jonstond2

Friedrich Nietzsche

Dec 15th, 2015
287
0
Never
Not a member of Pastebin yet? Sign Up, it unlocks many cool features!
  1. Introduction
  2.  
  3. Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900) is one of the major figures of 19th-century European philosophy, whose influence on 20th-century thought was rivaled only by Marx. Trained as a classical scholar of antiquity, he was forced by ill health into an early retirement from his academic career while still in his thirties. Until his mental and physical collapse in early 1889, he spent his time writing his most celebrated works (including Thus Spoke Zarathustra, Beyond Good and Evil, and On the Genealogy of Morality) while living in various inns in Italy, France, and Switzerland. Little recognized during his productive lifetime, by the time of his death in 1900 he was quickly becoming the most influential figure in European intellectual life. His scathing attack on morality, his penetrating psychological insights into human behavior, and his startling views about truth and knowledge, all presented in some of the most brilliant and memorable prose ever written by a philosopher, made Nietzsche one of the most important intellectual forces with which to be reckoned at the dawn of the 20th century. Freud, Hesse, Gide, Mann, and Heidegger were among his admirers, and political movements of every stripe—anarchist, socialist, and fascist—all claimed the mantle of his influence. The political triumph of Nazism, and the efforts of his proto-Nazi sister to align him with its cause, tainted his reputation: illiberal and anti-egalitarian, to be sure, Nietzsche was also an enemy of nationalism and capitalism, which he saw as fatal obstacles to the realization of human genius and cultural excellence. In the post-World War II era, Nietzsche gradually reemerged as a thinker of profound importance, read variously as a forerunner of existentialism, post-structuralism, and philosophical naturalism, among other philosophical movements.
  4.  
  5. General Overviews
  6.  
  7. These studies differ in methodology and philosophical ambition, but they all cover some of the most famous themes in Nietzsche’s philosophy, such as the will to power, eternal recurrence, and perspectivism (though they differ on how central these themes really are to his philosophy). Clark 1990 is unusual in focusing almost entirely on the books Nietzsche published, whereas the other studies draw heavily (sometimes very heavily, as in Deleuze 1983, Heidegger 1979–1982, Richardson 1995) on the notebooks that were unpublished at the time of Nietzsche’s collapse (the Nachlass). See Editions of Nietzsche’s Work and Controversies about the Canon for more on the controversy surrounding the Nachlass material. Of these books, Clark 1990 has had the most impact on subsequent work, revolutionizing Anglophone scholarship especially, both by engaging with Nietzsche’s texts at a level of philosophical sophistication not seen previously, and by advancing, on the basis of careful readings of texts, an important hypothesis about the development of Nietzshe’s views on truth and knowledge.
  8.  
  9. Clark, Maudemarie. Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990.
  10. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  11. Argues that Nietzsche moved from skepticism about the possibility of truth based on neo-Kantian doubts about the accessibility of the world as it is (the “noumenal” world) to a repudiation of this idea and renewed confidence in the senses and empirical science. Also contains important chapters on will to power (arguing that it is mainly a kind of psychological hypothesis and not a metaphysical thesis) and eternal recurrence.
  12. Find this resource:
  13. Deleuze, Gilles. Nietzsche and Philosophy. Translated by Hugh Tomlinson. New York: Columbia University Press, 1983.
  14. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  15. English translation of Nietzsche et la Philosophie (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1962). Drawing heavily on Nachlass material, Deleuze treats the ideas of “activity” and “reactivity” as central to a systematic reading of the corpus. Not for beginners, but worth the attention of scholars and graduate students.
  16. Find this resource:
  17. Heidegger, Martin. Nietzsche. 4 vols. Translated and edited by David Farrell Krell. San Francisco: Harper and Row, 1979–1982.
  18. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  19. Heidegger’s lecture courses on Nietzsche between 1936 and 1941, transcriptions of which first appeared in two volumes in German in 1961. Essential reading for students of Heidegger, more controversial as a guide to Nietzsche, though it has been influential, especially in European scholarship. Heidegger relies heavily on Nachlass material and treats Nietzsche as the culmination of the tradition of Western metaphysics that begins with Plato. “Will to power” and the problem of “nihilism” are central in Heidegger’s reading.
  20. Find this resource:
  21. Magnus, Bernd. Nietzsche’s Existential Imperative. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1978.
  22. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  23. An important defense of the idea that Nietzsche’s doctrine of eternal recurrence ought to be understood as a kind of ethical imperative about how one should aspire to live one’s life (roughly, live in such a way that one could will the eternal repetition of one’s life).
  24. Find this resource:
  25. Nehamas, Alexander. Nietzsche: Life as Literature. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985.
  26. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  27. An elegant synthesis and restatement of what came to be known as the “French” post-structuralist Nietzsche associated with Paul DeMan, Jacques Derrida, and Sarah Kofman. Ascribes to Nietzsche a view Nehamas dubs “aestheticism,” according to which Nietzsche views the world as like a literary text and its occupants as like literary characters. The chapter on eternal recurrence remains influential, though the central interpretive thesis about aestheticism has not won much favor over time.
  28. Find this resource:
  29. Reginster, Bernard. The Affirmation of Life: Nietzsche on Overcoming Nihilism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2006.
  30. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  31. An impressive recent attempt to give an overview of Nietzsche’s philosophical corpus, organized, like Heidegger’s, around the themes of will to power and nihilism, though with much greater sensitivity to the texts than Heidegger and far more lucid. Very illuminating on the role of responses to Schopenhauer in Nietzsche’s work. Not always sensitive, however, to the philosophical plausibility of the views ascribed to Nietzsche. Its treatment of will to power is usefully contrasted with the account in Richardson 1995. Accessible to advanced undergraduates.
  32. Find this resource:
  33. Richardson, John. Nietzsche’s System. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995.
  34. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  35. Gives, as its title suggests, a systematic account of Nietzsche’s entire corpus, organized around the Heideggerian theme of will to power, and the Deleuzian theme of activity/reactivity—but does so with much greater clarity and care than either of his European interpreters. The account of will to power as the teleological tendency of any drive to co-opt other drives for its ends is the most compelling account in the literature, which all others must address. Accessible to advanced undergraduates.
  36. Find this resource:
  37. Schacht, Richard. Nietzsche. London: Routledge, 1983.
  38. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  39. Comprehensive and carefully documented overview of every aspect of Nietzsche’s philosophy, giving equal weight in its interpretation to both published and unpublished work. Schacht’s methodical canvassing of textual evidence makes his book a useful check on any interpretive hypothesis about Nietzsche. Sometimes long-winded, and not philosophically sophisticated, but a valuable resource for beginners and advanced students.
  40. Find this resource:
  41. Anthologies
  42.  
  43. There are a huge number of anthologies of essays on Nietzsche’s philosophy, most of poor quality. Those listed below have either been influential or offer enough good chapters to be worth the time of student and scholars. Allison 1977 is a good representative of the “French” Nietzsche that was popular for awhile in literary theory circles, though many of these approaches have not survived philosophical or scholarly scrutiny. Richardson and Leiter 2001, Ansell-Pearson 2006, Gemes and Richardson 2010, Schacht 1994, and Solomon 1973 feature essays spanning a wide array of topics, whereas Gemes and May 2009 and Leiter and Sinhababu 2007 represent state-of-the-art approaches to more specialized topics given by their titles.
  44.  
  45. Allison, David, ed. The New Nietzsche. New York: Dell, 1977.
  46. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  47. A collection of translations of mostly French secondary literature on Nietzsche by figures such as Blanchot, Deleuze, Derrida, Haar, and Kofman. A useful representation of a style of reading Nietzsche that was influential in literary theory circles in the 1970s and 1980s, though one now largely discredited in philosophical scholarship on Nietzsche.
  48. Find this resource:
  49. Ansell-Pearson, Keith, ed. A Companion to Nietzsche. Oxford: Blackwell, 2006.
  50. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  51. Very uneven collection of new essays on Nietzsche. Essays that are especially recommended include Came on The Birth of Tragedy, Clark and Dudrick on philosophical naturalism in Beyond Good and Evil, Loeb on eternal recurrence, Poellner on phenomenology and science, and Staten on will to power, among others.
  52. Find this resource:
  53. Gemes, Ken, and Simon May, eds. Nietzsche on Freedom and Autonomy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009.
  54. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  55. Mostly new essays on Nietzsche’s theory of the mind and action, with a particular focus on questions of free will, autonomy, and responsibility. Some essays are accessible to advanced undergraduates, but this is mainly a collection for specialists.
  56. Find this resource:
  57. Gemes, Ken, and John Richardson, eds. The Oxford Handbook of Nietzsche. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010.
  58. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  59. Promises to be an essential resource for scholars, graduate students, and even advanced undergraduates.
  60. Find this resource:
  61. Leiter, Brian, and Neil Sinhababu, eds. Nietzsche and Morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.
  62. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  63. New essays examining Nietzsche’s normative and meta-ethics, as well as his moral psychology, with contributions by leading Nietzsche scholars and moral philosophers (including Simon Blackburn, Thomas Hurka, and R. Jay Wallace). Some essays are accessible to advanced undergraduates, but this is mainly a collection for Nietzsche specialists and moral philosophers interested in Nietzsche.
  64. Find this resource:
  65. Richardson, John, and Brian Leiter, eds. Nietzsche. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001.
  66. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  67. Reprints a dozen essays and book chapters representing opposing interpretive views on such topics as truth, will to power, the critique of morality, the self and self-creation, and genealogy. Widely used in undergraduate classes, so most contributions are accessible to undergraduates.
  68. Find this resource:
  69. Schacht, Richard, ed. Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality: Essays on Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morals. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994.
  70. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  71. Contributors focus quite a bit on Nietzsche’s Genealogy, but many of the essays range much more widely. Essays that have generated substantial discussion since the volume’s publication include Clark and Foot on Nietzsche’s immoralism, Bittner on ressentiment, Nussbaum on pity, Williams on moral psychology, and Leiter on perspectivism.
  72. Find this resource:
  73. Solomon, Robert C., ed. Nietzsche: A Collection of Critical Essays. Garden City, NY: Anchor, 1973.
  74. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  75. Mostly reprints of essays and book chapters by a diverse cast of both Anglophone philosophers (e.g., Danto, Kaufmann, Schacht, Solomon) and European literary figures and philosophers (e.g., Hesse, Mann). Many of the philosophical essays have been superseded by later work, but this is still a useful book for those new to Nietzsche.
  76. Find this resource:
  77. Biographies
  78.  
  79. Kaufmann 1974 is an early effort to introduce Nietzsche’s life in conjunction with his philosophy to a modern audience, whereas Safranski 1992 is a more recent attempt to integrate the life with the ideas—neither is particularly satisfying for advanced students of philosophy, but both are helpful for novices. Janz 1978 and Hayman 1980 are very different but useful biographies, while Schain 2001 challenges the widespread claim that Nietzsche’s madness was the product of syphilis.
  80.  
  81. Hayman, Ronald. Nietzsche: A Critical Life. New York: Oxford University Press, 1980.
  82. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  83. The best short biography in English, with some attention to Nietzsche’s ideas. Accessible to beginners.
  84. Find this resource:
  85. Janz, Curt P. Friedrich Nietzsche: Biographie in drei Banden. 3 vols. Munich: Hanser, 1978.
  86. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  87. The most exhaustive biography of Nietzsche in existence, often reporting Nietzsche’s activities day by day! A rich repository of details and information for scholars, but somewhat dreary reading for the beginner.
  88. Find this resource:
  89. Kaufmann, Walter. Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist. 4th ed. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1974.
  90. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  91. Integrates an account of the main themes of Nietzsche’s philosophy with a biographical account and attention to the history of the publication of Nietzsche’s texts, with particular critical scrutiny of his sister’s efforts to misrepresent him as a proto-Nazi. Discussions of sublimation and will to power still have value for contemporary scholars, but Kaufmann’s whitewash of Nietzsche as a kind of secular humanist—while a useful antidote at the time to the even worse Nazi caricature of his ideas—is now very dated and implausible.
  92. Find this resource:
  93. Safranski, Rüdiger. Nietzsche: A Philosophical Biography. New York: Norton, 1992.
  94. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  95. Translation of Nietzsche: Biographie seines Denkens (Munich: Hauser, 2000). Integrates a detailed biographical account with generally serviceable and sensible summaries of Nietzsche’s works. A good place to start for someone wanting both the life story and a very introductory overview of the main themes of his books.
  96. Find this resource:
  97. Schain, Richard. The Legend of Nietzsche’s Syphilis. Westport, CT: Greenwood, 2001.
  98. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  99. A medical doctor offers a detailed examination of all the available evidence pertaining to Nietzsche’s collapse in 1889 and his subsequent physical and mental decline until his death in 1900. Schain argues the breakdown was not the consequence of an early syphilitic infection, but instead paranoid schizophrenia. The attempts to draw connections between the medical detective work and Nietzche’s philosophy should be ignored, but the book is an excellent resource for anyone wanting to determine the cause of Nietzsche’s mental and physical collapse.
  100. Find this resource:
  101. Editions of Nietzsche’s Work and Controversies about the Canon
  102.  
  103. Three kinds of issues have arisen about Nietzsche’s corpus. First were the efforts by his sister Elizabeth Förster-Nietzsche, after Nietzsche’s collapse in 1889, to present a selective version of the corpus that would make him more palatable to German nationalists and proto-Nazis. Kaufmann 1974 documents the violence this required her to do to the texts, especially given Nietzsche’s loathing for Germans, German nationalism, and anti-Semites (the issue is also taken up in various essays in Montinari 2003). Second, there were for many years competing editions of the corpus, but the Italian scholars Giorgio Colli and Mazzino Montinari produced the definitive edition between 1967 and 1977 (Colli and Montinari 1988). Third, and finally, questions have arisen about the weight to give to Nietzsche’s enormous Nachlass, the notebooks that were unpublished at the time of his collapse and which he had requested be destroyed. We know that Nietzsche compiled his published works from his notebooks, so the material he did not use, and wanted destroyed, is arguably not probative of his considered views. We also know that he abandoned the idea of writing a book titled The Will to Power, though after his collapse, his sister spearheaded the production of a book with that name. Magnus 1988 and Montinari 2003 are informative on these issues.
  104.  
  105. German Editions
  106.  
  107. Italian scholars Colli and Montinari have produced the authoritative editions of Nietzsche’s published and unpublished works (Colli and Montinari 1986), including his letters (Colli and Montinari 1988).
  108.  
  109. Colli, Giorgio, and Mazzino Montinari, eds. Sämtliche Briefe: Kritische Studiensausgabe. Munich: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag, 1986.
  110. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  111. Nietzsche’s complete letters.
  112. Find this resource:
  113. Colli, Giorgio, and Mazzino Montinari, eds. Sämtliche Werke: Kritische Studienausgabe in 15 Bänden. Munich: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag, 1988.
  114. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  115. The authoritative edition of Nietzsche’s complete writings (apart from letters), including all his notebook material, as well as all the books he published. A digital version is available online.
  116. Find this resource:
  117. English Editions: Kaufmann Translations
  118.  
  119. Walter Kaufmann produced generally good-quality translations (sometimes with R. J. Hollingdale) of most of Nietzsche’s major works between 1954 and 1974. These are now all available in paperback editions from Vintage (the paperback imprint of Random House), some volumes including more than one book (Kaufmann 1954 includes four). Although Kaufmann frequently sacrifices literalism in translation in order to capture in English the flavor of Nietzsche’s German, his translations are undoubtedly the most enjoyable to read in English.
  120.  
  121. Kaufmann, Walter, ed. and trans. The Portable Nietzsche. New York: Viking, 1954.
  122. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  123. Includes translations of four books (Thus Spoke Zarathustra, Twilight of the Idols, The Antichrist, and Nietzsche contra Wagner). Zarathustra was Nietzsche’s own favorite, and the first two parts sound many important Nietzschean themes taken up in later works; it is a difficult work to interpret (in part because it is a parody of The New Testament, with Zarathustra an anti-Christ figure) and is not a good place for those new to Nietzsche to begin.
  124. Find this resource:
  125. Nietzsche, Friedrich. Beyond Good and Evil. Translated by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage, 1966a.
  126. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  127. One of Nietzsche’s most important works, in which all the major themes of his philosophy are developed.
  128. Find this resource:
  129. Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Birth of Tragedy and The Case of Wagner. Translated by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage, 1966b.
  130. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  131. A useful volume for those interested in Nietzsche’s aesthetic views; The Birth of Tragedy was his first book, and reflects the profound influence of Schopenhauer and Wagner.
  132. Find this resource:
  133. Nietzsche, Friedrich. On the Genealogy of Morals and Ecce Homo. Translated by Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale. New York: Vintage, 1968a.
  134. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  135. The Genealogy is one of Nietzsche’s most important works and is unusual in that it consists of three essays that develop sustained arguments about the different origins of morality. Ecce Homo is a brilliantly entertaining autobiography, with lots of philosophical content as well, and is at the same time a parody of this self-congratulatory genre (hence its chapter titles like “Why I Am So Clever”).
  136. Find this resource:
  137. Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Will to Power. Translated by Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale. New York: Vintage, 1968b.
  138. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  139. Nietzsche abandoned the idea of writing a book with this title, but after his death, his sister and his friend Peter Gast compiled this volume from his unpublished notebooks. Although it has some continuity with themes in the published works, many of the strangest ideas or weakest arguments are found only in this material that Nietzsche had, perhaps wisely, wanted destroyed.
  140. Find this resource:
  141. Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Gay Science. Translated by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage, 1974.
  142. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  143. A richly aphoristic work of the early 1880s, it is also one of Nietzsche’s most important books. It is noticeably less polemical than work from later in the decade.
  144. Find this resource:
  145. Other English Editions
  146.  
  147. Cambridge University Press has begun publishing (mostly) new translations of Nietzsche’s books, with introductions and editorial apparatus by various scholars. All also include a chronology of Nietzsche’s life prepared by Clark and Leiter for Nietzsche 1997b. There is some variation in translation quality, but they are all generally reliable; significant variation exists in the quality of editorial apparatus (the materials accompanying Writings from the Early Notebooks and Writings from the Late Notebooks, The Birth of Tragedy, Daybreak, and The Gay Science are particularly recommended). Finally, Hackett has produced an important edition of On the Genealogy of Morality (Nietzsche 1998), notable for both the translation and the editorial apparatus.
  148.  
  149. Nietzsche, Friedrich. Human, All Too Human. Translated by R. J. Hollingdale, edited by Richard Schacht. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
  150. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  151. The major work of Nietzsche’s so-called positivist phase, in which his break with Schopenhauer and Wagner gave way to a somewhat uncritical celebration of science and scientific knowledge.
  152. Find this resource:
  153. Nietzsche, Friedrich. Untimely Meditations. Translated by R. J. Hollingdale, edited by Daniel Breazeale. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1997a.
  154. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  155. These early essays are interesting in their own right and sometimes shed light on Nietzsche’s mature views.
  156. Find this resource:
  157. Nietzsche, Friedrich. Daybreak. Translated by R. J. Hollingdale, edited by Maudemarie Clark and Brian Leiter. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1997b.
  158. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  159. First published in 1881, this book marks the arrival of the mature Nietzsche’s critique of morality; under-studied but philosophically rich, it introduces many themes developed in later work.
  160. Find this resource:
  161. Nietzsche, Friedrich. On the Genealogy of Morality. Edited and translated by Maudemarie Clark and Alan Swensen. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1998.
  162. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  163. Genealogy is one of Nietzsche’s most important works and is unusual in consisting of three essays that develop sustained arguments about the different origins of morality.
  164. Find this resource:
  165. Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Birth of Tragedy. Translated by Ronald Speirs, edited by Ronald Speirs and Raymond Geuss. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
  166. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  167. The Birth of Tragedy was Nietzsche’s first book and reflects the profound influence of Schopenhauer and Wagner.
  168. Find this resource:
  169. Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Gay Science. Translated by Josefine Nauckhoff, edited by Bernard Williams. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
  170. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  171. A richly aphoristic work of the early 1880s, it is also one of Nietzsche’s most important books. It is noticeably less polemical than work from later in the decade.
  172. Find this resource:
  173. Nietzsche, Friedrich. Beyond Good and Evil. Translated by Judith Norman, edited by Rolf-Peter Horstmann and Judith Norman. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2002.
  174. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  175. One of Nietzsche’s most important works, in which all the major themes of his philosophy are developed.
  176. Find this resource:
  177. Nietzsche, Friedrich. Writings from the Late Notebooks (1885–1888). Translated by Kate Sturge, edited by Rüdiger Bittner. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2003.
  178. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  179. This volume partially overlaps with material in the posthumous book Will to Power, compiled by Nietzsche’s sister and his friend Peter Gast. Bear in mind that Nietzsche wanted his notebooks destroyed, and that they largely consist of material he chose not to publish.
  180. Find this resource:
  181. Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Anti-Christ, Ecce Homo, Twilight of the Idols, The Case of Wagner, Nietzsche contra Wagner. Translated by Judith Norman, edited by Aaron Ridley and Judith Norman. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2005.
  182. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  183. Four late works, of which Twilight is the most philosophically important.
  184. Find this resource:
  185. Nietzsche, Friedrich. Thus Spoke Zarathustra. Translated by Adrian Del Caro, edited by Robert Pippin and Adrian Del Caro. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2006.
  186. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  187. Zarathustra was Nietzsche’s own favorite, and the first two parts sound many important Nietzschean themes taken up in later works; it is a difficult work to interpret (in part because it is a parody of The New Testament, with Zarathustra an anti-Christ figure), and not a good place for those new to Nietzsche to begin.
  188. Find this resource:
  189. Nietzsche, Friedrich. Writings from the Early Notebooks. Translated by Ladislau Löb, edited by Raymond Geuss and Alexander Nehamas. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2009.
  190. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  191. Bear in mind that Nietzsche wanted his notebooks destroyed, and that they largely consist of material he chose not to publish. Still, there are continuities here with published work.
  192. Find this resource:
  193. Controversy and Questions about the Canon
  194.  
  195. Schaberg 1995 is a detailed history of Nietzsche’s efforts to get his work published, while Kaufmann 1974 and Montinari 2003 review the ways in which, after his collapse and death, others, especially Nazis and proto-Nazis, repackaged his writings for political and other purposes. Magnus 1988 and Montinari 2003 address the status of Nietzsche’s unpublished notebooks, the Nachlass.
  196.  
  197. Kaufmann, Walter. Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist. 4th ed. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1974.
  198. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  199. Useful documentation of the malign influence of Nietzsche’s proto-Nazi sister Elizabeth on the selective editing and presentation of Nietzsche’s corpus after his collapse. See the prologue and chapter 1.
  200. Find this resource:
  201. Magnus, Bernd. “The Use and Abuse of The Will to Power.” In Reading Nietzsche. Edited by Kathleen M. Higgins and Robert C. Solomon, 218–236. New York: Oxford University Press, 1988.
  202. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  203. A briefer version of the story told in Montinari 2003 regarding the nonbook The Will to Power, compiled after Nietzsche’s mental collapse and based on notebook material he had wanted destroyed. Draws, however, some dubious conclusions about how excluding this material would affect an interpretation of Nietzsche.
  204. Find this resource:
  205. Montinari, Mazzino. Reading Nietzsche. Translated by Greg Whitlock. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 2003.
  206. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  207. Translation of the collection of essays and lectures Nietzsche Lesen (Berlin and New York: de Gruyter, 1982) by the co-editor of the authoritative edition of Nietzsche’s complete works. Most useful on the history of the texts and their publication, especially regarding Nietzsche’s intention that his unpublished notebooks not be published but destroyed. Also covers the misappropriation of Nietzsche by the Nazis and deals with some of the editorial and publication issues also treated in Kaufmann 1974.
  208. Find this resource:
  209. Schaberg, William. The Nietzsche Canon: A Publication History and Bibliography. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995.
  210. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  211. Well described by its title; a useful resource for scholars of the canon.
  212. Find this resource:
  213. Influences on Nietzsche
  214.  
  215. Trained as a scholar of the classical world—its history, literature, culture, and philosophy—Nietzsche was largely self-taught in other parts of philosophy. In the 1860s his readings of Arthur Schopenhauer’s The World as Will and Representation and Friedrich Lange’s massive History of Materialism had a profound influence on his philosophical thinking, as did later readings in German materialist and neo-Kantian philosophy of the time (Brobjer 2008 is a detailed accounting of what he read and when). It is useful to divide these influences on his philosophy into those deriving from his background as a classicist and those traceable to contemporaneous philosophical, scientific, and cultural developments.
  216.  
  217. Brobjer, Thomas. Nietzsche’s Philosophical Context: An Intellectual Biography. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 2008.
  218. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  219. A very detailed accounting—going year by year, sometimes month by month—of Nietzsche’s reading in philosophy and cognate fields. Extremely useful resource for scholars, but Brobjer’s own philosophical judgments and opinions are not always reliable.
  220. Find this resource:
  221. Influences from Antiquity
  222.  
  223. Nietzsche’s own views are nicely represented in Nietzsche 2006, whereas Barnes 1986 assesses Nietzsche’s early scholarship on Diogenes Laertius. Berry 2010a and Cancik 1995 give general overviews of Nietzsche’s engagement with ancient philosophy and (especially in Cancik) culture and literature. Berry 2010b makes a case for the relevance of Phyronnian skepticism to Nietzsche’s philosophy, while Mann 2003 examines the importance of the Sophists.
  224.  
  225. Barnes, Jonathan. “Nietzsche and Diogenes Laertius.” Nietzsche-Studien 15 (1986): 16–40.
  226. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  227. Leading contemporary scholar of classical philosophy favorably reviews Nietzsche’s dissertation work on Diogenes Laertius.
  228. Find this resource:
  229. Berry, Jessica. “Nietzsche and the Greeks.” In The Oxford Handbook of Nietzsche. Edited by Ken Gemes and John Richardson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010a.
  230. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  231. Helpful and authoritative survey of the different ways in which Greek philosophy, from the pre-Socratics onward, influenced Nietzsche’s philosophical work. Accessible to advanced undergraduates.
  232. Find this resource:
  233. Berry, Jessica. Nietzsche and the Ancient Skeptical Tradition. New York: Oxford University Press, 2010b.
  234. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  235. A systematic examination of the role of ideas derived from Phyronnian skepticism in Nietzsche’s philosophy, including his perspectivism and ethics. For scholars and graduate students.
  236. Find this resource:
  237. Cancik, Hubert. Nietzsches Antike: Vorlesung. Stuttgart, Germany: Metzler, 1995.
  238. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  239. Probably the best single-volume resource on Nietzsche’s engagement with (mainly) Greek antiquity, from his early education as a classical philologist through his writings and lectures on the pre-Socratics and Greek tragedy, and then his later philosophical work (the somewhat polemical lectures on Nietzsche’s later work can be safely ignored). Also useful on the influence of contemporaries such as Wagner and Burckhardt on Nietzsche’s conception of ancient literature and culture. Cancik is erudite and informative but not always attuned to what is philosophically important.
  240. Find this resource:
  241. Mann, Joel. “Nietzsche’s Interest and Enthusiasm for the Greek Sophists.” Nietzsche-Studien 32 (2003): 406–428.
  242. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  243. Useful in documenting the important influence of the Greek Sophists on Nietzsche, with due appreciation for the centrality of Thucydides in Nietzsche’s understanding of the Sophistic movement.
  244. Find this resource:
  245. Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Pre-Platonic Philosophers. Edited and translated by Greg Whitlock. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 2006.
  246. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  247. A compilation, with helpful editorial apparatus by Whitlock, of Nietzsche’s lectures on the pre-Socratic philosophers as well as Socrates.
  248. Find this resource:
  249. Influences from the Modern Era
  250.  
  251. The best-known influences on Nietzsche were Schopenhauer (Janaway 1998, Silk and Stern 1981, Young 1992), Lange (Salaquarda 1978, Stack 1983), and Wagner (Silk and Stern 1981), but recent scholarship has drawn attention to Nietzsche’s engagement with neo-Kantianism beyond Lange (Green 2002) and to the importance of developments in 19th-century biology and medicine to Nietzsche’s thinking (Moore 2002).
  252.  
  253. Green, Michael Steven. Nietzsche and the Transcendental Tradition. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 2002.
  254. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  255. Systematic and philosophically ambitious study of the influence of neo-Kantian philosopher Afrikaner Spir on Nietzsche’s thought. Essential reading for graduate students and scholars considering the neo-Kantian background to Nietzsche’s thought. Interesting critical questions about Green’s interpretation are raised in the review by Nadeem Hussain in Philosophical Review 113 (2004): 275–278.
  256. Find this resource:
  257. Janaway, Christopher, ed. Willing and Nothingness: Schopenhauer as Nietzsche’s Educator. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998.
  258. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  259. A collection of new essays examining different facets of Schopenhauer’s influence on Nietzsche. The introduction and chapter 1, both by Janaway, a leading Schopenhauer scholar, are especially good places to start.
  260. Find this resource:
  261. Moore, Gregory. Nietzsche, Biology, and Metaphor. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2002.
  262. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  263. Illuminating about the themes in 19th-century biology and medicine that would have informed Nietzsche’s frequent use of physiological and medical language (such as “health” and “sickness”). Its interpretive hypotheses about Nietzsche’s philosophy are debatable, but its portrait of the contemporaneous scientific culture is a useful corrective to readings that dismiss Nietzsche’s interest in these matters. The bibliography of the work is also a valuable resource in its own right.
  264. Find this resource:
  265. Salaquarda, Jörg. “Nietzsche und Lange.” Nietzsche-Studien 7 (1978): 236–253.
  266. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  267. An overview, with citations, to many points of actual and possible influence of Lange’s ideas on Nietzsche. An important starting place for graduate students and scholars.
  268. Find this resource:
  269. Silk, M. S., and J. P. Stern. Nietzsche on Tragedy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1981.
  270. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  271. Helpful discussions of the impact of Schopenhauer and Wagner on the young Nietzsche, especially with respect to his first book, The Birth of Tragedy. Chapter 1 also illuminates the scholarly culture of 19th-century German classics, against which Nietzsche, in large part, reacted.
  272. Find this resource:
  273. Stack, George. Lange and Nietzsche. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1983.
  274. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  275. An even more comprehensive version of the task begun in Salaquarda 1978, though Stack systematically overstates Lange’s influence on Nietzsche. Defects notwithstanding, a necessary resource for scholars looking at the Lange–Nietzsche connection.
  276. Find this resource:
  277. Young, Julian. Nietzsche’s Philosophy of Art. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1992.
  278. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  279. Provocative and often ingenious defense of the contrarian view that despite Nietzsche’s claim to find in art a way to resist Schopenhauer’s pessimistic verdict about the senselessness of human existence, in reality Nietzsche, without perhaps realizing it, ends up endorsing that verdict. Essential reading for scholars and graduate students interested in The Birth of Tragedy and the Nietzsche–Schopenhauer relationship more generally.
  280. Find this resource:
  281. Genealogy, Naturalism, and Questions of Philosophical Methodology
  282.  
  283. Nietzsche’s rhetorical style—inflammatory, provocative, dispensing with conventional philosophical discursiveness—raises a number of puzzles about his conception of philosophy and its proper method. Janaway 2007 is a powerful and plausible argument for the centrality of this style to his project of a revaluation of values, though he also takes partial issue with another strand in the secondary literature, namely, reading Nietzsche as a kind of philosophical naturalist, who thinks of philosophical inquiry as proceeding in tandem with the empirical sciences (such as psychology and biology). Janaway 2007, though agreeing that Nietzsche is a kind of philosophical naturalist, disputes the presentation of Nietzsche’s naturalism in Leiter’s Nietzsche on Morality (Leiter 2002, cited under Moral Philosophy). Leiter 2010 sets out the naturalist reading and responds to many of Janaway’s concerns. Kail 2009 helpfully compares Nietzsche’s naturalism to that of the other great philosophical naturalist in the modern tradition, Hume. Others associate Nietzsche’s philosophical practice with the “genealogical” method, an idea that was influentially articulated in Foucault 1977; Foucault’s treatment is usefully compared with that in Geuss 1994.
  284.  
  285. Foucault, Michel. “Nietzsche, Genealogy, History.” In Language, Counter-Memory, Practice: Selected Essays and Interviews by Michel Foucault. Edited and translated by D. F. Bouchard, 139–164. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1977.
  286. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  287. English translation of the 1971 essay Nietzsche, Genealogie, Historie, laying out an influential account of genealogy, which is also illuminating about Foucault’s own practice. Usefully contrasted with Geuss 1994. Also reprinted in Richardson and Leiter 2001 (cited under Anthologies).
  288. Find this resource:
  289. Geuss, Raymond. “Nietzsche and Genealogy.” European Journal of Philosophy 2 (1994): 275–292.
  290. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  291. Nice counterpoint to Foucault 1977; helpful discussion of the idea of a family genealogy and what it illuminates about Nietzsche’s practice. Also reprinted in Richardson and Leiter 2001 (cited under Anthologies).
  292. Find this resource:
  293. Janaway, Christopher. Beyond Selflessness: Reading Nietzsche’s Genealogy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.
  294. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  295. Discusses the main themes of Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morality, which emphasizes the role of Nietzsche’s stylistic devices for arousing the passions and emotions of his readers, a practice central, by Janaway’s account, to effecting a revaluation of values. Views Nietzsche as a naturalist, but takes issue in particular with the influential naturalistic reading of Nietzsche in Leiter 2002 (cited under Moral Philosophy). See especially chapters 1 and 3.
  296. Find this resource:
  297. Kail, Peter. “Nietzsche and Hume: Naturalism and Explanation.” Journal of Nietzsche Studies 37 (2009): 5–22.
  298. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  299. Leading Hume scholar offers a systematic overview of the role of naturalistic themes in the works of Hume and Nietzsche.
  300. Find this resource:
  301. Leiter, Brian. “Nietzsche’s Naturalism Reconsidered.” In The Oxford Handbook of Nietzsche. Edited by Ken Gemes and John Richardson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010.
  302. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  303. A defense and elaboration of the reading of Nietzsche as a naturalist from Leiter 2002 (cited under Moral Philosophy); responds in several places to Janaway 2007 and is usefully read in conjunction with the latter.
  304. Find this resource:
  305. Moral Philosophy
  306.  
  307. Issues in ethics are at the center of Nietzsche’s philosophical corpus: his critique of morality, his understanding of moral agency and psychology, his views on the objectivity of morality, and his conception of “higher men” and the ideal kind of person. Leiter 2002 and May 1999 are general overviews, whereas the other references address particular themes in Nietzsche’s moral philosophy, such as his meta-ethics (Hussain 2007), moral psychology (Risse 2001, Williams 1993), and positive ethical vision (Hurka 2007).
  308.  
  309. Clark, Maudemarie. “Nietzsche’s Immoralism and the Concept of Morality.” In Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality. Edited by Richard Schacht, 15–34. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994.
  310. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  311. What is Nietzsche’s target in attacking morality? Clark’s account may be usefully compared with Leiter 2002.
  312. Find this resource:
  313. Foot, Philippa. “Nietzsche: The Revaluation of Values.” In Nietzsche: A Collection of Critical Essays. Edited by Robert C. Solomon, 156–168. South Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1973.
  314. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  315. A useful introduction to Nietzsche’s attack on morality by a leading moral philosopher, both sympathetic to and critical of Nietzsche’s views. Also reprinted in Richardson and Leiter 2001 (cited under Anthologies).
  316. Find this resource:
  317. Hurka, Thomas. “Nietzsche: Perfectionist.” In Nietzsche and Morality. Edited by Brian Leiter and Neil Sinhbabu, 9–31. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.
  318. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  319. Leading moral philosopher reconstructs Nietzsche’s positive ethical vision as a kind of perfectionism, based on a conception of human excellence.
  320. Find this resource:
  321. Hussain, Nadeem. “Honest Illusion: Valuing for Nietzsche’s Free Spirits.” In Nietzsche and Morality. Edited by Brian Leiter and Neil Sinhababu, 157–191. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.
  322. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  323. Important recent account of Nietzsche’s meta-ethics as a kind of moral fictionalism.
  324. Find this resource:
  325. Leiter, Brian. Nietzsche on Morality. London: Routledge, 2002.
  326. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  327. Systematic and influential account of Nietzsche’s critique of morality, his conception of “higher men,” his moral psychology, and his meta-ethics. Later chapters include a commentary on Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morality. Accessible to advanced undergraduates and patient beginners. There is a compressed version of the account available online.
  328. Find this resource:
  329. May, Simon. Nietzsche’s Ethics and His “War on Morality.” Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.
  330. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  331. Useful overview of Nietzsche’s critique of morality, though it often betrays its origins as a doctoral thesis. Accessible to advanced undergraduates and patient beginners.
  332. Find this resource:
  333. Risse, Mathias. “The Second Treatise in On the Genealogy of Morality: Nietzsche on the Origin of Bad Conscience.” European Journal of Philosophy 9 (2001): 55–81.
  334. DOI: 10.1111/1468-0378.00130Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  335. Important and much discussed analysis of the most difficult of the three essays of Nietzsche’s Genealogy. Essential for scholars and graduate students.
  336. Find this resource:
  337. Williams, Bernard. “Nietzsche’s Minimalist Moral Psychology.” European Journal of Philosophy 1 (1993): 4–14.
  338. DOI: 10.1111/j.1468-0378.1993.tb00021.xSave Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  339. Moderately interesting account of Nietzsche’s moral psychology from a leading Anglophone philosopher who had a sustained interest in Nietzsche’s work.
  340. Find this resource:
  341. Political Philosophy
  342.  
  343. Nietzsche’s apparent illiberal and anti-egalitarian sentiments have raised vexing questions about what kind of political philosophy, if any, he had. One view (well represented in Detwiler 1990) is that Nietzsche was an advocate for the restoration of an aristocratic political order, one in which the “herd” of humanity would be put to service on behalf of geniuses such as Goethe and Nietzsche. Some (like Brobjer 1998) question the textual basis for ascribing this political program to Nietzsche, whereas others (Hunt 1985 is representative) call attention to Nietzsche’s astonishing hostility to politics and political philosophy: he may have been more the “esoteric moralist,” looking to transform the consciousness of select readers, than the proponent of a political program. Shaw 2007 suggests a new approach to the question of Nietzsche’s political philosophy, treating him as interested in the problem of how the modern state could be legitimate.
  344.  
  345. Brobjer, Thomas H. “The Absence of Political Ideals in Nietzsche’s Writings: The Case of the Law of Manu and the Associated Caste Society.” Nietzsche-Studien 27 (1998): 300–318.
  346. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  347. A shrewd, skeptical analysis of a famous passage from The Antichrist often adduced as evidence of Nietzsche’s commitment to an aristocratic political order.
  348. Find this resource:
  349. Detwiler, Bruce. Nietzsche and the Politics of Aristocratic Radicalism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990.
  350. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  351. An accessible and careful assembling of textual evidence in support of the idea that Nietzsche was, as his contemporary Georg Brandes dubbed him, a proponent of “aristocratic radicalism.”
  352. Find this resource:
  353. Hunt, Lester. “Politics and Anti-Politics: Nietzsche’s View of the State.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 2 (1985): 453–468.
  354. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  355. An important paper making the case that Nietzsche had no interest in politics or political philosophy.
  356. Find this resource:
  357. Shaw, Tamsin. Nietzsche’s Political Skepticism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007.
  358. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  359. Makes the novel argument that Nietzsche was concerned with the problem of how legitimate political authority is possible in a secular era, when religion is no longer a credible source of normative guidance and philosophy itself is ineffective in the public arena. The textual basis for ascribing these concerns to Nietzsche is debatable, but Shaw’s account is provocative and essential reading for graduate students and scholars interested in the question of Nietzsche’s political thought.
  360. Find this resource:
  361. Art and Literature
  362.  
  363. From Schopenhauer, Nietzsche inherited the fundamental existential problem of how life could be justified in the face of widespread and continued suffering. In his first book, The Birth of Tragedy (1872), he introduced the idea that art could justify existence in the face of human suffering. This problem occupied Nietzsche throughout his corpus and plays a particularly important role in his conception of art. Schacht 2001 is a valuable introduction to the central issues, while Young 1992 offers a contrarian view of the role of The Birth of Tragedy in Nietzsche’s corpus. Silk and Stern 1981 is a systematic analysis of The Birth of Tragedy, while Whitman 1986 is helpful in explaining Nietzsche’s intellectual “upbringing” and its role in the development of his view of Greek tragedy. Benjamin 1977 remains the most important work of literary theory influenced by Nietzsche.
  364.  
  365. Benjamin, Walter. The Origin of German Tragic Drama. Translated by John Osborne. London: New Left, 1977.
  366. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  367. Translation of Ursprung des deutschen Trauerspiels (Berlin: Rowohlt, 1928), one of the most influential works of literary and cultural criticism of the 20th century; it contains several extended discussions of Nietzsche’s views on tragedy, but the influence of Nietzsche on Benjamin’s own views can be felt in many other places. Strictly for scholars and graduate students.
  368. Find this resource:
  369. Schacht, Richard. “Making Life Worth Living: Nietzsche on Art in The Birth of Tragedy.” In Nietzsche. Edited by John Richardson and Brian Leiter. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001.
  370. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  371. Reprint of a hard-to-find 1977 essay that provides an excellent starting point for those new to The Birth of Tragedy and Nietzsche’s relationship to Schopenhauer.
  372. Find this resource:
  373. Silk, M. S., and J. P. Stern. Nietzsche on Tragedy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1981.
  374. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  375. Still the best single-volume commentary on The Birth of Tragedy, in both its intellectual background and its detailed argument. Usefully evaluates Nietzsche’s claims about Greek tragedy for their soundness, finding both faults and real insights.
  376. Find this resource:
  377. Whitman, James. “Nietzsche and the Magisterial Tradition of German Classical Philology.” Journal of the History of Ideas 47 (1986): 453–468.
  378. DOI: 10.2307/2709663Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  379. Illuminating about the German academic culture of classical philology against which The Birth of Tragedy was written.
  380. Find this resource:
  381. Young, Julian. Nietzsche’s Philosophy of Art. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1992.
  382. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  383. Provocative and often ingenious defense of the contrarian view that despite Nietzsche’s claim to have found in art a way to resist Schopenhauer’s pessimistic verdict about the senselessness of human existence, in reality Nietzsche, without perhaps realizing it, ends up endorsing that verdict. Essential readings for scholars and graduate students interested in The Birth of Tragedy and the Nietzsche–Schopenhauer relationship more generally.
  384. Find this resource:
  385. Truth, Knowledge, and Perspectivism
  386.  
  387. Perhaps no subject has been as interpretively vexed as Nietzsche’s views about truth and knowledge, which are often lumped under the rubric of his “perpectivism” (though the most famous passage on perspectivism from On the Genealogy of Morality is concerned only with knowledge, not truth). Under the influence of post-structuralism, Nietzsche was often associated with a radical skepticism about truth and knowledge, but that reading is now largely in disfavor. Clark 1990 marked a turning point, though many scholars (Poellner 1995 and Anderson 1996 are representative) have taken issue with its reading. Anderson 1998, Berry 2010, and Janaway 1997 have all tried to develop alternative accounts, paying heed to the influence of Kant, Schopenhauer, and even ancient skepticism on Nietzsche’s philosophy. Gemes 1992 is an important source for the idea that Nietzsche has no interesting contribution to make to metaphysics and epistemology, but is illuminating on the question he really cared about, namely, the value of truth.
  388.  
  389. Anderson, R. Lanier. “Overcoming Charity: The Case of Maudemarie Clark’s Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy.” Nietzsche-Studien 25 (1996): 307–341.
  390. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  391. Sustained critique of the developmental account of Nietzsche’s views in Clark 1990.
  392. Find this resource:
  393. Anderson, R. Lanier. “Truth and Objectivity in Perspectivism.” Synthèse 115 (1998): 1–32.
  394. DOI: 10.1023/A:1004984312166Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  395. Careful analysis of the “perspective” metaphor, attempting to situate Nietzsche’s views of truth and objectivity in the context of both reactions to Kant and contemporary philosophical debates about realism and antirealism. For scholars and graduate students.
  396. Find this resource:
  397. Berry, Jessica. Nietzsche and the Ancient Skeptical Tradition. New York: Oxford University Press, 2010.
  398. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  399. Provocative brief for the idea that the only kind of skepticism at work in Nietzsche is the Phyronnian kind, which demands a suspension of belief.
  400. Find this resource:
  401. Clark, Maudemarie. Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1990.
  402. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  403. The starting point for all work on this topic. Argues that Nietzsche abandons the (incoherent) view of truth in the early essay “On Truth and Lie in an Extra-Moral Sense” (popular with post-structuralist readings), and that Nietzsche’s views undergo a remarkable development: he moves from an early skepticism about the possibility of truth and knowledge based on neo-Kantian doubts about the accessibility of the world as it is (the “noumenal” world) to a repudiation of the idea of a noumenal world and a renewed confidence in the senses and empirical science.
  404. Find this resource:
  405. Clark, Maudemarie. “On Knowledge, Truth, and Value: Nietzsche’s Debt to Schopenhauer and the Development of His Empiricism.” In Willing and Nothingness: Schopenhauer as Nietzsche’s Educator. Edited by Christopher Janaway, 37–78. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998.
  406. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  407. Revises aspects of the account in Clark 1990, arguing that Nietzsche’s confidence in the deliverances of the senses predates his works of 1887–1888.
  408. Find this resource:
  409. Gemes, Ken. “Nietzsche’s Critique of Truth.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1992): 47–65.
  410. DOI: 10.2307/2107743Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  411. Argues that Nietzsche is neither much interested in theories of truth and knowledge, nor very good at formulating philosophically interesting positions on these topics; instead, his real contribution is in raising questions about the value of truth and our pursuit of it.
  412. Find this resource:
  413. Janaway, Christopher. Beyond Selflessness: Reading Nietzsche’s Genealogy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997.
  414. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  415. Exposition of Nietzsche’s critique of the idea of “disinterested” knowledge and the overvaluation of truth, as well as Nietzsche’s alternative “perspectival” account of knowledge and objectivity; skillfully situates these themes against the backdrop of Nietzsche’s reaction to Schopenhauer and Kant. The account in chapter 12 of the role of “affects” in the kind of knowledge the Genealogy aspires to impart to select readers is especially insightful, as is the explication of the connection between knowing and Nietzsche’s attack on the idea of the unitary subject. See also chapters 11 and 13.
  416. Find this resource:
  417. Poellner, Peter. Nietzsche and Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995.
  418. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  419. Erudite and philosophically demanding examination of Nietzsche’s views on causation, truth, and skepticism. Essential reading for scholars and graduate students. See especially chapters 2–4.
  420. Find this resource:
  421. Mind, Agency, and Free Will
  422.  
  423. Nietzsche denigrates the significance of consciousness, emphasizes the importance of the body, expresses skepticism about our ability to know our own motivations, and often denies the possibility of free will and moral responsibility. Leiter 1998 gives a radical interpretation of the import of these remarks, whereas many of the contributors to Gemes and May 2009 find room for putatively Nietzschean notions of freedom and responsibility. Katsafanas 2005 and Katsafanas 2010 offer careful treatments of Nietzsche’s conceptions of the unconscious and of drives, while Poellner 1995 is equally illuminating on Nietzsche’s philosophical psychology, especially the idea of the unconscious.
  424.  
  425. Gemes, Ken, and Simon May, eds. Nietzsche on Freedom and Autonomy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009.
  426. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  427. Most, not all, contributors are sympathetic to the idea that Nietzsche has room for meaningful ideas of free agency and responsibility. Essays by Gemes, Richardson, and Poellner give systematic articulations of the idea that Nietzsche has a substantive account of freedom and/or free will; Leiter represents the more skeptical view, which is then contested in the chapter by Clark and Dudrick. A natural starting point for graduate students and scholars interested in these issues.
  428. Find this resource:
  429. Katsafanas, Paul. “Nietzsche’s Theory of Mind: Consciousness and Conceptualization.” European Journal of Philosophy 13 (2005): 1–31.
  430. DOI: 10.1111/j.0966-8373.2005.00220.xSave Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  431. Important recent treatment of how Nietzsche conceives the distinction between conscious and unconscious mental states; argues provocatively that the key lies in the idea of conceptual articulatibility. Essential reading for scholars and graduate students working on this topic.
  432. Find this resource:
  433. Katsafanas, Paul. “Nietzsche’s Philosophical Psychology.” In The Oxford Handbook of Nietzsche. Edited by Ken Gemes and John Richardson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010.
  434. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  435. Careful and philosophically informed exposition of Nietzsche’s idea of a “drive” and its role in his picture of agency. Accessible to advanced undergraduates, and clearly essential for future work on this undertreated topic.
  436. Find this resource:
  437. Leiter, Brian. “The Paradox of Fatalism and Self-Creation in Nietzsche.” In Willing and Nothingness: Schopenhauer as Nietzsche’s Educator. Edited by Christopher Janaway, 217–256. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998.
  438. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  439. A widely discussed—and disputed (see Katsafanas 2005 and some of the contributions to Gemes and May 2009)—account of Nietzsche on freedom and agency, according to which Nietzsche embraces a kind of fatalism that involves the denial that agents are ever responsible for what they do. Argues that Nietzsche’s talk about “self-creation” must be read in a radically revisionary way as describing a causal process in which no “self” makes any autonomous contribution.
  440. Find this resource:
  441. Poellner, Peter. Nietzsche and Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995.
  442. Save Citation »Export Citation »E-mail Citation »
  443. Erudite and sophisticated exploration of select themes from Nietzsche’s philosophical psychology. Suitable for graduate students and scholars. See especially chapter 5.
  444. Find this resource:
Add Comment
Please, Sign In to add comment