Advertisement
Guest User

Untitled

a guest
Jan 30th, 2018
383
0
Never
Not a member of Pastebin yet? Sign Up, it unlocks many cool features!
text 71.36 KB | None | 0 0
  1.  
  2.  
  3. Forwarded message:
  4.  
  5. > From: Elliot Temple <curi@curi.us>
  6. > To: FI <fallible-ideas@yahoogroups.com>, FIGG
  7. > <fallible-ideas@googlegroups.com>
  8. > Subject: [FI] Popper on Kant
  9. > Date: Mon, 12 Jun 2017 11:40:01 -0700
  10. >
  11. > Let's reread some Popper on Kant! Popper's positive comments on Kant are one
  12. > of the reasons many Objectivists refuse to learn what Popper's views are.
  13. >
  14. > C&R, ch 7, Kant’s Critique and Cosmology:
  15. >
  16. > Popper calls Kant:
  17. >
  18. >> a teacher of the Rights of Man, of equality before the law, of world
  19. >> citizenship, of peace on earth, and, perhaps most important, of emancipation
  20. >> through knowledge.
  21. >
  22. > Those sound good.
  23. >
  24. >> Kant believed in the Enlightenment. He was its last great defender. I realize
  25. >> that this is not the usual view. While I see Kant as the defender of the
  26. >> Enlightenment, he is more often taken as the founder of the school which
  27. >> destroyed it—of the Romantic School of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel. I
  28. >> contend that these two interpretations are incompatible.
  29. >
  30. > That sounds interesting.
  31. >
  32. > Note: Popper's sometimes overly nice to other thinkers, so be careful with his
  33. > praise. He goes out of his way to acknowledge anything he thinks they got
  34. > right. Except Hegel, who Popper is harsh to in OSE. Popper may want to
  35. > separate Kant from Hegel because he likes Kant and dislikes Hegel. Or,
  36. > alternatively, Popper may like one and not the other because he saw major ways
  37. > they are separate.
  38. >
  39. > Example of Popper giving too much credit:
  40. >
  41. > _The Philosophy of Karl Popper_, vol 2, edited by Schilpp, part 3, ch 3,
  42. > section 13, page 1014:
  43. >
  44. >> Although I am fully aware of the fact that I may be mistaken, I think that I
  45. >> have solved the problem of induction, this major philosophical problem first
  46. >> raised by David Hume. Perhaps I should be more wary; I claim only to have
  47. >> solved the other half of the philosophical problem whose more fundamental
  48. >> half was already solved by Hume, in his early *Treatise on Human Nature*,
  49. >> 1739. With a little generosity the problem may even be described as the
  50. >> *problem of human knowledge*.
  51. >
  52. >
  53. > Popper solved the problem of induction, and Hume didn't, but Popper wants to
  54. > give Hume more than half the credit! Meanwhile, Popper criticizes Hume's views
  55. > extensively here and elsewhere. Popper mostly disagrees with Hume about this.
  56. > He thinks Hume got one part right (induction doesn't logically work) and
  57. > basically went badly wrong from there. Hume was led to irrationalism because
  58. > he thought induction didn't work but was unwilling to reject it. I sympathize
  59. > with that difficult problem. Coming up with an alternative to induction is the
  60. > really hard part. Which is why I think Popper's contribution was the big
  61. > breakthrough.
  62. >
  63. >
  64. > Back to C&R:
  65. >
  66. >> In *A Public Declaration Concerning Fichte*,[6] which is too little known,
  67. >> Kant wrote: ‘May God protect us from our friends. … For there are fraudulent
  68. >> and perfidious so-called friends who are scheming for our ruin while speaking
  69. >> the language of good-will.’
  70. >
  71. > That's a good sign.
  72. >
  73. >> Kant chose [the name] ‘Transcendental Idealism’. He soon regretted this
  74. >> choice,[14] for it made people believe that he was an idealist in the sense
  75. >> of denying the reality of physical things: that he declared physical things
  76. >> to be mere ideas. Kant hastened to explain that he had only denied that space
  77. >> and time are empirical and real— empirical and real in the sense in which
  78. >> physical things and events are empirical and real. But in vain did he
  79. >> protest. His difficult style sealed his fate: he was to be revered as the
  80. >> father of German Idealism. I suggest that it is time to put this right. Kant
  81. >> always insisted[15] that the physical things in space and time are real.
  82. >
  83. >
  84. > Popper thinks Kant has been misunderstood. But in a rather different way than
  85. > Rand claims.
  86. >
  87. > There's some overlap though. That difficult writing style was criticized by
  88. > Rand too.
  89. >
  90. > I think that's an important matter. Did Kant do it on purpose? Was he bad at
  91. > writing? Did everyone write like that, given the date and country?
  92. >
  93. > Today some people write badly on purpose. They try to be impressive. They try
  94. > to imitate old thinkers like Kant or Locke. And sometimes they use dense
  95. > writing because they have little to say and that'd be too obvious if they
  96. > wrote clearly.
  97. >
  98. > But it's much harder to judge this issue for thinkers from the past,
  99. > especially via translation. (Though Popper didn't need a translation.)
  100. >
  101. >> For what the *Critique* criticizes is pure reason; it criticizes and attacks
  102. >> all reasoning about the world that is ‘pure’ in the sense of being untainted
  103. >> by sense experience. Kant attacked pure reason by showing that pure reasoning
  104. >> about the world must always entangle us in antinomies.
  105. >
  106. > People get confused by reductio arguments a lot. You argue that X implies Y,
  107. > and that Y is wrong. They often think you're advocating X or Y.
  108. >
  109. > I (and Rand too) agree that it's important to connect our reasoning to the
  110. > real world using sense data.
  111. >
  112. > In C&R ch 8, Popper finds pieces of his own solution to the problem of
  113. > induction in Kant. E.g.
  114. >
  115. >> Thus Kant wrote in the preface to the 2nd edition of the *Critique of Pure
  116. >> Reason*:
  117. >>
  118. >>> When Galileo let his globes run down an inclined plane with a gravity which
  119. >>> he had chosen himself; when Torricelli caused the air to sustain a weight
  120. >>> which he had calculated beforehand to be equal to that of a column of water
  121. >>> of known height; … then a light dawned upon all natural philosophers. They
  122. >>> learnt that our reason can understand only *what it creates according to its
  123. >>> own design: that we must compel Nature to answer our questions*, rather than
  124. >>> cling to Nature’s apron strings and allow her to guide us. *For purely
  125. >>> accidental observations, made without any plan having been thought out in
  126. >>> advance, cannot be connected by a … law—which is what reason is searching
  127. >>> for.*[5]
  128. >
  129. >
  130. > I can see why Popper likes this. Popper would read it as contradicting e.g.
  131. > Bacon's view that we should open our minds, empty them of designs, plans and
  132. > biases, and let observation teach us.
  133. >
  134. > Popper sees here the need to have ideas first, and then search *selectively*
  135. > for relevant observations which can help test those ideas.
  136. >
  137. > I have a hard time thinking of how a non-Popperian would interpret this Kant
  138. > passage and make much sense of it.
  139. >
  140. > For example, someone could read, "reason can only understand what it creates"
  141. > and think it's anti-realism. Does that mean only products of your own mind are
  142. > comprehensible to you, and the rest of the universe will always be a
  143. > mysterious jumble?
  144. >
  145. > And someone could read the comment on accidental observations as meaning the
  146. > law of gravity only connects different data points if you think of it in
  147. > advance, but gravity won't apply if you observe haphazardly.
  148. >
  149. > Popper goes on to say Kant made an error:
  150. >
  151. >> [Kant] was convinced that Newton’s theory was *true*.
  152. >
  153. > Popper says the error was basically unavoidable until Einstein, which I think
  154. > is overly generous. I think William Godwin, for example, was a post-Newton,
  155. > pre-Einstein fallibilist.
  156. >
  157. > Popper basically says Kant recognized induction doesn't work, and that this
  158. > clashes with Newton's claims. Popper then gives arguments on the matter and
  159. > it's unclear which aspects of them come from Kant.
  160. >
  161. > Popper attributes to Kant the view that:
  162. >
  163. >> *the world as we know it is our interpretation of the observable facts in the
  164. >> light of theories that we ourselves invent.* As Kant puts it: ‘Our intellect
  165. >> does not draw its laws from nature … but imposes them upon nature.’
  166. >
  167. > I agree with Popper's version, though it requires various elaborations to
  168. > avoid the undermining all human knowledge as arbitrary and subjective.
  169. >
  170. > Kant's version, quoted here, I read as ambiguous. I can see how it could mean
  171. > Popper's view. That sentence could also mean other things, e.g. that man's
  172. > consciousness has control over reality. And it could mean that our minds are
  173. > outside of nature and not controlled by the laws of physics.
  174. >
  175. > "Impose" is the wrong word. We're trying to understand nature, not impose our
  176. > will on it. The point is to take an active and (tentatively, fallibly)
  177. > opinionated role in understanding the world.
  178. >
  179. >> Since Kant believed that it was his task to explain the uniqueness and the
  180. >> truth of Newton’s theory, he was led to the belief that this theory followed
  181. >> inescapably and with logical necessity from the laws of our understanding.
  182. >> The modification of Kant’s solution which I propose, in accordance with the
  183. >> Einsteinian revolution, frees us from this compulsion. In this way, theories
  184. >> are seen to be the *free* creations of our own minds, the result of an almost
  185. >> poetic intuition, of an attempt to understand intuitively the laws of nature.
  186. >> But we no longer try to force our creations upon nature.
  187. >
  188. > Popper apparently does think Kant meant something about forcing our ideas on
  189. > nature, and wants to revise that part.
  190. >
  191. > Elliot Temple
  192. > www.curi.us
  193. >
  194. > --
  195. > You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups
  196. > "Fallible Ideas" group.
  197. > To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an
  198. > email to fallible-ideas+unsubscribe@googlegroups.com.
  199. > To view this discussion on the web visit
  200. > https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/fallible-ideas/B88F4FDB-4AE7-48A1-9A3D-AE7A25DC626B%40curi.us.
  201. > For more options, visit https://groups.google.com/d/optout.
  202.  
  203. Forwarded message:
  204.  
  205. > From: Elliot Temple <curi@curi.us>
  206. > To: FI <fallible-ideas@yahoogroups.com>, FIGG
  207. > <fallible-ideas@googlegroups.com>
  208. > Subject: [FI] More Kant Popper Quotes and Comments
  209. > Date: Mon, 12 Jun 2017 12:32:10 -0700
  210. >
  211. > I'm searching previous discussion of Kant. I found some Popper quotes I used
  212. > the past. Some emphasis is probably missing from these quotes. If someone
  213. > knows more (especially primary source info) or wants to discuss (positively or
  214. > negatively) any of the ideas from these quotes, please reply!
  215. >
  216. > From _Objective Knowledge_:
  217. >
  218. >> When Kant said that our intellect imposes its laws upon nature, he was
  219. >> right-except that he did not notice how often our intellect fails in the
  220. >> attempt: the regularities we try to impose are psychologically a priori, but
  221. >> there is not the slightest reason to assume that they are a priori valid, as
  222. >> Kant thought.
  223. >
  224. > That sounds to me like Kant was mistaken.
  225. >
  226. > I also broadly disagree with *anything* being a priori valid. I think that
  227. > epistemology and logic depend on the laws of physics. Under different physics,
  228. > evolution (which is how I think knowledge is created) doesn't have to work at
  229. > all. And physics controls the results of computations, including for the logic
  230. > operations AND, OR, NOT, etc.
  231. >
  232. > _Objective Knowledge_:
  233. >
  234. >> This solved for him [Kant] Hume's problem. But was it a tenable theory? How
  235. >> could the truth of the principle of causality (for example) be established a
  236. >> priori?
  237. >>
  238. >> Here Kant brought in his 'Copernican Revolution': it was the human intellect
  239. >> which invented, and imposed, its laws upon the sensual morass, thus creating
  240. >> the order of nature.
  241. >>
  242. >> This was a bold theory. But it collapsed once it was realized that Newtonian
  243. >> dynamics was not a priori valid but a marvellous hypothesis-a conjecture.
  244. >
  245. >
  246. >
  247. > From Open Society (OSE):
  248. >
  249. >> Kant, in his Critique of Pure Reason, asserted under the influence of Hume
  250. >> that pure speculation or reason, whenever it ventures into a field in which
  251. >> it cannot possibly be checked by experience, is liable to get involved in
  252. >> contradictions or 'antinomies' and to produce what he unambiguously described
  253. >> as 'mere fancies'; 'nonsense'; 'illusions'; 'a sterile dogmatism'; and 'a
  254. >> superficial pretension to the knowledge of everything'. He tried to show that
  255. >> to every metaphysical assertion or thesis, concerning for example the
  256. >> beginning of the world in time, or the existence of God, there can be
  257. >> contrasted a counter-assertion or antithesis; and both, he held, may proceed
  258. >> from the same assumptions, and can be proved with an equal degree of
  259. >> 'evidence'.
  260. >
  261. > I agree with this. One can take any idea and then manufacture infinitely many
  262. > contradictory claims which equally fit (do not contradict) the identical set
  263. > of empirical evidence.
  264. >
  265. > This is why, as Deutsch explains, we criticize most ideas with arguments (e.g.
  266. > saying why it's a bad explanation, contains contradictions, contains non
  267. > sequiturs, etc) and only use empirical tests when there's contradicting
  268. > empirical claims to adjudicate.
  269. >
  270. >> In other words, when leaving the field of experience, our speculation can
  271. >> have no scientific status, since to every argument there must be an equally
  272. >> valid counter-argument. Kant's intention was to stop once and forever the
  273. >> 'accursed fertility' of the scribblers on metaphysics. But unfortunately, the
  274. >> effect was very different. What Kant stopped was only the attempts of the
  275. >> scribblers to use rational argument; they only gave up the attempt to teach,
  276. >> but not the attempt to bewitch the public (as Schopenhauer puts it 29 ).
  277. >
  278. > Oh dear! And that effect, which Popper attributes to Kant, is one of Rand's
  279. > biggest complaints about Kant as well.
  280. >
  281. >> For this development, Kant himself undoubtedly bears a very considerable
  282. >> share of the blame; for the obscure style of his work (which he wrote in a
  283. >> great hurry, although only after long years of meditation) contributed
  284. >> considerably to a further lowering of the low standard of clarity in German
  285. >> theoretical writing 30 .
  286. >
  287. > :(
  288. >
  289. >> None of the metaphysical scribblers who came after Kant made any attempt to
  290. >> refute him 31 ; and Hegel, more particularly, even had the audacity to
  291. >> patronize Kant for 'reviving the name of Dialectics, which he restored to
  292. >> their post of honour'. He taught that Kant was quite right in pointing out
  293. >> the antinomies, but that he was wrong to worry about them. It just lies in
  294. >> the nature of reason that it must contradict itself, Hegel asserted; and it
  295. >> is not a weakness of our human faculties, but it is the very essence of all
  296. >> rationality that it must work with contradictions and antinomies; for this is
  297. >> just the way in which reason develops. Hegel asserted that Kant had analysed
  298. >> reason as if it were something static; that he forgot that mankind develops,
  299. >> and with it, our social heritage. But what we are pleased to call our own
  300. >> reason is nothing but the product of this social heritage, of the historical
  301. >> development of the social group in which we live, the nation.
  302. >
  303. > If anyone knows something good about Hegel, I'd be interested to hear it.
  304. >
  305. > I recall Bryan Magee was positive about some German philosophers in
  306. > _Confessions of a Philosopher_, particularly Kant and Schopenhauer. But he
  307. > failed to convince me. The index has a lot of entries for Hegel. I found Magee
  308. > quoting Schopenhauer on pp 361-2:
  309. >
  310. >> Fichte, Schelling and Hegel are in my opinion not philosophers, for they lack
  311. >> the first requirement of a philosopher, namely a seriousness and honesty of
  312. >> enquiry. They are merely sophists who wanted to appear to be, rather than to
  313. >> be, something. They sought not truth but their own interest and advancement
  314. >> in the world. ... they have excelled in one thing, in the art of beguiling
  315. >> the public ..."
  316. >
  317. > But Magee says he disagrees with Schopenhauer. Magee goes on to discuss three
  318. > of Schopenhauer's arguments against them. He does concede that they
  319. > deliberately wrote obscurely, as Schopenhauer and Rand charge. But did Kant do
  320. > that too? Popper above offers the explanation that Kant rushed his writing.
  321. >
  322. >
  323. > Back to quoting OSE:
  324. >
  325. >> The sociology of knowledge can be considered as a Hegelian version of Kant's
  326. >> theory of knowledge. For it continues on the lines of Kant's criticism of
  327. >> what we may term the 'passivist' theory of knowledge. I mean by this the
  328. >> theory of the empiricists down to and including Hume, a theory which may be
  329. >> described, roughly, as holding that knowledge streams into us through our
  330. >> senses, and that error is due to our interference with the sense-given
  331. >> material, or to the associations which have developed within it; the best way
  332. >> of avoiding error is to remain entirely passive and receptive. Against this
  333. >> receptacle theory of knowledge (I usually call it the 'bucket theory of the
  334. >> mind'), Kant argued that knowledge is not a collection of gifts received by
  335. >> our senses and stored in the mind as if it were a museum, but that it is very
  336. >> largely the result of our own mental activity; that we must most actively
  337. >> engage ourselves in searching, comparing, unifying, generalizing, if we wish
  338. >> to attain knowledge. We may call this theory the 'activist' theory of
  339. >> knowledge. In connection with it, Kant gave up the untenable ideal of a
  340. >> science which is free from any kind of presuppositions. (That this ideal is
  341. >> even self-contradictory will be shown in the next chapter.) He made it quite
  342. >> clear that we cannot start from nothing, and that we have to approach our
  343. >> task equipped with a system of presuppositions which we hold without having
  344. >> tested them by the empirical methods of science; such a system may be called
  345. >> a 'categorial apparatus' 3 . Kant believed that it was possible to discover
  346. >> the one true and unchanging categorial apparatus, which represents as it were
  347. >> the necessarily unchanging framework of our intellectual outfit, i.e. human
  348. >> 'reason'. This part of Kant's theory was given up by Hegel, who, as opposed
  349. >> to Kant, did not believe in the unity of mankind. [it continues by talking
  350. >> about Hegel]
  351. >>
  352. >> Both Kantians and Hegelians make the same mistake of assuming that our
  353. >> presuppositions (since they are, to start with, undoubtedly indispensable
  354. >> instruments which we need in our active 'making' of experiences) can neither
  355. >> be changed by decision nor refuted by experience; that they are above and
  356. >> beyond the scientific methods of testing theories, constituting as they do
  357. >> the basic presuppositions of all thought. But this is an exaggeration, based
  358. >> on a misunderstanding of the relations between theory and experience in
  359. >> science.
  360. >
  361. > That sounds like Kantians basically think we're born biased and can't fix it.
  362. >
  363. > I agree with Popper's view that we're born with something like some initial
  364. > ideas, expectations and biases, but that we can change them and make progress.
  365. >
  366. > Some things are very difficult to change, e.g. changing our eyes to see
  367. > infrared light. That would require some sci fi technology. But we can use
  368. > tools to help us see the world better, so it's OK and doesn't present some
  369. > kind of fundamental limit on human knowledge.
  370. >
  371. > I acknowledge the common experience that people's minds are tangled messes and
  372. > it's daunting to try to fix their biases. But I don't think we're screwed from
  373. > birth by some ideas which are too hard to change. I think people create their
  374. > own messes and could, step by step, untangle their thinking.
  375. >
  376. >
  377. > OSE:
  378. >
  379. >> A critical interpretation, however, must take the form of a rational
  380. >> reconstruction, and must be systematic; it must try to reconstruct the
  381. >> philosopher's thought as a consistent edifice. Cp. also what A. C. Ewing says
  382. >> of Kant (A Short Commentary on Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, 1938, p. 4):
  383. >> '.. we ought to start with the assumption that a great philosopher is not
  384. >> likely to be always contradicting himself, and consequently, wherever there
  385. >> are two interpretations, one of which will make Kant consistent and the other
  386. >> inconsistent, prefer the former to the latter, if reasonably possible.' This
  387. >> surely applies also to Plato, and even to interpretation in general.
  388. >
  389. > I like Popper's method.
  390. >
  391. >
  392. >
  393. >> I may remark, in this connection, that Kant's ardent liberalism is very
  394. >> little appreciated in English and American writings on political philosophy
  395. >> (in spite of Hastie's Kant's Principles of Politics). He is only too often
  396. >> claimed to be a forerunner of Hegel; but in view of the fact that he
  397. >> recognized in the romanticism of both Herder and Fichte a doctrine
  398. >> diametrically opposed to his own, this claim is grossly unjust to Kant, and
  399. >> there can be no doubt that he would have strongly resented it. It is the
  400. >> tremendous influence of Hegelianism that led to a wide acceptance of this, I
  401. >> believe, completely untenable claim.
  402. >
  403. > I'm doubtful of Kant's liberalism, on Popper's statement, because I consider
  404. > Popper to misunderstand liberalism. For example Popper said, "if there could
  405. > be such a thing as socialism combined with individual liberty, I would be a
  406. > socialist still"
  407. >
  408. >
  409. >
  410. > OSE:
  411. >
  412. >> It is astonishing to see that, thanks to a conspiracy of noise, a man like
  413. >> Fichte succeeded in perverting the teaching of his 'master', in spite of
  414. >> Kant's protests, and in Kant's lifetime. This happened only a hundred years
  415. >> ago and can easily be checked by anybody who takes the trouble to read Kant's
  416. >> and Fichte's letters, and Kant's public announcements; and it shows that my
  417. >> theory of Plato's perversion of the teaching of Socrates is by no means so
  418. >> fantastic as it may appear to Platonists. Socrates was dead then, and he had
  419. >> left no letters.
  420. >
  421. > and
  422. >
  423. >> I agree with Nietzsche that Kleist's words are moving; and I agree that
  424. >> Kleist's reading of Kant's doctrine that it is impossible to attain any
  425. >> knowledge of things in themselves is straightforward enough, even though it
  426. >> conflicts with Kant's own intentions; for Kant believed in the possibility of
  427. >> science, and of finding the truth.
  428. >
  429. > this says Kant contradicted himself. that would help explain confusion about
  430. > his views.
  431. >
  432. >
  433. >
  434. > From C&R:
  435. >
  436. >> Kant believed that Newton's dynamics was a priori valid. (See his
  437. >> Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science, published between the first and
  438. >> the second editions of the Critique of Pure Reason.)
  439. >
  440. >
  441. >> His Critique of Pure Reason is one of the most difficult books ever written.
  442. >> Kant wrote in great haste, and about a problem which, I shall try to show,
  443. >> was not only insoluble but also misconceived.
  444. >
  445. > it's conceivable that Kant himself was OK but his legacy is awful.
  446. >
  447. >
  448. >> What lesson did Kant draw from these bewildering antinomies? He concluded
  449. >> that our ideas of space and time are inapplicable to the universe as a whole.
  450. >> We can, of course, apply the ideas of space and time to ordinary physical
  451. >> things and physical events. But space and time themselves are neither things
  452. >> nor events: they cannot even be observed: they are more elusive. They are a
  453. >> kind of framework for things and events: something like a system of
  454. >> pigeon-holes, or a filing system, for observations. Space and time are not
  455. >> part of the real empirical world of things and events, but rather part of our
  456. >> mental outfit, our apparatus for grasping this world. Their proper use is as
  457. >> instruments of observation: in observing any event we locate it, as a rule,
  458. >> immediately and intuitively in an order of space and time. Thus space and
  459. >> time may be described as a frame of reference which is not based upon
  460. >> experience but intuitively used in experience, and properly applicable to
  461. >> experience. This is why we get into trouble if we misapply the ideas of space
  462. >> and time by using them in a field which transcends all possible
  463. >> experience--as we did in our two proofs about the universe as a whole. To the
  464. >> view which I have just outlined Kant chose to give the ugly and doubly
  465. >> misleading name "'Transcendental Idealism'". He soon regretted this choice,
  466. >> for it made people believe that he was an idealist in the sense of denying
  467. >> the reality of physical things: that he declared physical things to be mere
  468. >> ideas. Kant hastened to explain that he had only denied that space and time
  469. >> are empirical and real--empirical and real in the sense in which physical
  470. >> things and events are empirical and real. But in vain did he protest. His
  471. >> difficult style sealed his fate: he was to be revered as the father of German
  472. >> Idealism. I suggest that it is time to put this right. Kant always insisted
  473. >> that the physical things in space and time are real. And as to the wild and
  474. >> obscure metaphysical speculations of the German Idealists, the very title of
  475. >> Kant Critique was chosen to announce a critical attack upon all such
  476. >> speculative reasoning. For what the Critique criticizes is pure reason; it
  477. >> criticizes and attacks all reasoning about the world that is 'pure' in the
  478. >> sense of being untainted by sense experience. Kant attacked pure reason by
  479. >> showing that pure reasoning about the world must always entangle us in
  480. >> antinomies.
  481. >
  482. >
  483. >> KANT'S COPERNICAN REVOLUTION Kant's faith in his theory of space and time as
  484. >> an intuitive frame of reference was confirmed when he found in it a key to
  485. >> the solution of a second problem. This was the problem of the validity of
  486. >> Newtonian theory in whose absolute and unquestionable truth he believed, in
  487. >> common with all concontemporary physicists.
  488. >
  489. >
  490. >> It was inconceivable, he felt, that this exact mathematical theory should be
  491. >> nothing but the result of accumulated observations. But what else could be
  492. >> its basis? Kant approached this problem by first considering the status of
  493. >> geometry. Euclid's geometry is not based upon observation, he said, but upon
  494. >> our intuition of spatial relations. Newtonian science is in a similar
  495. >> position. Although confirmed by observations it is the result not of these
  496. >> observations but of our own ways of thinking, of our attempts to order our
  497. >> sense-data, to understand them, and to digest them intellectually. It is not
  498. >> these sense-data but our own intellect, the organization of the digestive
  499. >> system of our mind, which is responsible for our theories. Nature as we know
  500. >> it, with its order and with its laws, is thus largely a product of the
  501. >> assimilating and ordering activities of our mind. In Kant's own striking
  502. >> formulation of this view, 'Our intellect does not draw its laws from nature,
  503. >> but imposes its laws upon nature'. This formula sums up an idea which Kant
  504. >> himself proudly calls his 'Copernican Revolution'. As Kant puts it,
  505. >> Copernicus, finding that no progress was being made with the theory of the
  506. >> revolving heavens, broke the deadlock by turning the tables, as it were: he
  507. >> assumed that it is not the heavens which revolve while we the observers stand
  508. >> still, but that we the observers revolve while the heavens stand still. In a
  509. >> similar way, Kant says, the problem of scientific knowledge is to be
  510. >> solved--the problem how an exact science, such as Newtonian theory, is
  511. >> possible, and how it could ever have been found. We must give up the view
  512. >> that we are passive observers, waiting for nature to impress its regularity
  513. >> upon us. Instead we must adopt the view that in digesting our sense-data we
  514. >> actively impress the order and the laws of our intellect upon them. Our
  515. >> cosmos bears the imprint of our minds. By emphasizing the role played by the
  516. >> observer, the investigator, the theorist, Kant made an indelible impression
  517. >> not only upon philosophy but also upon physics and cosmology. There is a
  518. >> Kantian climate of thought without which Einstein's theories or Bohr's are
  519. >> hardly conceivable; and Eddington might be said to be more of a Kantian, in
  520. >> some respects, than Kant: himself. Even those who, like myself, cannot follow
  521. >> Kant all the way can accept his view that the experimenter must not wait till
  522. >> it pleases nature to reveal her secrets, but that he must question her. He
  523. >> must cross examine nature in the light of his doubts, his conjectures, his
  524. >> theories, his ideas, and his inspirations. Here, I believe, is a wonderful
  525. >> philosophical find. It makes it possible to look upon science, whether
  526. >> theoretical or experimental, as a human creation, and to look upon its
  527. >> history as part of the history of ideas, on a level with the history of art
  528. >> or of literature. There is a second and even more interesting meaning
  529. >> inherent in Kant's version of the Copernican Revolution, a meaning which may
  530. >> perhaps indicate an ambivalence in his attitude towards it. For Kant's
  531. >> Copernican Revolution solves a human problem to which Copernicus' own
  532. >> revolution gave rise. Copernicus deprived man of his central position in the
  533. >> physical universe. Kant's Copernican Revolution takes the sting out of this.
  534. >> He shows us not only that our location in the physical universe is
  535. >> irrelevant, but also that in a sense our universe may well be said to turn
  536. >> about us; for it is we who produce, at least in part, the order we find in
  537. >> it; it is we who create our knowledge of it. We are discoverers: and
  538. >> discovery is a creative art.
  539. >
  540. >
  541. >> Thus Kant wrote in the preface to the 2nd edition of the Critique of Pure
  542. >> Reason: 'When Galileo let his balls run down an inclined plane with a gravity
  543. >> which he had chosen himself; when Torricelli caused the air to sustain a
  544. >> weight which he had calculated beforehand to be equal to that of a column of
  545. >> water of known height; . . . then a light dawned upon all natural
  546. >> philosophers. They learnt that our reason can understand only what it creates
  547. >> according to its own design: that we must compel Nature to answer our
  548. >> questions, rather than cling to Nature's apron strings and allow her to guide
  549. >> us. For purely accidental observations, made without any plan having been
  550. >> thought out in advance, cannot be connected by a . . . law which is what
  551. >> reason is searching for.' This quotation from Kant shows how well he
  552. >> understood that we ourselves must confront nature with hypotheses and demand
  553. >> a reply to our questions; and that, lacking such hypotheses, we can only make
  554. >> haphazard observations which follow no plan and which can therefore never
  555. >> lead us to a natural law. In other words, Kant saw with perfect clarity that
  556. >> the history of science had refuted the Baconian myth that we must begin with
  557. >> observations in order to derive our theories from them. And Kant also
  558. >> realized very clearly that behind this historical fact lay a logical fact;
  559. >> that there were logical reasons why this kind of thing did not occur in the
  560. >> history of science: that it was logically impossible to derive theories from
  561. >> observations. My third point the contention that it is logically impossible
  562. >> to derive Newton's theory from observations follows immediately from Hume's
  563. >> critique of the validity of inductive inferences, as pointed out by Kant.
  564. >> [The details of the argument follows]
  565. >
  566. >
  567. >> As I have said, Kant, like almost all philosophers and epistemologists right
  568. >> into the twentieth century, was convinced that Newton's theory was true. This
  569. >> conviction was inescapable. Newton's theory had made the most astonishing and
  570. >> exact predictions, all of which had proved strikingly correct. Only ignorant
  571. >> men could doubt its truth. How little we may reproach Kant for his belief is
  572. >> best shown by the fact that even Henri Poincaré, the greatest mathematician,
  573. >> physicist and philosopher of his generation, who died shortly before the
  574. >> First World War, believed like Kant that Newton's theory was true and
  575. >> irrefutable. Poincaré was one of the few scientists who felt about Kant's
  576. >> paradox almost as strongly as Kant himself; and though he proposed a solution
  577. >> which differed somewhat from Kant's, it was only a variant of it. The
  578. >> important point, however, is that he fully shared Kant's error, as I have
  579. >> called it. It was an unavoidable error--unavoidable, that is, before
  580. >> Einstein.
  581. >
  582. >
  583. >> We must therefore make trial whether we may not have more success in the
  584. >> tasks of metaphysics, if we suppose that objects must conform to our
  585. >> knowledge. This would agree better with what is desired, namely, that it
  586. >> should be possible to have knowledge of objects a priori, determining
  587. >> something in regard to them prior to their being given.
  588. >
  589. > To actually judge Kant well would require looking at primary sources.
  590. > Preferably in German, which I can't read.
  591. >
  592. > However one can judge something like Kant's influence on the world today, and
  593. > the meaning most people have taken from him, just from secondary sources in
  594. > English.
  595. >
  596. >
  597. > Elliot Temple
  598. > Get my philosophy newsletter:
  599. > www.fallibleideas.com/newsletter
  600. >
  601. > --
  602. > You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups
  603. > "Fallible Ideas" group.
  604. > To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an
  605. > email to fallible-ideas+unsubscribe@googlegroups.com.
  606. > To view this discussion on the web visit
  607. > https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/fallible-ideas/DB595F85-089C-4955-98D1-05F8195B2801%40curi.us.
  608. > For more options, visit https://groups.google.com/d/optout.
  609.  
  610. Forwarded message:
  611.  
  612. > From: Elliot Temple <curi@curi.us>
  613. > To: FI <fallible-ideas@yahoogroups.com>, FIGG
  614. > <fallible-ideas@googlegroups.com>
  615. > Subject: [FI] Kant Quotes
  616. > Date: Mon, 12 Jun 2017 12:50:11 -0700
  617. >
  618. > http://www.gutenberg.org/files/4280/4280-h/4280-h.htm
  619. >
  620. >> The understanding was defined above only negatively, as a non-sensuous
  621. >> faculty of cognition. Now, independently of sensibility, we cannot possibly
  622. >> have any intuition; consequently, the understanding is no faculty of
  623. >> intuition. But besides intuition there is no other mode of cognition, except
  624. >> through conceptions; consequently, the cognition of every, at least of every
  625. >> human, understanding is a cognition through conceptions—not intuitive, but
  626. >> discursive. All intuitions, as sensuous, depend on affections; conceptions,
  627. >> therefore, upon functions. By the word function I understand the unity of the
  628. >> act of arranging diverse representations under one common representation.
  629. >> Conceptions, then, are based on the spontaneity of thought, as sensuous
  630. >> intuitions are on the receptivity of impressions. Now, the understanding
  631. >> cannot make any other use of these conceptions than to judge by means of
  632. >> them. As no representation, except an intuition, relates immediately to its
  633. >> object, a conception never relates immediately to an object, but only to some
  634. >> other representation thereof, be that an intuition or itself a conception. A
  635. >> judgement, therefore, is the mediate cognition of an object, consequently the
  636. >> representation of a representation of it. In every judgement there is a
  637. >> conception which applies to, and is valid for many other conceptions, and
  638. >> which among these comprehends also a given representation, this last being
  639. >> immediately connected with an object. For example, in the judgement—"All
  640. >> bodies are divisible," our conception of divisible applies to various other
  641. >> conceptions; among these, however, it is here particularly applied to the
  642. >> conception of body, and this conception of body relates to certain phenomena
  643. >> which occur to us. These objects, therefore, are mediately represented by the
  644. >> conception of divisibility. All judgements, accordingly, are functions of
  645. >> unity in our representations, inasmuch as, instead of an immediate, a higher
  646. >> representation, which comprises this and various others, is used for our
  647. >> cognition of the object, and thereby many possible cognitions are collected
  648. >> into one. But we can reduce all acts of the understanding to judgements, so
  649. >> that understanding may be represented as the faculty of judging. For it is,
  650. >> according to what has been said above, a faculty of thought. Now thought is
  651. >> cognition by means of conceptions. But conceptions, as predicates of possible
  652. >> judgements, relate to some representation of a yet undetermined object. Thus
  653. >> the conception of body indicates something—for example, metal—which can be
  654. >> cognized by means of that conception. It is therefore a conception, for the
  655. >> reason alone that other representations are contained under it, by means of
  656. >> which it can relate to objects. It is therefore the predicate to a possible
  657. >> judgement; for example: "Every metal is a body." All the functions of the
  658. >> understanding therefore can be discovered, when we can completely exhibit the
  659. >> functions of unity in judgements. And that this may be effected very easily,
  660. >> the following section will show.
  661. >
  662. > This is terribly hard to understand, and also I'm suspicious of the
  663. > translation. Consider, "besides intuition there is no other mode of cognition,
  664. > except through conceptions". What? The original text could be bad. But it
  665. > could easily be that the words "intuition" and "conceptions" are inadequate
  666. > translations. (It also presumably makes more sense if you read the whole
  667. > book.)
  668. >
  669. > I'm not motivated to try to make sense of passages like these unless someone
  670. > can tell me the value to be gained. But I've read some pro-Kant secondary
  671. > sources and wasn't convinced of the value.
  672. >
  673. > Here's one more which is relevant to the Popper quotes I posted.
  674. >
  675. >> It appears to me that the examples of mathematics and natural philosophy,
  676. >> which, as we have seen, were brought into their present condition by a sudden
  677. >> revolution, are sufficiently remarkable to fix our attention on the essential
  678. >> circumstances of the change which has proved so advantageous to them, and to
  679. >> induce us to make the experiment of imitating them, so far as the analogy
  680. >> which, as rational sciences, they bear to metaphysics may permit. It has
  681. >> hitherto been assumed that our cognition must conform to the objects; but all
  682. >> attempts to ascertain anything about these objects a priori, by means of
  683. >> conceptions, and thus to extend the range of our knowledge, have been
  684. >> rendered abortive by this assumption. Let us then make the experiment whether
  685. >> we may not be more successful in metaphysics, if we assume that the objects
  686. >> must conform to our cognition. This appears, at all events, to accord better
  687. >> with the possibility of our gaining the end we have in view, that is to say,
  688. >> of arriving at the cognition of objects a priori, of determining something
  689. >> with respect to these objects, before they are given to us. We here propose
  690. >> to do just what Copernicus did in attempting to explain the celestial
  691. >> movements. When he found that he could make no progress by assuming that all
  692. >> the heavenly bodies revolved round the spectator, he reversed the process,
  693. >> and tried the experiment of assuming that the spectator revolved, while the
  694. >> stars remained at rest. We may make the same experiment with regard to the
  695. >> intuition of objects. If the intuition must conform to the nature of the
  696. >> objects, I do not see how we can know anything of them a priori. If, on the
  697. >> other hand, the object conforms to the nature of our faculty of intuition, I
  698. >> can then easily conceive the possibility of such an a priori knowledge. Now
  699. >> as I cannot rest in the mere intuitions, but—if they are to become
  700. >> cognitions—must refer them, as representations, to something, as object, and
  701. >> must determine the latter by means of the former, here again there are two
  702. >> courses open to me. Either, first, I may assume that the conceptions, by
  703. >> which I effect this determination, conform to the object—and in this case I
  704. >> am reduced to the same perplexity as before; or secondly, I may assume that
  705. >> the objects, or, which is the same thing, that experience, in which alone as
  706. >> given objects they are cognized, conform to my conceptions—and then I am at
  707. >> no loss how to proceed. For experience itself is a mode of cognition which
  708. >> requires understanding. Before objects, are given to me, that is, a priori, I
  709. >> must presuppose in myself laws of the understanding which are expressed in
  710. >> conceptions a priori. To these conceptions, then, all the objects of
  711. >> experience must necessarily conform. Now there are objects which reason
  712. >> thinks, and that necessarily, but which cannot be given in experience, or, at
  713. >> least, cannot be given so as reason thinks them. The attempt to think these
  714. >> objects will hereafter furnish an excellent test of the new method of thought
  715. >> which we have adopted, and which is based on the principle that we only
  716. >> cognize in things a priori that which we ourselves place in them.[*]
  717. >
  718. > Note e.g., "It has hitherto been assumed that our cognition must conform to
  719. > the objects". Then Kant appears to say let's try assuming reality will match
  720. > some of our a priori ideas.
  721. >
  722. > You have to be really careful though because the book is a *criticism* of pure
  723. > reason. When you read an isolated passage you don't know if Kant actually
  724. > agrees with it or is just discussing it.
  725. >
  726. > Elliot Temple
  727. > www.curi.us
  728. >
  729. > --
  730. > You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups
  731. > "Fallible Ideas" group.
  732. > To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an
  733. > email to fallible-ideas+unsubscribe@googlegroups.com.
  734. > To view this discussion on the web visit
  735. > https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/fallible-ideas/70A07812-74F9-4318-98ED-20920F65ED94%40curi.us.
  736. > For more options, visit https://groups.google.com/d/optout.
  737.  
  738. Forwarded message:
  739.  
  740. > From: Elliot Temple <curi@curi.us>
  741. > To: FI <fallible-ideas@yahoogroups.com>, FIGG
  742. > <fallible-ideas@googlegroups.com>
  743. > Subject: [FI] Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy on Kant
  744. > Date: Mon, 12 Jun 2017 13:30:19 -0700
  745. >
  746. > Regardless of what Kant meant to say, let's look at what he means to English
  747. > speaking philosophers today. I think this should be a reasonably
  748. > representative source:
  749. >
  750. > https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant/
  751. >
  752. > by Michael Rohlf
  753. >
  754. >> The problem is that to some it seemed unclear whether progress would in fact
  755. >> ensue if reason enjoyed full sovereignty over traditional authorities; or
  756. >> whether unaided reasoning would instead lead straight to materialism,
  757. >> fatalism, atheism, skepticism (Bxxxiv), or even libertinism and
  758. >> authoritarianism (8:146). The Enlightenment commitment to the sovereignty of
  759. >> reason was tied to the expectation that it would not lead to any of these
  760. >> consequences
  761. >
  762. >
  763. > My position: reason properly understood doesn't lead to those things. But
  764. > misunderstandings of reason are common and can lead there. (That is what
  765. > happened in the French Revolution which Burke criticized.)
  766. >
  767. >> Kant's main goal is to show that a critique of reason by reason itself,
  768. >> unaided and unrestrained by traditional authorities, establishes a secure and
  769. >> consistent basis for both Newtonian science and traditional morality and
  770. >> religion. In other words, free rational inquiry adequately supports all of
  771. >> these essential human interests and shows them to be mutually consistent. So
  772. >> reason deserves the sovereignty attributed to it by the Enlightenment.
  773. >
  774. >
  775. > The page also says Kant thinks something like: metaphysics = a priori thinking
  776. > = the domain of reason.
  777. >
  778. >
  779. >> Kant's revolutionary position in the Critique is that we can have a priori
  780. >> knowledge about the general structure of the sensible world because it is not
  781. >> entirely independent of the human mind. The sensible world, or the world of
  782. >> appearances, is constructed by the human mind from a combination of sensory
  783. >> matter that we receive passively and a priori forms that are supplied by our
  784. >> cognitive faculties.
  785. >
  786. > and
  787. >
  788. >> For Kant, analogously, the phenomena of human experience depend on both the
  789. >> sensory data that we receive passively through sensibility and the way our
  790. >> mind actively processes this data according to its own a priori rules.
  791. >
  792. > and
  793. >
  794. >> we cannot have a priori knowledge about things whose existence and nature are
  795. >> entirely independent of the human mind, which Kant calls things in themselves
  796. >
  797. > and
  798. >
  799. >> That is, Kant's constructivist foundation for scientific knowledge restricts
  800. >> science to the realm of appearances and implies that a priori knowledge of
  801. >> things in themselves that transcend possible human experience — or
  802. >> transcendent metaphysics — is impossible.
  803. >
  804. > and
  805. >
  806. >> [Kant] claims that rejecting knowledge about things in themselves is
  807. >> necessary for reconciling science with traditional morality and religion
  808. >
  809. >
  810. >
  811. > This denies that science deals with the real world with things "independent of
  812. > the human mind".
  813. >
  814. > So either science can't deal with rocks, or rocks don't exist in nature as
  815. > things in themselves apart from humans.
  816. >
  817. > Does someone have a more positive reading of this?
  818. >
  819. > The only way I see to make much sense of this is to interpret it heavily along
  820. > Popperian lines. Something like this:
  821. >
  822. >> Humans don't have pure, unbiased, or a priori knowledge. We use our fallible
  823. >> sense organs and our fallible reasoning. We try to understand the real world
  824. >> from limited, imperfect information. That's OK. We can still find and correct
  825. >> errors in order to make progress in scientifically understanding objective
  826. >> reality.
  827. >
  828. >
  829. > But I don't actually read the Kant material as saying this.
  830. >
  831. > I can agree with Kant that "human beings experience only appearances, not
  832. > things in themselves". We don't have direct knowledge of reality. Our eyes,
  833. > for example, are tools, like a camera, which detect a small
  834. > evolutionarily-determined slice of the available information and which can
  835. > malfunction. (This claim deeply disturbs some Objectivists, but I don't recall
  836. > Rand herself contradicting it.)
  837. >
  838. > As to what Kant meant:
  839. >
  840. >> But scholars disagree widely on how to interpret these claims, and there is
  841. >> no such thing as the standard interpretation of Kant's transcendental
  842. >> idealism.
  843. >
  844. >
  845. > The article presents two main types of interpretation:
  846. >
  847. >> According to the two-objects interpretation, transcendental idealism is
  848. >> essentially a metaphysical thesis that distinguishes between two classes of
  849. >> objects: appearances and things in themselves.
  850. >
  851. > ok, sort of. i wouldn't call appearances "objects". the photons i see which
  852. > carry information to me about a chair are a different sort of thing than the
  853. > chair. also this is sounding similar to Plato's cave.
  854. >
  855. >> Things in themselves, on this interpretation, are absolutely real in the
  856. >> sense that they would exist and have whatever properties they have even if no
  857. >> human beings were around to perceive them. Appearances, on the other hand,
  858. >> are not absolutely real in that sense, because their existence and properties
  859. >> depend on human perceivers.
  860. >
  861. > This reading sounds neither valuable today nor particularly bad for an old
  862. > view. It's kinda confused by the gist is trying to understand the difference
  863. > between 1) a chair 2) my perception of a chair. I get that that's a hard
  864. > problem. This stuff is much easier to understand if you're familiar with
  865. > modern physics, photons, cameras, information theory, etc.
  866. >
  867. >> Moreover, whenever appearances do exist, in some sense they exist in the mind
  868. >> of human perceivers.
  869. >
  870. > This statement isn't very clear. It's trying to talk about something without
  871. > knowing all the details: that photons carry information about objects to our
  872. > eyes which is then processed by our brains which are computers. In this modern
  873. > physics view, one can understand what information exists at what locations at
  874. > what times.
  875. >
  876. >> Kant is walking a fine line in claiming on the one hand that we can have no
  877. >> knowledge about things in themselves, but on the other hand that we know that
  878. >> things in themselves exist, that they affect our senses, and that they are
  879. >> non-spatial and non-temporal.
  880. >
  881. > This kind of statement worries me about translations and context. What did
  882. > Kant actually mean by "no knowledge"? Maybe he meant no justified, true
  883. > believe. Maybe he meant no infallible knowledge.
  884. >
  885. > This passage directly asserts (according to the two-objects interpretation)
  886. > that Kant was a skeptic. No knowledge of the real world! But it doesn't leave
  887. > me confident the author is conveying Kant's meaning correctly.
  888. >
  889. >> even if that problem is surmounted, it has seemed to many that Kant's theory,
  890. >> interpreted in this way, implies a radical form of skepticism that traps each
  891. >> of us within the contents of our own mind and cuts us off from reality.
  892. >
  893. > My primary opinion of this is I don't really care. People are confused
  894. > (perhaps Kant, and certainly many of his interpreters) and a much better view
  895. > of the matter is available today.
  896. >
  897. > The article goes on to talk about the "two-aspects reading" of Kant, which I
  898. > again don't see the value in.
  899. >
  900. >
  901. > Elliot Temple
  902. > Get my philosophy newsletter:
  903. > www.fallibleideas.com/newsletter
  904. >
  905. > --
  906. > You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups
  907. > "Fallible Ideas" group.
  908. > To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an
  909. > email to fallible-ideas+unsubscribe@googlegroups.com.
  910. > To view this discussion on the web visit
  911. > https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/fallible-ideas/09D9D94B-0095-4F5F-8D80-8BE4BCE1C3D3%40curi.us.
  912. > For more options, visit https://groups.google.com/d/optout.
  913.  
  914. Forwarded message:
  915.  
  916. > From: Elliot Temple <curi@curi.us>
  917. > To: FI <fallible-ideas@yahoogroups.com>, FIGG
  918. > <fallible-ideas@googlegroups.com>
  919. > Subject: [FI] Kant and Liberalism
  920. > Date: Mon, 12 Jun 2017 14:45:14 -0700
  921. >
  922. > I want to find some information about Kant's political views, separate from
  923. > his complex, abstract views about reason. Was he liberal or anti-liberal? Did
  924. > he have a view on free trade or small government? That's a different sort of
  925. > thing than e.g. discussion of the Categorical Imperative which only relates to
  926. > human life indirectly.
  927. >
  928. >
  929. > https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-moral/
  930. >
  931. >> Kant defines virtue as “the moral strength of a *human being’s* will in
  932. >> fulfilling his duty” (MM 6:405)
  933. >
  934. > This sounds really bad. It sounds like a recipe for obedience to authorities
  935. > who say what your duty is.
  936. >
  937. > Why should it take strength and will to act morally, instead of being
  938. > pleasant? Why should you fulfill duty instead of self-interest?
  939. >
  940. > https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/liberalism/
  941. >
  942. >> According to Kantian contractualism, “society, being composed of a plurality
  943. >> of persons, each with his own aims, interests, and conceptions of the good,
  944. >> is best arranged when it is governed by principles that do not *themselves*
  945. >> presuppose any particular conception of the good…” (Sandel, 1982: 1).
  946. >
  947. >
  948. > This might mean a tolerant society where the laws don't discriminate against
  949. > people with different moral views.
  950. >
  951. > https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Political_philosophy_of_Immanuel_Kant
  952. >
  953. >> Kant's most significant contribution to political philosophy and the
  954. >> philosophy of law is the doctrine of *Rechtsstaat*. According to this
  955. >> doctrine, the power of the state is limited in order to protect citizens from
  956. >> the arbitrary exercise of authority.
  957. >
  958. >
  959. > That sounds good. But it doesn't sound like a big contribution. Wasn't that
  960. > idea already known by e.g. Locke?
  961. >
  962. >> Kant opposed "democracy" – which, in that era, meant direct democracy –
  963. >> believing that majority rule posed a threat to individual liberty.
  964. >
  965. > Guess who else criticizes democracy similarly. Ayn Rand! e.g.
  966. >
  967. > http://aynrandlexicon.com/lexicon/democracy.html
  968. >
  969. >> “Democratic” in its original meaning [refers to] unlimited majority rule . .
  970. >> . a social system in which one’s work, one’s property, one’s mind, and one’s
  971. >> life are at the mercy of any gang that may muster the vote of a majority at
  972. >> any moment for any purpose.
  973. >
  974. >
  975. > I found a discussion of whether Kant is a classical liberal at Cato Unbound.
  976. > It's new (Oct 2016) and I hadn't seen it before!
  977. >
  978. > Mark White argues in favor, and an Objectivist and Gregory Salmieri (an
  979. > Objectivist) and two others write replies. Let's take a look:
  980. >
  981. > https://www.cato-unbound.org/issues/october-2016/immanuel-kant-classical-liberalism
  982. >
  983. > Quotes are from individual pages and I mention when I switch authors.
  984. >
  985. > White says Kant favors autonomy, meaning:
  986. >
  987. >> the ability to make moral choices without undue regard or deference to either
  988. >> external authority or internal inclinations
  989. >
  990. > sounds good.
  991. >
  992. >> Kant wrote that his categorical imperative was nothing but a formalization of
  993. >> the moral intuitions of the common person on the street: treat everyone the
  994. >> same and, if you need their cooperation, convince them to work with you,
  995. >> rather than lying or forcing them to
  996. >
  997. >
  998. > sounds good.
  999. >
  1000. >> the categorical imperative generates two types of duties. *Perfect duties*,
  1001. >> also called strict duties, allow for no exceptions in one’s own interests,
  1002. >> and are normally negative in nature: do not lie, do not steal, do not kill,
  1003. >> and so forth.
  1004. >
  1005. > And there's weaker duties which are like general guidelines such as "help
  1006. > others, cultivate your talents", etc.
  1007. >
  1008. > The perfect duties concern me because there are no conflicts between morality
  1009. > and self-interest! Does Kant think lying, stealing and murdering are actually
  1010. > in one's self-interest?
  1011. >
  1012. > White makes an accusation about Rand but doesn't footnote a Rand quote. That's
  1013. > a bad sign!
  1014. >
  1015. > White denies that Kant advocated extreme altruism.
  1016. >
  1017. >> Given the negative nature of duties and the ubiquity of conflicts among them,
  1018. >> our judgment ends up being more useful than the duties themselves, which are
  1019. >> just the building blocks of moral behavior. The need for judgment to decide
  1020. >> how to implement and balance duties and obligations also has the effect of
  1021. >> highlighting the surprising degree of flexibility in Kant’s ethics, where
  1022. >> even perfect duties can be overridden by an imperfect duty if the latter has
  1023. >> a stronger ground of obligation. This flexibility belies caricatures of Kant
  1024. >> as a cold, rigid moralist, and reveal him to be a true supporter of freedom
  1025. >> within the bounds of sociality.
  1026. >
  1027. > This sounds like an unprincipled mess. If your principles conflict, some of
  1028. > them are wrong! Don't ignore the contradiction and then take different sides
  1029. > of it as it suits you!
  1030. >
  1031. > The details of those bounds on freedom concern me too.
  1032. >
  1033. > White says Kant advocated small government.
  1034. >
  1035. > On to Salmieri:
  1036. >
  1037. >> Kant coopted some of the Enlightenment’s language and used it to defend a
  1038. >> purified form of the dogmas that had long been accepted as common sense but
  1039. >> were newly under attack. In particular, by defining morality in
  1040. >> contradistinction to prudence, Kant gave a new prominence to the idea that
  1041. >> morality requires sacrifice. The “freedom” (or “autonomy”) he extols is not
  1042. >> the Enlightenment’s freedom to conceive and pursue ambitious, life-affirming
  1043. >> goals, nor is it the freedom to follow one’s whims. Rather, it is the ability
  1044. >> to obey a morality the entire content of which Kant derives from the notion
  1045. >> that there must be *something* for the sake of which one must be always ready
  1046. >> to sacrifice the whole of one’s happiness.
  1047. >
  1048. >
  1049. > Scathing! And footnoted:
  1050. >
  1051. >> See especially Ak. IV 405–407 and Ak. V 73.
  1052. >
  1053. >
  1054. > I wish people would just link public domain works, it'd be way easier to find
  1055. > the right passage. I could also Google the passage if he'd given any quote.
  1056. > I'll look for this later.
  1057. >
  1058. > Salmieri also denies White's claim that sometimes perfect duties can be
  1059. > overridden.
  1060. >
  1061. >> [Kant insisted] that motives of philanthropy give us no right to lie to
  1062. >> murderers who inquire after the locations of their intended victims.
  1063. >
  1064. >
  1065. > Awful! And Footnoted to Ak. VIII 425–430.
  1066. >
  1067. >> This Kantian conception of morality as something essentially different from
  1068. >> prudence was widely adopted by subsequent ethicists, who disagreed with Kant
  1069. >> on specific content of morality.
  1070. >
  1071. > In other words, Kant may bear substantial responsibility for a disaster: the
  1072. > current widespread anti-commonsense belief that morality and practicality are
  1073. > in massive conflict.
  1074. >
  1075. >> For Locke, rights defined the freedoms a rational and industrious person
  1076. >> needs to pursue his happiness in the world. The Kantian conception of
  1077. >> morality, which accords no value to this pursuit as such, leaves these rights
  1078. >> with no foundation. Appeals to Kantian dignity are of no help, because a
  1079. >> person has this dignity only qua being able to act dutifully, and acting
  1080. >> dutifully has little to do with charting one’s course through the world or
  1081. >> supporting oneself in it. How is one’s ability to be dutiful infringed upon
  1082. >> by, for example, a political system that redistributes money?
  1083. >
  1084. >
  1085. > If someone could refute this, I'd be interested.
  1086. >
  1087. > But part of the difficulty is that people disagree about what Kant actually
  1088. > said and meant. So it can be better to move on and talk about what's true and
  1089. > false, rather than worrying too much about Kant.
  1090. >
  1091. > Moving on to Hicks:
  1092. >
  1093. >> [Kant] did argue for a robust freedom of speech, at least for the
  1094. >> philosophical use of reason. He advocated property rights. He resisted some
  1095. >> types of commodifications of human beings. And on numerous matters in foreign
  1096. >> policy he called for more peace-oriented and humanistic policies.
  1097. >>
  1098. >> Yet he also argued against allowing the smallpox vaccination: “So that states
  1099. >> do not become overcrowded with people and thus stifled from the outset, two
  1100. >> evils are placed in them as antidotes: smallpox and war.”
  1101. >
  1102. >
  1103. > Hicks says Kant was against the freedom to sell your hair to a wigmaker, and
  1104. > thought it's no crime for an unmarried mother to kill her child because
  1105. > bastards are illegitimate.
  1106. >
  1107. >> Also, given Kant’s many negative remarks about Jews,[4] women,[5] and blacks
  1108. >> and other races,[6] it is far from clear that he believes the majority of
  1109. >> human beings are capable of agency at a level worthy of moral dignity.
  1110. >
  1111. > :(
  1112. >
  1113. >> I will argue that the anti-liberalism is much deeper in Kant’s philosophy
  1114. >> than the liberalism.
  1115. >
  1116. > ok let's see.
  1117. >
  1118. >> What some philosophers mean by *self*, *individual*, and *freedom* is the
  1119. >> opposite of what other philosophers mean.
  1120. >
  1121. >
  1122. > i agree with Hicks's methodological point about interpretation, and
  1123. > specifically that terms like these get used in widely different ways.
  1124. >
  1125. >> incorporating [Kant's] fundamental distinction between phenomenal and
  1126. >> noumenal realms is essential.
  1127. >
  1128. > ok
  1129. >
  1130. >> Kant argues that we experience only the phenomenal world with its features of
  1131. >> time, space, cause and effect. This world is bounded, finite, and
  1132. >> Isaac-Newton-physically deterministic. Yet beyond the phenomenal world is the
  1133. >> noumenal, which is perhaps the realm of God, freedom, and immortality.
  1134. >>
  1135. >> Kant also believes that if there is to be morality, it must come from a place
  1136. >> of freedom. Consequently, that freedom must be outside of the phenomenal
  1137. >> world, since the phenomenal is ruled by deterministic cause and effect in
  1138. >> space and time. In other words, since morality depends upon freedom and the
  1139. >> phenomenal realm is unfree, the origin of morality can only be noumenal.
  1140. >
  1141. > really bad if correct.
  1142. >
  1143. >> So when Kant says that human selves are moral agents, that they have a
  1144. >> capacity for dignity, and that their freedoms ought to be respected, he is
  1145. >> speaking only about *noumenal* selves. He is *not* speaking about our
  1146. >> phenomenal selves. Our phenomenal selves are not free and are consequently
  1147. >> not in the realm of morality.
  1148. >
  1149. > ewwww
  1150. >
  1151. >
  1152. > moving on to Long:
  1153. >
  1154. >> I think Kant’s political writings have strong classical liberal, even
  1155. >> libertarian strands, and that these stem in large part from his more basic
  1156. >> principles. I also think his political writings contain deeply illiberal
  1157. >> elements. In many cases, I take these to be the result of Kant’s
  1158. >> misapplication of his own principles, and would expect a more consistent
  1159. >> application of those principles to result in a still more thoroughgoingly
  1160. >> libertarian set of policies.
  1161. >
  1162. >
  1163. > and he says Kant is good on the principle of property rights. and something
  1164. > about everyone gets as much freedom as possible without coercing each other.
  1165. >
  1166. > he says overall he sides with Kant's defenders against Rand, but accepts she
  1167. > had some correct points.
  1168. >
  1169. >> But however libertarian Kant’s theory of property may be in its basic
  1170. >> outlines, it is far less so in application. And here I cannot agree with Dr.
  1171. >> White’s statement that “Kant did not support forced beneficence,” or that
  1172. >> Kant’s political theory “rules out any state welfare system.” As part of the
  1173. >> social contract (a *fictional* social contract – more on that anon), Kantian
  1174. >> citizens are understood to cede to the ruler a degree of ownership over their
  1175. >> private holdings; hence Kant explicitly defends
  1176. >>
  1177. >>> the right of the supreme commander … as supreme proprietor (lord of the
  1178. >>> land), to *tax* private owners of land, that is, to require payment of taxes
  1179. >>> on land, excise taxes and import duties, or to require the performance of
  1180. >>> services (such as providing troops for military service) …. On this supreme
  1181. >>> proprietorship also rests the right to administer the state’s economy,
  1182. >>> finances, and police.[11]
  1183. >
  1184. >
  1185. > That services clause, including conscription, is a big deal!
  1186. >
  1187. >> the taxing power also includes “the right to impose taxes on the people … to
  1188. >> support organizations providing for the poor, foundling homes, and church
  1189. >> organizations,” which sounds like a state welfare system to me. Kant even
  1190. >> stresses that such public support is to occur “not merely by voluntary
  1191. >> contributions” but “by way of coercion,” explaining that taxpayers “have
  1192. >> acquired an obligation to the commonwealth, since they owe their existence to
  1193. >> an act of submitting to its protection and care, which they need in order to
  1194. >> live.”[12]
  1195. >
  1196. > that really doesn't sound liberal to me.
  1197. >
  1198. >> Kant’s (classically) illiberal streak goes much farther than mere support for
  1199. >> state welfare. He holds that illegitimate children have “stolen into the
  1200. >> commonwealth … like contraband merchandise” and so stand outside the
  1201. >> protection of civil law;[13] he denies citizens a right of self-defense
  1202. >> against the state by declaring the ruler to be above the law and not to be
  1203. >> rebelled against;[14] he denies wage workers the right of self-defense
  1204. >> against the wealthy classes by depriving them of the vote;[15] and he is so
  1205. >> enamored of capital punishment as to insist that “if a civil society were to
  1206. >> be dissolved by the consent of all its members … the last murderer remaining
  1207. >> in prison would first have to be executed.”[16]
  1208. >
  1209. > and there's more, e.g. that husbands should dominate wives because they're
  1210. > naturally superior.
  1211. >
  1212. > i'm now curious what *good* things Long is going to say about Kant! so far
  1213. > Long is basically like: "Kant mentioned a few good principles from which I can
  1214. > derive great political views which Kant would disagree with."
  1215. >
  1216. > well i read the rest and it has more really bad things about Kant and I didn't
  1217. > find the good things very convincing.
  1218. >
  1219. >
  1220. > there's some back and forth discussion after the first 4 pieces. White follows
  1221. > up once and makes some concessions, then stops responding when further
  1222. > criticism comes in. read more if you're interested.
  1223. >
  1224. >
  1225. >
  1226. >
  1227. > in the big picture my takeaway is that Kant is bad. if someone knows a good
  1228. > thing to read to change my mind, please point me to it.
  1229. >
  1230. >
  1231. > Elliot Temple
  1232. > www.curi.us
  1233. >
  1234. > --
  1235. > You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups
  1236. > "Fallible Ideas" group.
  1237. > To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an
  1238. > email to fallible-ideas+unsubscribe@googlegroups.com.
  1239. > To view this discussion on the web visit
  1240. > https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/fallible-ideas/05B3D3E8-43DE-4555-89C1-1AA973E4F6A4%40curi.us.
  1241. > For more options, visit https://groups.google.com/d/optout.
  1242.  
  1243. Forwarded message:
  1244.  
  1245. > From: Elliot Temple <curi@curi.us>
  1246. > To: FI <fallible-ideas@yahoogroups.com>, FIGG
  1247. > <fallible-ideas@googlegroups.com>
  1248. > Subject: [FI] Looking at Kant Cites
  1249. > Date: Mon, 12 Jun 2017 17:04:01 -0700
  1250. >
  1251. > I managed to look up the three Kant primary source cites from:
  1252. >
  1253. > https://www.cato-unbound.org/2016/10/12/gregory-salmieri/kant-ideal-statement-classical-liberalism
  1254. >
  1255. > Many Kant cites are a mess to deal with because they give the volume and page
  1256. > number from a German collection. Then you have to try to figure out which
  1257. > English book it's in, which I'm told is usually reasonably easy to guess once
  1258. > you've read a lot of Kant... And you can't use public domain copies of Kant
  1259. > that I've found because they don't have the German page numbers in the
  1260. > margins. I've never found cites for any other author to pose this kind of
  1261. > difficulty to look up.
  1262. >
  1263. > This page helps:
  1264. >
  1265. > http://users.manchester.edu/Facstaff/SSNaragon/Kant/Helps/AcadEd.htm
  1266. >
  1267. > But if you expected (like my first guess) to find everything from Volume 8,
  1268. > Essays after 1781, in the Cambridge _Theoretical Philosophy after 1781_ you'd
  1269. > be wrong.
  1270. >
  1271. > I found the 3 cites in the Cambridge *Practical Philosophy*.
  1272. >
  1273. > https://www.amazon.com/Practical-Philosophy-Cambridge-Works-Immanuel-ebook/dp/B00AKE1RYO/
  1274. >
  1275. > OK so let's actually check Salmieri's claims about Kant against his footnotes.
  1276. >
  1277. >> Kant coopted some of the Enlightenment’s language and used it to defend a
  1278. >> purified form of the dogmas that had long been accepted as common sense but
  1279. >> were newly under attack. In particular, by defining morality in
  1280. >> contradistinction to prudence, Kant gave a new prominence to the idea that
  1281. >> morality requires sacrifice. The “freedom” (or “autonomy”) he extols is not
  1282. >> the Enlightenment’s freedom to conceive and pursue ambitious, life-affirming
  1283. >> goals, nor is it the freedom to follow one’s whims. Rather, it is the ability
  1284. >> to obey a morality the entire content of which Kant derives from the notion
  1285. >> that there must be *something* for the sake of which one must be always ready
  1286. >> to sacrifice the whole of one’s happiness. Though a softer face is often put
  1287. >> on it by present-day Kantians, this point is crucial to his derivation of the
  1288. >> first formulation of the categorical imperative.[7]
  1289. >
  1290. >
  1291. > There's two cites. First: 4:405–407.
  1292. >
  1293. > Kant says people's needs, inclinations and satisfaction (in sum, happiness)
  1294. > are a powerful counterweight against the commands of duty. Kant says reason
  1295. > tells us of this duty while having disregard and contempt for our happiness.
  1296. > So Kant says there's a "*natural dialectic*" to argue against duty, corrupt
  1297. > it, and destroy its dignity, in order to try to make duty better suited to
  1298. > human happiness.
  1299. >
  1300. > Kant says moral worth requires doing your duty because it's your duty. If you
  1301. > do the same actions for a different reason (e.g. because they are practical)
  1302. > you don't get any moral credit.
  1303. >
  1304. > Kant says even if you carefully introspect and think there's nothing powerful
  1305. > enough in yourself to move you to moral duty -- "move us to this or that good
  1306. > action and to so great a sacrifice" -- then there could still be covert
  1307. > self-love as the real cause of your will. We can never be morally pure no
  1308. > matter how hard we try. (Note the comment abruptly equating good action with
  1309. > great sacrifice .)
  1310. >
  1311. > Second cite: 5:73
  1312. >
  1313. >> we can see a priori that the moral law, as the determining ground of the
  1314. >> will, must by thwarting all our inclinations produce a feeling that can be
  1315. >> called pain
  1316. >
  1317. >
  1318. > Morality is pain!? This is sure separating morality from practical concerns
  1319. > like human happiness, as Salmieri claimed.
  1320. >
  1321. > Kant then uses the word "freedom" to mean "an intellectual causality", rather
  1322. > than in the usual way.
  1323. >
  1324. > Kant calls *satisfaction with oneself* "self-conceit" and says the moral law
  1325. > strikes it down. He also says reason restricts self-love and self-benevolence.
  1326. >
  1327. >
  1328. > Salmieri's next paragraph is:
  1329. >
  1330. >> It is this observation about the structure of Kant’s position, rather any
  1331. >> concern about rigidity or heroic amounts of charity, that is the essence of
  1332. >> Rand’s objection to Kantian ethics.[8]She recognized that Kantian ethics is
  1333. >> flexible in many of the ways White describes, and she did not consider it a
  1334. >> point in Kant’s favor.[9] (This is as good a spot as any to mention one
  1335. >> interpretive claim White makes about Kant’s ethics that was new to me: he
  1336. >> writes of “the surprising degree of flexibility in Kant’s ethics, where even
  1337. >> perfect duties can be overridden by an imperfect duty if the latter has a
  1338. >> stronger ground of obligation.” It would certainly be surprising if Kant
  1339. >> thought this, especially given his insistence that motives of philanthropy
  1340. >> give us no right to lie to murderers who inquire after the locations of their
  1341. >> intended victims.[10] I’d be interested to hear more about which texts
  1342. >> support this interpretation.)
  1343. >
  1344. >
  1345. > And footnote 10 is 8:425–430, a short essay titled, "On a supposed right to
  1346. > lie from philanthropy"
  1347. >
  1348. > Kant says if you speak, then you must speak the truth. That's your duty to
  1349. > everyone no matter how much harm it causes, and even if lying would do no harm
  1350. > to the person you're speaking to. Kant says lying harms humanity in general
  1351. > even if no individual is harmed.
  1352. >
  1353. > Kant himself discusses the case of a murderer at your door who wants to kill
  1354. > someone in your home. Kant says if you try to lie and say "he's not home", and
  1355. > you're mistaken (he actually isn't home, but you thought he was) and then the
  1356. > murderer leaves (since you said he's not home) and finds and kills him
  1357. > elsewhere, you "can by right be prosecuted as the author of his death". I
  1358. > wondered if Kant really meant you'd be legally prosecuted, rather than just
  1359. > morally guilty. He makes this clear by bringing up paying a penalty in civil
  1360. > court.
  1361. >
  1362. > Kant states very clearly that being truthful in all your declarations is a
  1363. > "sacred command of reason" which is unconditional regardless of convenience.
  1364. >
  1365. > Kant says if you tell the truth and aid in a murder, you bear no moral guilt
  1366. > because you had no freedom to choose in the matter because truthfulness is
  1367. > your duty. Kant says an "accident *causes* the harm" in that case (not the
  1368. > murderer!?)
  1369. >
  1370. >
  1371. > ----
  1372. >
  1373. > From this reading, I judge Salmieri's claims about Kant's positions to be
  1374. > reasonable. Cite check passed!
  1375. >
  1376. > I thought all the Kant I read in this post was really bad. Does anyone
  1377. > disagree?
  1378. >
  1379. > Elliot Temple
  1380. > www.curi.us
  1381. >
  1382. > --
  1383. > You received this message because you are subscribed to the Google Groups
  1384. > "Fallible Ideas" group.
  1385. > To unsubscribe from this group and stop receiving emails from it, send an
  1386. > email to fallible-ideas+unsubscribe@googlegroups.com.
  1387. > To view this discussion on the web visit
  1388. > https://groups.google.com/d/msgid/fallible-ideas/3B34A5EC-141D-4802-A49C-9A6671E4DA5D%40curi.us.
  1389. > For more options, visit https://groups.google.com/d/optout.
Advertisement
Add Comment
Please, Sign In to add comment
Advertisement