Not a member of Pastebin yet?
Sign Up,
it unlocks many cool features!
- Expert Intuition: When Can We Trust It?
- Professional controversies bring out the worst in academics. Scientific
- journals occasionally publish exchanges, often beginning with someone’s
- critique of another’s research, followed by a reply and a rejoinder. I have
- always thought that these exchanges are a waste of time. Especially when
- the original critique is sharply worded, the reply and the rejoinder are often
- exercises in what I have called sarcasm for beginners and advanced
- sarcasm. The replies rarely concede anything to a biting critique, and it is
- almost unheard of for a rejoinder to admit that the original critique was
- misguided or erroneous in anyway. On a few occasions I have responded
- to criticisms that I thought were grossly misleading, because a failure to
- respond can be interpreted as conceding error, but I have never found the
- hostile exchanges instructive. In search of another way to deal with
- disagreements, I have engaged in a few “adversarial collaborations,” in
- which scholars who disagree on the science agree to write a jointly
- authored paper on their differences, and sometimes conduct research
- together. In especially tense situations, the research is moderated by an
- arbiter.
- My most satisfying and productive adversarial collaboration was with
- Gary Klein, the intellectual leader of an association of scholars and
- practitioners who do not like the kind of work I do. They call themselves
- students of Naturalistic Decision Making, or NDM, and mostly work in
- organizations where the"0%Jb ty often study how experts work. The N
- DMers adamantly reject the focus on biases in the heuristics and biases
- approach. They criticize this model as overly concerned with failures and
- driven by artificial experiments rather than by the study of real people doing
- things that matter. They are deeply skeptical about the value of using rigid
- algorithms to replace human judgment, and Paul Meehl is not among their
- heroes. Gary Klein has eloquently articulated this position over many
- years.
- This is hardly the basis for a beautiful friendship, but there is more to the
- story. I had never believed that intuition is always misguided. I had also
- been a fan of Klein’s studies of expertise in firefighters since I first saw a
- draft of a paper he wrote in the 1970s, and was impressed by his book
- Sources of Power, much of which analyzes how experienced professionals
- develop intuitive skills. I invited him to join in an effort to map the boundary
- that separates the marvels of intuition from its flaws. He was intrigued by
- the idea and we went ahead with the project—with no certainty that it would
- succeed. We set out to answer a specific question: When can you trust an
- experienced professional who claims to have an intuition? It was obvious
- that Klein would be more disposed to be trusting, and I would be more
- skeptical. But could we agree on principles for answering the general
- question?
- Over seven or eight years we had many discussions, resolved many
- disagreements, almost blew up more than once, wrote many draft s,
- became friends, and eventually published a joint article with a title that tells
- the story: “Conditions for Intuitive Expertise: A Failure to Disagree.”
- Indeed, we did not encounter real issues on which we disagreed—but we
- did not really agree.
- Marvels and Flaws
- Malcolm Gladwell’s bestseller Blink appeared while Klein and I were
- working on the project, and it was reassuring to find ourselves in
- agreement about it. Glad well’s book opens with the memorable story of art
- experts faced with an object that is described as a magnificent example of
- a kouros, a sculpture of a striding boy. Several of the experts had strong
- visceral reactions: they felt in their gut that the statue was a fake but were
- not able to articulate what it was about it that made them uneasy. Everyone
- who read the book—millions did—remembers that story as a triumph of
- intuition. The experts agreed that they knew the sculpture was a fake
- without knowing how they knew—the very definition of intuition. The story
- appears to imply that a systematic search for the cue that guided the
- experts would have failed, but Klein and I both rejected that conclusion.
- From our point of view, such an inquiry was needed, and if it had been
- conducted properly (which Klein knows how to do), it would probably have
- succeeded.
- Although many readers of the kouros example were surely drawn to an
- almost magical view of expert intuition, Gladwell himself does not hold that
- position. In a later chapter he describes a massive failure of intuition:
- Americans elected President Harding, whose only qualification for the
- position was that he perfectly looked the part. Square jawed and tall, he
- was the perfect image of a strong and decisive leader. People voted for
- someone who looked strong and decisive without any other reason to
- believe that he was. An intuitive prediction of how Harding would perform
- as president arose from substituting one question for another. A reader of
- this book should expect such an intuition to be held with confidence.
- Intuition as Recognition
- The early experiences that shaped Klein’s views of intuition were starkly
- different from mine. My thinking was formed by observing the illusion of
- validity in myself and by reading Paul Meehl’s demonstrations of the
- inferiority of clinical prediction. In contrast, Klein’s views were shaped by
- his early studies of fireground commanders (the leaders of firefighting
- teams). He followed them as they fought fires and later interviewed the
- leader about his thoughts as he made decisions. As Klein described it in
- our joint article, he and his collaborators
- investigated how the commanders could make good decisions
- without comparing options. The initial hypothesis was that
- commanders would restrict their analysis to only a pair of options,
- but that hypothesis proved to be incorrect. In fact, the
- commanders usually generated only a single option, and that was
- all they needed. They could draw on the repertoire of patterns that
- they had compiled during more than a decade of both real and
- virtual experience to identify a plausible option, which they
- considered first. They evaluated this option by mentally simulating
- it to see if it would work in the situation they were facing.... If the
- course of action they were considering seemed appropriate, they
- would implement it. If it had shortcomings, they would modify it. If
- they could not easily modify it, they would turn to the next most
- plausible option and run through the same procedure until an
- acceptable course of action was found.
- Klein elaborated this description into a theory of decision making that he
- called the recognition-primed decision (RPD) model, which applies to
- firefighters but also describes expertise in other domains, including chess.
- The process involves both System 1 and System 2. In the first phase, a
- tentative plan comes to mind by an automatic function of associative
- memory—System 1. The next phase is a deliberate process in which the
- plan is mentally simulated to check if it will work—an operation of System
- 2. The model of intuitive decision making as pattern recognition develops
- ideas presented some time ago by Herbert Simon, perhaps the only
- scholar who is recognized and admired as a hero and founding figure by
- all the competing clans and tribes in the study of decision making. I quoted
- Herbert Simon’s definition of intuition in the introduction, but it will make
- more sense when I repeat it now: “The situation has provided a cue; this
- cue has given the expert access to information stored in memory, and the
- information provides the answer. Intuition is nothing more and nothing less
- than recognition.”
- This strong statement reduces the apparent magic of intuition to the
- everyday experience of memory. We marvel at the story of the firefighter
- who has a sudden urge to escape a burning house just before it collapses,
- because the firefighter knows the danger intuitively, “without knowing how
- he knows.” However, we also do not know how we immediately know that a
- person we see as we enter a room is our friend Peter. The moral of
- Simon’s remark is that the mystery of knowing without knowing is not a
- distinctive feature of intuition; it is the norm of mental life.
- Acquiring Skill
- How does the information that supports intuition get “stored in memory”?
- Certain types of intuitions are acquired very quickly. We have inherited
- from our ancestors a great facility to learn when to be afraid. Indeed, one
- experience is often sufficient to establish a long-term aversion and fear.
- Many of us have the visceral memory of a single dubious dish tto hat still
- leaves us vaguely reluctant to return to a restaurant. All of us tense up when
- we approach a spot in which an unpleasant event occurred, even when
- there is no reason to expect it to happen again. For me, one such place is
- the ramp leading to the San Francisco airport, where years ago a driver in
- the throes of road rage followed me from the freeway, rolled down his
- window, and hurled obscenities at me. I never knew what caused his
- hatred, but I remember his voice whenever I reach that point on my way to
- the airport.
- My memory of the airport incident is conscious and it fully explains the
- emotion that comes with it. On many occasions, however, you may feel
- uneasy in a particular place or when someone uses a particular turn of
- phrase without having a conscious memory of the triggering event. In
- hindsight, you will label that unease an intuition if it is followed by a bad
- experience. This mode of emotional learning is closely related to what
- happened in Pavlov’s famous conditioning experiments, in which the dogs
- learned to recognize the sound of the bell as a signal that food was
- coming. What Pavlov’s dogs learned can be described as a learned hope.
- Learned fears are even more easily acquired.
- Fear can also be learned—quite easily, in fact—bywords rather than by
- experience. The fireman who had the “sixth sense” of danger had certainly
- had many occasions to discuss and think about types of fires he was not
- involved in, and to rehearse in his mind what the cues might be and how he
- should react. As I remember from experience, a young platoon
- commander with no experience of combat will tense up while leading
- troops through a narrowing ravine, because he was taught to identify the
- terrain as favoring an ambush. Little repetition is needed for learning.
- Emotional learning may be quick, but what we consider as “expertise”
- usually takes a long time to develop. The acquisition of expertise in
- complex tasks such as high-level chess, professional basketball, or
- firefighting is intricate and slow because expertise in a domain is not a
- single skill but rather a large collection of miniskills. Chess is a good
- example. An expert player can understand a complex position at a glance,
- but it takes years to develop that level of ability. Studies of chess masters
- have shown that at least 10,000 hours of dedicated practice (about 6 years
- of playing chess 5 hours a day) are required to attain the highest levels of
- performance. During those hours of intense concentration, a serious chess
- player becomes familiar with thousands of configurations, each consisting
- of an arrangement of related pieces that can threaten or defend each
- other.
- Learning high-level chess can be compared to learning to read. A first
- grader works hard at recognizing individual letters and assembling them
- into syllables and words, but a good adult reader perceives entire clauses.
- An expert reader has also acquired the ability to assemble familiar
- elements in a new pattern and can quickly “recognize” and correctly
- pronounce a word that she has never seen before. In chess, recurrent
- patterns of interacting pieces play the role of letters, and a chess position
- is a long word or a sentence.
- A skilled reader who sees it for the first time will be able to read the
- opening stanza of Lewis Carroll’s “Jabberwocky” with perfect rhythm and
- intonation, as well as pleasure:
- ’Twas brillig, and the slithytoves
- Did gyre and gimble in the wabe:
- All mimsy were the borogoves,
- And the mome raths outgrabe.
- Acquiring expertise in chess is harder and slower than learning to read
- because there are many more letters in the “alphabet” of chess and
- because the “words” consist of many letters. After thousands of hours of
- practice, however, chess masters are able to read a chess situation at a
- glance. The few moves that come to their mind are almost always strong
- and sometimes creative. They can deal with a “word” they have never
- encountered, and they can find a new way to interpret a familiar one.
- The Environment of Skill
- Klein and I quickly found that we agreed both on the nature of intuitive skill
- and on how it is acquired. We still needed to agree on our key question:
- When can you trust a self-confident professional who claims to have an
- intuition?
- We eventually concluded that our disagreement was due in part to the
- fact that we had different experts in mind. Klein had spent much time with
- fireground commanders, clinical nurses, and other professionals who have
- real expertise. I had spent more time thinking about clinicians, stock
- pickers, and political scientists trying to make unsupportable long-term
- forecasts. Not surprisingly, his default attitude was trust and respect; mine
- was skepticism. He was more willing to trust experts who claim an intuition
- because, as he told me, true experts know the limits of their knowledge. I
- argued that there are many pseudo-experts who have no idea that they do
- not know what they are doing (the illusion of validity), and that as a general
- proposition subjective confidence is commonly too high and often
- uninformative.
- Earlier I traced people’s confidence in a belief to two related
- impressions: cognitive ease and coherence. We are confident when the
- story we tell ourselves comes easily to mind, with no contradiction and no
- competing scenario. But ease and coherence do not guarantee that a
- belief held with confidence is true. The associative machine is set to
- suppress doubt and to evoke ideas and information that are compatible
- with the currently dominant story. A mind that follows WY SIATI will achieve
- high confidence much too easily by ignoring what it does not know. It is
- therefore not surprising that many of us are prone to have high confidence
- in unfounded intuitions. Klein and I eventually agreed on an important
- principle: the confidence that people have in their intuitions is not a reliable
- guide to their validity. In other words, do not trust anyone—including
- yourself—to tell you how much you should trust their judgment.
- If subjective confidence is not to be trusted, how can we evaluate the
- probable validity of an intuitive judgment? When do judgments reflect true
- expertise? When do they display an illusion of validity? The answer comes
- from the two basic conditions for acquiring a skill:
- • an environment that is sufficiently regular to be predictable
- • an opportunity to learn these regularities through prolonged practice
- When both these conditions are satisfied, intuitions are likely to be skilled.
- Chess is an extreme example of a regular environment, but bridge and
- poker also provide robust statistical regularities that can support skill.
- Physicians, nurses, athletes, and firefighters also face complex but
- fundamentally orderly situations. The accurate intuitions that Gary Klein has
- described are due to highly valid cues that es the expert’s System 1 has
- learned to use, even if System 2 has not learned to name them. In contrast,
- stock pickers and political scientists who make long-term forecasts
- operate in a zero-validity environment. Their failures reflect the basic
- unpredictability of the events that they try to forecast.
- Some environments are worse than irregular. Robin Hogarth described
- “wicked” environments, in which professionals are likely to learn the wrong
- lessons from experience. He borrows from Lewis Thomas the example of
- a physician in the early twentieth century who often had intuitions about
- patients who were about to develop typhoid. Unfortunately, he tested his
- hunch by palpating the patient’s tongue, without washing his hands
- between patients. When patient after patient became ill, the physician
- developed a sense of clinical infallibility. His predictions were accurate—
- but not because he was exercising professional intuition!
- Meehl’s clinicians were not inept and their failure was not due to lack of
- talent. They performed poorly because they were assigned tasks that did
- not have a simple solution. The clinicians’ predicament was less extreme
- than the zero-validity environment of long-term political forecasting, but they
- operated in low-validity situations that did not allow high accuracy. We
- know this to be the case because the best statistical algorithms, although
- more accurate than human judges, were never very accurate. Indeed, the
- studies by Meehl and his followers never produced a “smoking gun”
- demonstration, a case in which clinicians completely missed a highly valid
- cue that the algorithm detected. An extreme failure of this kind is unlikely
- because human learning is normally efficient. If a strong predictive cue
- exists, human observers will find it, given a decent opportunity to do so.
- Statistical algorithms greatly outdo humans in noisy environments for two
- reasons: they are more likely than human judges to detect weakly valid
- cues and much more likely to maintain a modest level of accuracy by using
- such cues consistently.
- It is wrong to blame anyone for failing to forecast accurately in an
- unpredictable world. However, it seems fair to blame professionals for
- believing they can succeed in an impossible task. Claims for correct
- intuitions in an unpredictable situation are self-delusional at best,
- sometimes worse. In the absence of valid cues, intuitive “hits” are due
- either to luck or to lies. If you find this conclusion surprising, you still have a
- lingering belief that intuition is magic. Remember this rule: intuition cannot
- be trusted in the absence of stable regularities in the environment.
- Feedback and Practice
- Some regularities in the environment are easier to discover and apply than
- others. Think of how you developed your style of using the brakes on your
- car. As you were mastering the skill of taking curves, you gradually learned
- when to let go of the accelerator and when and how hard to use the brakes.
- Curves differ, and the variability you experienced while learning ensures
- that you are now ready to brake at the right time and strength for any curve
- you encounter. The conditions for learning this skill are ideal, because you
- receive immediate and unambiguous feedback every time you go around
- a bend: the mild reward of a comfortable turn or the mild punishment of
- some difficulty in handling the car if you brake either too hard or not quite
- hard enough. The situations that face a harbor pilot maneuvering large
- ships are no less regular, but skill is much more difficult to acquire by sheer
- experience because of the long delay between actions and their
- noticeable outcomes. Whether professionals have a chance to develop
- intuitive expertise depends essentially on the quality and speed of
- feedback, as well as on sufficient opportunity to practice.
- Expertise is not a single skill; it is a collection of skills, and the same
- professional may be highly expert in some of the tasks in her domain while
- remaining a novice in others. By the time chess players become experts,
- they have “seen everything” (or almost everything), but chess is an
- exception in this regard. Surgeons can be much more proficient in some
- operations than in others. Furthermore, some aspects of any
- professional’s tasks are much easier to learn than others.
- Psychotherapists have many opportunities to observe the immediate
- reactions of patients to what they say. The feedback enables them to
- develop the intuitive skill to find the words and the tone that will calm anger,
- forge confidence, or focus the patient’s attention. On the other hand,
- therapists do not have a chance to identify which general treatment
- approach is most suitable for different patients. The feedback they receive
- from their patients’ long-term outcomes is sparse, delayed, or (usually)
- nonexistent, and in any case too ambiguous to support learning from
- experience.
- Among medical specialties, anesthesiologists benefit from good
- feedback, because the effects of their actions are likely to be quickly
- evident. In contrast, radiologists obtain little information about the accuracy
- of the diagnoses they make and about the pathologies they fail to detect.
- Anesthesiologists are therefore in a better position to develop useful
- intuitive skills. If an anesthesiologist says, “I have a feeling something is
- wrong,” everyone in the operating room should be prepared for an
- emergency.
- Here again, as in the case of subjective confidence, the experts may not
- know the limits of their expertise. An experienced psychotherapist knows
- that she is skilled in working out what is going on in her patient’s mind and
- that she has good intuitions about what the patient will say next. It is
- tempting for her to conclude that she can also anticipate how well the
- patient will do next year, but this conclusion is not equally justified. Short¬
- term anticipation and long-term forecasting are different tasks, and the
- therapist has had adequate opportunity to learn one but not the other.
- Similarly, a financial expert may have skills in many aspects of his trade
- but not in picking stocks, and an expert in the Middle East knows many
- things but not the future. The clinical psychologist, the stock picker, and the
- pundit do have intuitive skills in some of their tasks, but they have not
- learned to identify the situations and the tasks in which intuition will betray
- them. The unrecognized limits of professional skill help explain why experts
- are often overconfident.
- Evaluating Validity
- At the end of our journey, Gary Klein and I agreed on a general answer to
- our initial question: When can you trust an experienced professional who
- claims to have an intuition? Our conclusion was that for the most part it is
- possible to distinguish intuitions that are likely to be valid from those that
- are likely to be bogus. As in the judgment of whether a work of art is
- genuine or a fake, you will usually do better by focusing on its provenance
- than by looking at the piece itself. If the environment is sufficiently regular
- and if the judge has had a chance to learn its regularities, the associative
- machinery will recognize situations and generate quick and accurate
- predictions and decisions. You can trust someone’s intuitions if these
- conditions are met.
- Unfortunately, associative memory also generates subjectively
- compelling intuitions that are false. Anyone who has watched the chess
- progress of a talented youngster knows well that skill does not become
- perfect all at once, and that on the way to near perfection some mistakes
- are made with great confidence. When evaluating expert intuition you
- should always consider whether there was an adequate opportunity to
- learn the cues, even in a regular environment.
- In a less regular, or low-validity, environment, the heuristics of judgment
- are invoked. System 1 is often able to produce quick answers to difficult
- questions by substitution, creating coherence where there is none. The
- question that is answered is not the one that was intended, but the answer
- is produced quickly and may be sufficiently plausible to pass the lax and
- lenient review of System 2. You may want to forecast the commercial future
- of a company, for example, and believe that this is what you are judging,
- while in fact your evaluation is dominated by your impressions of the
- energy and competence of its current executives. Because substitution
- occurs automatically, you often do not know the origin of a judgment that
- you (your System 2) endorse and adopt. If it is the only one that comes to
- mind, it may be subjectively undistinguishable from valid judgments that
- you make with expert confidence. This is why subjective confidence is not
- a good diagnostic of accuracy: judgments that answer the wrong question
- can also be made with high confidence.
- You may be asking, Why didn’t Gary Klein and I come up immediately
- with the idea of evaluating an expert’s intuition by assessing the regularity
- of the environment and the expert’s learning history—mostly setting aside
- the expert’s confidence? And what did we think the answer could be?
- These are good questions because the contours of the solution were
- apparent from the beginning. We knew at the outset that fireground
- commanders and pediatric nurses would end up on one side of the
- boundary of valid intuitions and that the specialties studied by Meehl would
- be on the other, along with stock pickers and pundits.
- It is difficult to reconstruct what it was that took us years, long hours of
- discussion, endless exchanges of draft s and hundreds of e-mails
- negotiating over words, and more than once almost giving up. But this is
- what always happens when a project ends reasonably well: once you
- understand the main conclusion, it seems it was always obvious.
- As the title of our article suggests, Klein and I disagreed less than we
- had expected and accepted joint solutions of almost all the substantive
- issues that were raised. However, we also found that our early differences
- were more than an intellectual disagreement. We had different attitudes,
- emotions, and tastes, and those changed remarkably little over the years.
- This is most obvious in the facts that we find amusing and interesting. Klein
- still winces when the word bias is mentioned, and he still enjoys stories in
- which algorithms or formal procedures lead to obviously absurd decisions.
- I tend to view the occasional failures of algorithms as opportunities to
- improve them. On the other hand, I find more pleasure than Klein does in
- the come-uppance of arrogant experts who claim intuitive powers in zero-
- validity situations. In the long run, however, finding as much intellectual
- agreement as we did is surely more important than the persistent
- emotional differences that remained.
Add Comment
Please, Sign In to add comment