Advertisement
Guest User

Jacques Attali: Medicine Under Prosecution (from Future Li

a guest
Mar 14th, 2023
23
0
Never
Not a member of Pastebin yet? Sign Up, it unlocks many cool features!
text 32.21 KB | Writing | 0 0
  1. Jacques Attali: Medicine Under Prosecution
  2. From: Future Life, Michel Salomon, ed (Macmillan, 1983, original title 'L'avenir de la vie' (1981)
  3.  
  4. "Em Wunderkind," the Germans would say—a child prodigy. At less
  5. than forty years of age, Jacques Attali is an economist of international
  6. reputation, a professor, a political adviser much heeded by the Socialist
  7. Party, and a versatile writer—the author not only of theoretical works
  8. in his own discipline but of noted essays in such various fields as
  9. politics, music, and, recently, medicine. The book that he published in
  10. the fall of 1979, The Cannibalistic Order or the Rise and Fall of Medicitie,
  11. refueled the debate in France not only about the therapeutic act but
  12. about all the existential problems, from birth to death, that underlie
  13. medical care in the West.
  14. What makes Attali run?
  15. For his friends, so much energy expended in so many directions at
  16. once is disconcerting. For his enemies—and he has many of them, because
  17. of his political opinions, despite his amiable personality—this
  18. very gifted man is suspect. Rooted in the soil of reason, of measun
  19. the "juste milieu," the establishment has always been distrustful ^\ intellectuals.
  20.  
  21. Jacques Attali, with his excesses, his outrageousness, his constant,
  22. feverish questioning, is no doubt disturbing. But in these times of crisis,
  23. don't we do well to be more "bothered" than reassured?
  24. M.S. Why have you, an economist, taken such a passionate interest
  25. in medicine, in health?
  26. J. A. In studying the general economic problems of Western society,
  27. I found out that health costs are among the main factors in the
  28. economic crisis. The production and maintenance of consumers costs a
  29. lot—even more than the production of the commodities they consume.
  30. People are produced by the services they render one another, especially
  31. in the field of health, where economic productivity is not growing
  32. very fast. The "productivity of the production of machines" is
  33. growing more rapidly than the relative productivity of the production
  34. of consumers. That contradiction will be eliminated as health and educational
  35. systems become more commercialized and industrialized. One
  36. look at our economic history and it's easy to see that our society is,
  37. more than ever, transforming craft activities into industrial activities,
  38. and that a growing number of services are becoming mechanized.
  39. The confluence of these two questions leads one to ask: Can medical
  40. care, too, be produced by machines that will one day replace the
  41. doctor?
  42. M.S. That question seems a bit academic, theoretical. . . .
  43. J. A. Of course. But it goes a long way toward explaining the present
  44. crisis. If medical care could, like education, be mass-produced, the
  45. economic crisis would soon be resolved. This is somewhat the viewpoint
  46. of the astronomer who says: "If my reasoning is good, there is a
  47. star there." If this reasoning is accurate, and if our society is coherent,
  48. the logical conclusion is that, just as other functions have been devoured
  49. by the industrial apparatus in the earlier phases of the crisis,
  50. so medicine is becoming a mass-produced activity, which leads to the
  51. metaphor.
  52. Doctors are being replaced by prosthetic devices whose role it is
  53. to repair bodily function, restore it, or take its place. If the prosthesis
  54. tries to do those things, it behaves as the organs of the body do,
  55. hence becoming a copy of one of the body's organs or functions. Such
  56. devices would thus be objects destined to be consumed. In economic
  57. language, the metaphor is clear: it's cannibalism. The body is consumed.
  58. Beginning with this metaphor (and I've always believed it was
  59. the source of knowledge) I asked myself two questions. First, is cannibalism
  60. a possible form of treatment? Second, does there exist a conSlant in the different social structures such that an accepted kind of
  61. cannibalism, dissociated from one's experience of it and reduced to the
  62. lowest common denominator, would be found again in therapeutic
  63. behavior?
  64. First, cannibalism can be seen, on a wide scale, as a basic therapeutic
  65. strategy. Second, it seems that all strategies for healing a disease consist
  66. of a series of operations carried out by the body itself but also by
  67. cannibalism, and that one finds in all these strategies the following:
  68. selecting the signs that one is going to observe; monitoring them; denouncing
  69. what is going to break the order of those signs, what one
  70. calls Evil; negotiating with Evil, separating Evil from the rest. All healing
  71. systems employ these operations: selecting the signs, denouncing
  72. the Evil, watching, negotiating, separating. These different operations
  73. are equally applicable to political strategy: selecting the signs to be observed;
  74. watching them closely; denouncing the Evil, the scapegoat, the
  75. enemy; and driving him away. There are very profound connections
  76. between the strategy followed to combat an individual Evil and the
  77. strategy employed against a social Evil. This is what made me think,
  78. basically, that the distinction between social Evil and the individual
  79. Evil was not a very clear one. These various fundamental operations
  80. apply to different historical periods, to different conceptions of disease,
  81. of Evil, of power, of death, of life, and thus of what identifies the
  82. Evil—and effects the separation. In other words, the operations and
  83. the roles are the same, but the actors who play those roles are different.
  84. And the play does not always last the same length of time.
  85. M.S. From that to a theory founded on historical or mythical cannibalism.
  86. . . . Your essay upset and shocked not just doctors but the
  87. patients that we all are, potentially. In short, public opinion. . . .
  88. J. A. That essay tries to do three things. First, to recount an economic
  89. history of Evil—a history of its bearing on disease. Second, to
  90. show that there are, in a wav, four dominant periods and hence three
  91. great crises between which the see-sawings of the system are structured,
  92. and that each see-saw motion affects not only the healer but the
  93. very conception of life, death, and disease. Third, to show that these
  94. see-saw motions concern the signs and not the strategy, which remains
  95. cannibalistic, and that in fact we begin with cannibalism only to return
  96. to it. In short, industrial history can be interpreted as a machine for
  97. translating basic cannibalism—the first relation to Evil, wherein people
  98. eat people—into industrial cannibalism, where people become commodities
  99. that eat commodities. Industrial society would appear to function
  100. like a dictionary going through three different stages of translation
  101. and thus resulting in intermediate languages—in a sense, four major
  102. languages. First there is the basic order, the cannibalistic order. It is
  103. here that we find the first gods appearing as cannibals; and in the myths
  104. that follow, historically, the cannibal gods eat one another. Then it becomes
  105. frightful for gods to be cannibals.
  106. In all the myths I have studied, within different civilizations, religion
  107. serves to destroy cannibalism. For cannibalism, Evil is the souls of the
  108. dead. If I want to separate the souls of the dead from the dead, I must
  109. eat the bodies—because the best way of separating the dead from their
  110. souls is to eat their bodies. Thus, the idea of separation is fundamental
  111. to cannibalistic consumption. That's the point I wanted to make: Consumption
  112. is separation. Cannibalism is a formidable healing force for
  113. the power structure. Then why isn't cannibalism practiced anymore?
  114. (What I am about to say is evident in the myths. And in my essay I
  115. put forth an interpretation both of Girard's work on violence and of
  116. Freud's Totem and Taboo, in which he sees the totem and the totemic
  117. meal as basic, with the totemic meal disappearing into sexuality.) Well,
  118. from the moment I say that eating the dead permits me to live, I'll find
  119. some to eat. Thus, cannibalism is healing, but it also leads to violence.
  120. And it's in this way that I try to interpret the transition to sexual taboos,
  121. which are always the same as cannibalistic taboos. Because it's
  122. evident that if I kill my father or my mother or my children, I'm going
  123. to stop the reproduction of the group. And yet they are the easiest to
  124. kill, since they live next to me. Sexual taboos are secondary to food
  125. taboos.
  126. Next comes ritualization, the religious dramatization of cannibalism.
  127. In a sense, one delegates, represents, sets the scene. Religious civilization
  128. is a dramatization of cannibalism. The signs one observes are
  129. those of the gods. Illness is possession by the gods. The only sicknesses
  130. one can observe and cure are those of possession. Healing, finally,
  131. is expelling the Evil—and the Evil, in this case, is the Devil; that
  132. is, the gods. And the principal healer is the priest. There are always
  133. two healers on duty. The denouncer of Evil and the separater—people
  134. we will later encounter under the guises of physician and surgeon. The
  135. denouncer of Evil is the priest, and the separater is the practitioner.
  136. On the one hand, I tried to show that Christian ritual is basically
  137. cannibalistic. The texts of St. Luke on "the bread and wine," which are
  138. "the body and blood of Christ"—and which, if one eats them, give
  139. life—are cannibalistic texts and, of course, therapeutic. There is a medical,
  140. and at the same time cannibalistic, reading of those texts that is
  141. fascinating.
  142. next tried to recount the history of the Church's relation to healing,
  143. and to show little by little—around the twelfth and thirteenth centuries—
  144. the emergence of a new system of signs. Illnesses come not only
  145. from the gods but from the bodies of humans. Why? Because the economic
  146. organization is beginning. People are emerging from slavery.
  147. The dominant diseases are epidemics, which begin to circulate like men
  148. jnc\ commodities. The bodies of the poor transmit disease, and correlation
  149. between poverty (which didn't exist before, because almost
  150. everyone was either slave or seigneur) and disease is absolute. From
  151. the thirteenth to the nineteenth century, to be poor or sick meant the
  152. same thing. Hence, the political strategy with regard to the poor and
  153. the sick was the same. When one was poor, one got sick. And when
  154. one was sick, one got poor. Disease and poverty did not yet exist.
  155. What did exist was to be poor and sick. And once the poor or sick man
  156. was designated, good strategy consisted in separating him from others,
  157. containing him, not healing him but destroying him. In French texts,
  158. this was called "confining"
  159. enfermement in Foucault's vocabulary.
  160. People were confined in various ways: the quarantine camp, the lazaretto,
  161. the hospital, and, in England, the workhouse. The Poor Law and
  162. charitv were not means of helping people but means of designating
  163. them as such, and containing them. Charity was merely a form of
  164. denunciation.
  165. M.S. The policeman took the place of the priest as therapist.
  166. J .A. That's right. Religion withdrew and assumed power elsewhere
  167. because it could no longer claim the power of healing. Of course
  168. there were already doctors, but their role was limited to providing consolation;
  169. for proof of this, we have only to remember government authorities,
  170. very astutely, still did not recognize the doctors' diplomas.
  171. The political power structure considered its principal therapist the policeman,
  172. not the doctor. For that matter, in the Europe of the time,
  173. there was only one doctor for every 100,000 people.
  174. But now I come to the third period, when it was no longer possible
  175. to confine the poor because they were too numerous. They had, on the
  176. contrary, to be supported and maintained because they had become
  177. workers. And so they stopped being bodies and became machines. The
  178. signs one observed were those of machines. Illness, Evil, took the form
  179. of a breakdown. Clinical language isolated and objectified the Evil to
  180. an even greater extent. Thus, Evil was designated, separated, and
  181. expelled.
  182. During the entire nineteenth century, with public hygiene as a new
  183. means of control, the new binds of repairs, and the new distinction
  184. between doctor ,\iu\ surgeon, the policeman and the priest were replaced
  185. by the doctor.
  186. M.S. And today it's the doctor's turn to fall into the trap. . . .
  187. J. A. Today, the crisis is threefold. On the one hand, as in the
  188. preceding period, the system can no longer assure its own proper
  189. functioning. Today, for the most part, medicine is incapable of treating
  190. all diseases because it costs too much.
  191. On the other hand, there has been a loss of faith in the doctor. People
  192. have much more faith in quantified data than in the doctor.
  193. Finally, we witness the emergence of diseases and forms of behavior
  194. that no longer respond to the methods of classical medicine. These
  195. three characteristics lead to a kind of natural contiuum that moves from
  196. clinical medicine to prosthesis. And I have tried to set forth the three
  197. overlapping phases in that transformation.
  198. In the first phase, the system tries to endure by monitoring its financial
  199. cost. But that leads to the necessity of monitoring behavior and
  200. hence of defining norms of health and activity to which the individual
  201. must adhere. Thus the notion of an economical profile of a healthy life.
  202. From that, we go on to the second phase, which is that of self-diagnosis
  203. of illness (which corresponds to the designation of Evil) thanks
  204. to the tools of behavioral self-control. The individual can thus conform
  205. to the norm and become autonomous with respect to his illness.
  206. The principal criterion of behavior was, in the first order, to give
  207. meaning to death; in the second order, to contain death; in the third
  208. order, to increase the hope of life; and in the fourth, that in which we
  209. live, it's the search for an economical profile of a healthy life.
  210. The third phase is marked by the appearance of prosthetic devices
  211. that make it possible to designate the illness (Evil) in an industrial context.
  212. Thus, for example, electronic medication such as the pill coupled
  213. with a microcomputer makes it possible to release in the body, at regular
  214. intervals, regulating substances.
  215. M.S. In short, health care, with the appearance of these electronic
  216. prosthetic devices, will be the new driving force of industrial
  217. expansion. . . .
  218. J. A. Yes. In conclusion, all the traditional concepts disappear:
  219. production and consumption disappear, life and death disappear, because
  220. the prosthetic device makes death a fluid event. . . .
  221. I believe that the important thing in life will no longer be to work
  222. but to be in a position to consume—to be a consumer among other
  223. machines of consumption. The dominant social science up to the present
  224. has been the science of machines. Marx is a clinician because he
  225. designates the illness—the capitalist class—and eliminates it. In a way,
  226. he says the same thing as Pasteur. The dominant social science of the
  227. future will be the science of codes—data processing plus genetics. My
  228. book is a book about codes, because I try to show that there are successive
  229. codes: the religious code, the police code, the thermodynamic
  230. code, and today the data-processing code and what is called sociobiology.
  231. M.S. Does your thesis lead to a concrete approach to medicine,
  232. even in the long run? Does it constitute the beginnings of concrete
  233. ideas by an economist and politician on the organization of the medical
  234. profession and medical practice?
  235. J. A. I don't know. For the moment, I don't want to ask myself
  236. that question. I believe that the first thing I wanted to show—the only
  237. thing—was that healing is a process in full evolution toward a model
  238. of organization that has nothing to do with the present one, and that
  239. we have a choice between three types of attitude: to preserve the practice
  240. of medicine as we have known it; to accept its evolution and see
  241. that it is the best possible, ensuring equal access to prosthetic devices;
  242. or to rethink our view of illness entirely, in order to arrive at an acceptance
  243. of death and an awareness that the urgent thing is not to forget
  244. or delay or await death but to want life to be as free as possible. I think
  245. that people will eventually have to choose from among these three solutions;
  246. and I want to show that, in my opinion, the last one is the
  247. trulv human choice.
  248. M.S. That's social utopianism. It's sometimes dangerous to be
  249. Utopian. . . .
  250. J. A. Utopianism can take two different directions, depending on
  251. whether we are talking about Utopia as a dream of an absolute, in which
  252. case the dream is one of eternity, or as something that has never taken
  253. place in which case we then try to see which type of Utopia is most
  254. likely to be achieved. I believe that if we want to understand the problem
  255. of health care, we must realize that there are realizable Utopias.
  256. The future is necessarily a Utopia; and it's very important to understand
  257. that it need not be fraught with danger, because to talk about
  258. Utopia means to accept the idea that the future has nothing to do with
  259. merely continuing present tendencies.
  260. I would even say that all futures are possible but one: the continuation
  261. of the present situation.
  262. M.S. Is the future you postulate one in which a whole panoply
  263. of drugs will help man tolerate his condition?
  264. J. A. I'm frightened by the fascination with drugs that reduce
  265. anxiety. People are trying to find ways to make anxiety bearable instead
  266. of trying to learn how to stop feeling anxious.
  267. The medications of the future that are tied to behavior control could
  268. lead to political difficulties. It might be possible in fact to reconcile parliamentary
  269. democracy with totalitarianism. For totalitarianism to take
  270. hold, we would need only to maintain all the formal rules of parliamentary
  271. democracy but at the same time to generalize the use of those
  272. drugs.
  273. M.S. Does that seem possible—an Orwellian 1984 based on a
  274. pharmacology that would control behavior?
  275. J. A. I don't believe in the Orwellian model of technical totalitarianism
  276. with its visible and centralized Big Brother. I believe, instead, in
  277. an implicit totalitarianism with an invisible and decentralized Big
  278. Brother. Those machines that keep watch on our health, that we could
  279. use to our good, will enslave us for our good. In a way, we will undergo
  280. a gentle but permanent conditioning.
  281. M.S. How do you envision twenty-first century man?
  282. J.A. I believe that we must make a very clear distinction between
  283. two kinds of twenty-first-century man: the twenty-first-century man of
  284. the rich countries, and the twenty-first-century man of the poor countries.
  285. The former will certainly be a man much more anguished than
  286. he is today, but he will find the answer to the pain of living in passive
  287. flight, in antipain machines and antianxiety machines, in drugs; and
  288. he will try to live a commercialized form of the good life, no matter
  289. what the price.
  290. But I am convinced that the great majority of people, who will know
  291. about machines and life-style of the rich but will not have access to
  292. them, will be very aggressive and violent. From that distortion will
  293. arise enormous chaos, which will be expressed either by racial wars or
  294. by the immigration into our countries of millions of people who want
  295. to share our way of life.
  296. M.S. Do you believe that genetic engineering is one of the keys
  297. to the future?
  298. J.A. I believe that in the next twenty years genetic engineering
  299. will be as banal, well known, and commonplace procedure as the internal
  300. combustion engine is today. The analogy is, in fact, particularly
  301. apt.
  302. The internal combusion engine presented us with two options: either
  303. to favor public transportation and facilitate people's lives, or to produce
  304. automobiles—tools of aggressiveness, of consumption, of individualization,
  305. of solitude, of stockpiling, of desire, of rivalry. . . . The
  306. second option was chosen. I believe that genetic engineering occasions
  307. the same kind of choice, and that unfortunately the second option will
  308. again be chosen. In other words, genetic engineering could pretty much
  309. create conditions under which humanity could either take responsibility
  310. for itself freely but collectively, or else devise a new commodity,
  311. genetic this time, made up of copies of people sold to people, of chimeras
  312. or hybrids used as slaves, robots . . .
  313. M.S. Is it possible and desirable to live 120 years?
  314. J. A. Medically, I know nothing about it. I've always been told
  315. that it is possible. Is it desirable? First, I believe that the industrial system
  316. in which we find ourselves no longer sees an increase in life expectancy
  317. as a desirable objective. Why? Because increasing life
  318. expectancy only makes sense if the human machine's threshold of profitability
  319. is similarly increased. But as soon as a person gets to be older
  320. than sixty or sixty-five, and his productivity and profitability begin to
  321. slip, he costs society dearly.
  322. Hence, I believe that the very logic of the industrial society will require
  323. that the objective no longer be to prolong life expectancy but to
  324. see to it that man live in the best way possible—but with health care
  325. expenses as reduced as possible for the sake of the collective. Then we
  326. witness the emergence of a new criterion for life expectancy: the value
  327. attributed to extending life expectancy will not be as great as that placed
  328. on maximizing the number of years a person lives without illness, and
  329. particularly without hospitalization. Actually, from the viewpoint of the
  330. cost to society, it is much preferable that the human machine abruptly
  331. stop functioning than that it deteriorate very gradually.
  332. This is perfectly clear if we remember that two-thirds of all healthcare
  333. expenses are incurred during the last months of life. Likewise, all
  334. cvnicism aside, health-care expenses would not reach a third of the
  335. present level (175 billion francs, or about $35 billion, in 1979) if people
  336. all died in automobile accidents. We have to recognize that logic no
  337. longer resides merely in increasing life expectancy but rather in increasing
  338. life expectancy without illness. I think, however, that expanding
  339. life expectancy remains a fantasy that serves two purposes, the first
  340. of which is mainly a question of self-preservation of the power elite.
  341. The more totalitarian or centralized societies tend to be run by "old"
  342. men, and are in fact "gerontocracies." Secondly, capitalist society hopes
  343. to make old age economically profitable by making old men solvent.
  344. Right now the elderly are a "market," but not a solvent one.
  345. This all fits in very neatly with the view that man today 18 no longer
  346. important as a worker but as a consumer (because he is replaced by
  347. machines in the workplace). We see very well how the big pharmaceutical
  348. companies operate today in relatively egalitarian countries
  349. where retirement is adequately financed. They take aim at their target
  350. and favor geriatrics, at the expense of other fields of pharmacological
  351. research, such as tropical diseases. Thus, the technology of retirement
  352. determines the acceptability of increasing life expectancy.
  353. For my part, as a socialist, I am against the increasing life expectancy,
  354. because it's a decoy—a false problem. I believe that posing this
  355. type of problem enables us to avoid more essential questions such as
  356. how we go about freeing our time in the present. What is the use of
  357. living 100 years if all we gain is twenty years of dictatorship?
  358. M.S. The world to come, "liberal" or "socialist," will need a revamped,
  359. "biological" morality—an ethical code to cover cloning or euthanasia,
  360. for example.
  361. J. A. Euthanasia will be one of the essential instruments of future
  362. societies. Socialist logic is based on freedom, and the exercise of the
  363. most basic freedom is suicide. The right to commit suicide, directly or
  364. indirectly is an absolute value in this type of society. In a capitalist
  365. society, machines for killing, prosthetic devices that make it possible to
  366. eliminate life when it has become too unbearable or too expensive to
  367. sustain, will be used routinely. Euthanasia, whether an expression of
  368. freedom or a commodity, will be one of the givens of the future.
  369. M.S. Will the citizens of tomorrow be conditioned by psychotropic
  370. drugs and subjected to manipulations of the psyche? How can
  371. we guard against this?
  372. J. A. The best way to protect ourselves is to educate ourselves
  373. and increase our scientific store of knowledge. We will have to ban a
  374. great number of drugs. But perhaps the point of no return has already
  375. been passed. . . .
  376. Isn't television, for that matter, an abused drug?
  377. Hasn't alcohol always been an abused drug?
  378. The worst drug is the absence of culture. People want drugs because
  379. they have no culture. Why do they seek alienation by means of drugs?
  380. Because they have become aware of their impotence, their inability to
  381. live, and that impotence is expressed concretely in a total refusal of life.
  382. An optimistic bet on man would be to say that if man had culture,
  383. in the sense of tools for thinking, he would be able to escape solutions
  384. that only aggravate and deepen that impotence. To grasp this Evil by
  385. the root is to give people a formidable instrument of subversion and
  386. creativity-
  387. I don't believe that the banning of drugs will suffice. If we don't
  388. attack the problem at its root, we shall inevitably become enmeshed in
  389. the machinery of the police state, and that's worse.
  390. M.S. How are we going to handle mental illness in the future?
  391. J. A. The evolution of medical practice as regards mental illness
  392. will occur in two phases. In the first phase we will still rely on drugs,
  393. psychotropic ones, which have meant real progress in the treatment of
  394. mental illness during the past thirty years. In the second phase, and
  395. for economic reasons, we will begin to rely more on electronic means
  396. oi treatment—either to control pain (biofeedback), or provoke psychoanalytic
  397. dialogues (a data-processing system). This will then lead to
  398. what I call "the explicitation of the normal." That is, the electronic
  399. apparatus will make it possible to define the normal with precision,
  400. and to quantify social behavior, which will then become economically
  401. consumable because the means and criteria for conformity to norms
  402. will exist. In the long run, once a given mental illness is conquered,
  403. the temptation to conform to a "biological norm" will condition the
  404. functioning of social organization.
  405. Medicine reveals to us the evolution of a society that will orient itself
  406. toward a decentralized totalitarianism. The desire, conscious or unconscious,
  407. to conform as much as possible to social norms is nothing new.
  408. M.S. Will forced normalization govern all the realms of life, including
  409. sexuality, since science now makes possible the almost total
  410. dissociation of sexuality from conception?
  411. J. A. I think that we will go very far in that direction. The production
  412. of people is not yet a market like any other. But following the
  413. logic of my general reasoning, I can't see why procreation should not
  414. become one. The family, or the women, thus becomes a means of production
  415. of a particular object, the child. One can, in a way, imagine
  416. "wombs for rent"—something already possible, technically. This notion
  417. corresponds perfectly to an economic development in which the
  418. woman or the couple will take part in the division of labor and in general
  419. production, making it possible for people to buy children as they
  420. buy peanuts or a television set.
  421. If, on the economic plane, the child is a commodity like any other,
  422. society will in turn consider it such, but for social reasons. The survival
  423. oi the collective depends upon a sufficient pool of people. If, for economic
  424. reasons, a family does not want to have more than two children,
  425. the interests of the collective will be at risk. Thus, we get an absolute
  426. contradiction between the interests of the family and those al society.
  427. The only way to solve the contradiction is to allow society to buy children
  428. from the family. I'm not referring to family subsidies, which are
  429. feeble incentives. I mean that a family would agree to have lots of children
  430. if the state would guarantee it both the payment of progressive
  431. substantia] allowances and specific reimbursement of all material expenditures
  432. for each child. Under such a plan, the child would become
  433. a kind of medium of exchange between the individual and the collective.
  434. What I have just said is not something I take lightly or view complaisantly.
  435. It's a warning. I believe that the world we are building
  436. will be so frightful that it will mean the death of humankind. So we
  437. have to be prepared to resist it; and it seems to me today that the best
  438. way to do so is to understand and engage in the battle in order to
  439. avoid the worst. That's why I take my reasoning as far as I can.
  440. M.S. Resist what, since you foresee a world of prosthetic
  441. devices?
  442. J. A. The prosthetic devices I forsee are not mechanical but will
  443. be used to combat chronic afflictions linked to tissue degeneration. Cellular
  444. engineering, genetic engineering, and cloning are preparing the
  445. way for the development of prosthetic devices that will in effect replace
  446. defective organs.
  447. M.S. The increasing role of data processing in society calls for a
  448. revaluation of ethics. Do you see this increased reliance on data processing
  449. as a threat to man's freedom?
  450. J. A. It is clear that all the talk about preventive medicine, the
  451. economics of health care, and good medical practice will make it necessary
  452. that each person have his or her medical record on tape. For
  453. epidemiological reasons, all such dossiers will be centralized in a computer
  454. to which doctors will have access. The question arises: Will the
  455. police have access to those records too? Sweden has this kind of sophisticated
  456. system but does not have a dictatorship while certain other
  457. countries do not have this record-keeping system but do have dictatorships.
  458. In the face of new threats, we must know how to create new
  459. procedures. Democracy has a duty to adapt to technical evolution. The
  460. combination of old constitutions and new technologies may lead to totalitarian
  461. systems.
  462. M.S. One of the commonest predictions for the future is that man
  463. will be able to exercise biological control over his own body thanks to
  464. microprocessors, among other things.
  465. J.A. That control, which already exists, in the form of pacemakers
  466. for the heart, and likewise for the pancreas, should ideally be
  467. extended to apply to the elimination or reduction of pain. Researchers
  468. predict the perfection of little implants capable of releasing, in the target organs, hormones and active substances. If one's aim is to prolong
  469. life, such progress is inevitable.
  470. M.S. It seems that we are leaving an era of physics to enter <m
  471. era of biology—something close to a panbiology. Do you agree?
  472. J. A. I believe that we are leaving a world controlled by energy to
  473. enter a world of information. If matter is energy, life is information.
  474. That's why the major product of tomorrow's society will be living matter.
  475. Thanks in particular to genetic engineering, new therapeutic, nutritional,
  476. and energy tools will be developed.
  477. M.S. What is the future of medicine and medical power?
  478. J. A. In a rather brutal way, I would say that just as washerwomen
  479. have been displaced by advertising images of washing machines,
  480. so doctors integrated into the industrial system will become the
  481. developers of biological prostheses. The doctor as we know him will
  482. disappear, yielding his place to a new social category living off the
  483. prosthetics industry: inventors, salesmen, installers, and repairmen
  484. much as exist now to keep those washing machines in running order.
  485. What I have to say may seem surprising. But I wonder how many
  486. people are aware that the main enterprises interested in prosthetic devices
  487. are the big automobile manufacturers like Renault, General Motors,
  488. and Ford.
  489. M.S. In other words, we'll no longer have any need for internists
  490. because "normalization" will be effected by a kind of preventive medicine,
  491. self-managed or no, but in any case "controlled." But how can
  492. we accomplish this without resorting to force?
  493. J. A. The appearance on the market of implements for medical
  494. self-monitoring will create a preventive-medicine mentality. People will
  495. adapt to conformity to the norm. Preventive measures will not have to
  496. be forcibly imposed; people will embrace them to achieve social acceptance.
  497. But we must not lose sight of the fact that the most important
  498. thing is not technological progress but the highest form of commerce
  499. among men, represented by culture. The shape society takes in the
  500. future will be a function of our capacity to master technological progress.
  501. Will we dominate it, or be dominated by it? That's the question.
  502.  
  503.  
  504.  
  505.  
  506.  
  507.  
Advertisement
Add Comment
Please, Sign In to add comment
Advertisement