, ARE MADE TO YOU AS
  3979. TO THE EBOOK OR ANY MEDIUM IT MAY BE ON, INCLUDING BUT NOT
  3980. LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR A
  3981. PARTICULAR PURPOSE.
  3982.  
  3983. Some states do not allow disclaimers of implied warranties or
  3984. the exclusion or limitation of consequential damages, so the
  3985. above disclaimers and exclusions may not apply to you, and you
  3986. may have other legal rights.
  3987.  
  3988. INDEMNITY
  3989. You will indemnify and hold Michael Hart, the Foundation,
  3990. and its trustees and agents, and any volunteers associated
  3991. with the production and distribution of Project Gutenberg-tm
  3992. texts harmless, from all liability, cost and expense, including
  3993. legal fees, that arise directly or indirectly from any of the
  3994. following that you do or cause: [1] distribution of this eBook,
  3995. [2] alteration, modification, or addition to the eBook,
  3996. or [3] any Defect.
  3997.  
  3998. DISTRIBUTION UNDER "PROJECT GUTENBERG-tm"
  3999. You may distribute copies of this eBook electronically, or by
  4000. disk, book or any other medium if you either delete this
  4001. "Small Print!" and all other references to Project Gutenberg,
  4002. or:
  4003.  
  4004. [1] Only give exact copies of it. Among other things, this
  4005. requires that you do not remove, alter or modify the
  4006. eBook or this "small print!" statement. You may however,
  4007. if you wish, distribute this eBook in machine readable
  4008. binary, compressed, mark-up, or proprietary form,
  4009. including any form resulting from conversion by word
  4010. processing or hypertext software, but only so long as
  4011. *EITHER*:
  4012.  
  4013. [*] The eBook, when displayed, is clearly readable, and
  4014. does *not* contain characters other than those
  4015. intended by the author of the work, although tilde
  4016. (~), asterisk (*) and underline (_) characters may
  4017. be used to convey punctuation intended by the
  4018. author, and additional characters may be used to
  4019. indicate hypertext links; OR
  4020.  
  4021. [*] The eBook may be readily converted by the reader at
  4022. no expense into plain ASCII, EBCDIC or equivalent
  4023. form by the program that displays the eBook (as is
  4024. the case, for instance, with most word processors);
  4025. OR
  4026.  
  4027. [*] You provide, or agree to also provide on request at
  4028. no additional cost, fee or expense, a copy of the
  4029. eBook in its original plain ASCII form (or in EBCDIC
  4030. or other equivalent proprietary form).
  4031.  
  4032. [2] Honor the eBook refund and replacement provisions of this
  4033. "Small Print!" statement.
  4034.  
  4035. [3] Pay a trademark license fee to the Foundation of 20% of the
  4036. gross profits you derive calculated using the method you
  4037. already use to calculate your applicable taxes. If you
  4038. don't derive profits, no royalty is due. Royalties are
  4039. payable to "Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation"
  4040. the 60 days following each date you prepare (or were
  4041. legally required to prepare) your annual (or equivalent
  4042. periodic) tax return. Please contact us beforehand to
  4043. let us know your plans and to work out the details.
  4044.  
  4045. WHAT IF YOU *WANT* TO SEND MONEY EVEN IF YOU DON'T HAVE TO?
  4046. Project Gutenberg is dedicated to increasing the number of
  4047. public domain and licensed works that can be freely distributed
  4048. in machine readable form.
  4049.  
  4050. The Project gratefully accepts contributions of money, time,
  4051. public domain materials, or royalty free copyright licenses.
  4052. Money should be paid to the:
  4053. "Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation."
  4054.  
  4055. If you are interested in contributing scanning equipment or
  4056. software or other items, please contact Michael Hart at:
  4057. hart@pobox.com
  4058.  
  4059. [Portions of this eBook's header and trailer may be reprinted only
  4060. when distributed free of all fees. Copyright (C) 2001, 2002 by
  4061. Michael S. Hart. Project Gutenberg is a TradeMark and may not be
  4062. used in any sales of Project Gutenberg eBooks or other materials be
  4063. they hardware or software or any other related product without
  4064. express permission.]
  4065.  
  4066. *END THE SMALL PRINT! FOR PUBLIC DOMAIN EBOOKS*Ver.02/11/02*END*
Advertisement
Add Comment
Please, Sign In to add comment
Advertisement