Advertisement
Guest User

Untitled

a guest
Jul 29th, 2016
483
0
Never
Not a member of Pastebin yet? Sign Up, it unlocks many cool features!
text 1.13 MB | None | 0 0
  1. PROCESS AND REALITY
  2.  
  3. AN ESSAY IN COSMOLOGY
  4.  
  5. Gifford Lectures Delivered in the University
  6. of Edinburgh During the Session 1927-28
  7.  
  8. BY
  9.  
  10. ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
  11.  
  12. F.R.S., ScD. (Cambridge), Hon. D.Sc. (Manchester),
  13.  
  14. Hon. LL.D. (St. Andrews), Hon. D.Sc. (Wisconsin),
  15.  
  16. Hon. Sc.D. (Harvard and Yale)
  17.  
  18. CORRECTED EDITION
  19.  
  20. Edited By
  21.  
  22. DAVID RAY GRIFFIN
  23.  
  24. AND
  25.  
  26. DONALD W. SHERBURNE
  27.  
  28.  
  29.  
  30.  
  31. THE FREE PRESS
  32.  
  33. A Division of Macmillan Publishing Co,, Inc.
  34.  
  35. New York
  36.  
  37.  
  38.  
  39. Copyright © 1978 by The Free Press
  40.  
  41. A Division of Macmillan Publishing Co., Inc.
  42. Copyright, 1929, by Macmillan Publishing Co., Inc.
  43. Copyright renewed 1957 by Evelyn Whitehead.
  44.  
  45. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced
  46. or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or
  47. mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or by any
  48. information storage and retrieval system, without permission
  49. in writing from the Publisher.
  50.  
  51. The Free Press
  52.  
  53. **A Division of Macmillan Publishing Co., Inc.
  54. 866 Third Avenue, New York, N.Y. 10022
  55.  
  56. Collier Macmillan Canada, Ltd.
  57.  
  58. Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 77-90011
  59.  
  60. Printed in the United States of America
  61.  
  62. printing number
  63.  
  64. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10
  65.  
  66. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
  67.  
  68. Whitehead, Alfred North, IB6I-I9V7.
  69. Process and reality.
  70.  
  71. (Gifford lectures ; 1927-28)
  72.  
  73. Includes index.
  74.  
  75. 1. Cosmology— Addresses, essays, lectures.
  76.  
  77. 2. Science— .Philosophy— Addresses, essays, lectures.
  78.  
  79. 3. Organism (Philosophy)— Addresses, essays, lectures.
  80. I. Griffin, David II. Sherburne, Donald W.
  81. III. Title. IV. Series.
  82.  
  83. BD5H.W5 1978 113 77-90011
  84.  
  85. ISBN 0-02-93ll580-4 ^
  86.  
  87.  
  88.  
  89. EDITORS' PREFACE
  90.  
  91. Process and Reality, Whitehead's magnum opus, is one of the major
  92. philosophical works of the modern world, and an extensive body of sec-
  93. ondary literature has developed around it. Yet surely no significant philo-
  94. sophical book has appeared in the last two centuries in nearly so deplorable
  95. a condition as has this one, with its many hundreds of errors and with
  96. over three hundred discrepancies between the American (Macmillan) and
  97. the English (Cambridge) editions, which appeared in different formats
  98. with divergent paginations. The work itself is highly technical and far from
  99. easy to understand, and in many passages the errors in those editions were
  100. such as to compound the difficulties. The need for a corrected edition has
  101. been keenly felt for many decades.
  102.  
  103. The principles to be used in deciding what sorts of corrections ought to
  104. be introduced into a new edition of Process and Reality are not, however,
  105. immediately obvious. Settling upon these principles requires that one take
  106. into account the attitude toward book production exhibited by White-
  107. head, the probable history of the production of this volume, and the two
  108. original editions of the text as they compare with each other and with
  109. other books by Whitehead. We will discuss these various factors to provide
  110. background in terms of which the reader can understand the rationale for
  111. the editorial decisions we have made.
  112.  
  113. Whitehead did not spend much of his own time on the routine tasks
  114. associated with book production. Professor Raphael Demos was a young
  115. colleague of Whitehead on the Harvard faculty at the time, 1925, of the
  116. publication of Science and the Modern World. Demos worked over the
  117. manuscript editorially, read the proofs, and did the Index for that volume.
  118. The final sentence of Whitehead's Preface reads: "My most grateful
  119. thanks are due to my colleague Mr. Raphael Demos for reading the proofs
  120. and for the suggestion of many improvements in expression." After re-
  121. tiring from Harvard in the early 1960's, Demos became for four years a
  122. colleague at Vanderbilt University of Professor Sherburne and shared with
  123. him his personal observations concerning Whitehead's indifference to the
  124. production process.
  125.  
  126. Bertrand Russell x provides further evidence of Whitehead's sense of
  127. priorities when he reports that Whitehead, in response to Russell's com-
  128.  
  129. 1 Portraits from Memory (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1956), p. 104.
  130.  
  131.  
  132.  
  133. vi Editors' Preface
  134.  
  135. plaint that he had not answered a letter, "justified himself by saying that
  136. if he answered letters, he would have no time for original work/' Russell
  137. found this justification "complete and unanswerable/'
  138.  
  139. In 1929, when Process and Reality was in production, the same sense of
  140. priorities was operative. Whitehead was sixty-eight years old, and he still
  141. had major projects maturing in his mind: Adventures of Ideas, Modes of
  142. Thought, and numerous articles and lectures were still to come. "Original
  143. work," fortunately, continued to take precedence in his life over humdrum
  144. details and trivia. Unfortunately, however, 1929 found Demos in England
  145. (working with Russell). As best we can determine at this time, no one
  146. with both a familiarity with Whitehead's thought and an eye for detail
  147. undertook to shepherd Process and Reality through the production process
  148. —Demos, in particular, was never aware that anyone else from the philo-
  149. sophical community had worked on the manuscript or proofs. Whitehead's
  150. only personal acknowledgment in the Preface is to "the constant encourage-
  151. ment and counsel which I owe to my wife."
  152.  
  153. An examination of the available evidence, including the discrepancies
  154. between the two original editions and the types of errors they contained,
  155. has led us to the following reconstruction of the production process and of
  156. the origin of some of the types of errors.
  157.  
  158. First, to some extent in conjunction with the preparation of his Gifford
  159. Lectures and to some extent as an expansion and revision of them, 2 White-
  160. head prepared a hand-written manuscript. Many of the errors in the final
  161. product, such as incorrect references, misquoted poetry, other faulty quo-
  162. tations, faulty and inconsistent punctuation, and some of the wrong and
  163. missing words, surely originated at this stage and were due to Whitehead's
  164. lack of attention to details. In addition, the inconsistencies in formal mat-
  165. ters were undoubtedly due in part to the fact that the manuscript was
  166. quite lengthy and was written over a period of at least a year and a half.
  167.  
  168. Second, a typist (possibly at Macmillan) prepared a typed copy for the
  169. printer. The errors that crept into the manuscript at this stage seem to in-
  170. clude, besides the usual sorts of typographical errors, misreadings of White-
  171. head's somewhat difficult hand. 3 For example, the flourish initiating
  172. Whitehead's capital "H" was sometimes transcribed as a "T," so that
  173. "His" came out "This," and "Here" came out "There." Also, not only the
  174. regular mistranscription of "Monadology" as "MonodoZogy," but also
  175. other mistranscriptions, such as "transmuted" for "transmitted" and
  176. "goal" for "goad," probably occurred at this stage. (Professor Victor Lowe
  177.  
  178. 2 See Victor Lowe, "Whitehead's Gifford Lectures/' The Southern journal of
  179. Philosophy, Vol. 1, No. 4 (Winter, 1969-70), 329-38.
  180.  
  181. 3 For samples of his handwriting, see the letters published in Alfred North
  182. Whitehead: Essays on His Philosophy, ed. George L. Kline (New York: Pren-
  183. tice-Hall, 1963), p. 197; and The Philosophy of Alfred North Whitehead, ed.
  184. Paul Arthur Schilpp, 2nd ed. (New York: Tudor Publishing, 1951), pp. 664-
  185. 65.
  186.  
  187.  
  188.  
  189. Editors' Preface vii
  190.  
  191. has reported an incident which, whether or not it involved a misreading of
  192. Whitehead's handwriting, provided— as Lowe says— a bad omen for what
  193. would happen to the book: "On April 11, 1928, Kemp Smith received this
  194. cable from Whitehead: title gifford lectures is process and reality
  195.  
  196. SYLLOBUS FOLLOWING SHORTLY BY MAIL WHITCHCAD." 4 )
  197.  
  198. Third, it appears that Macmillan set type first and that Cambridge set
  199. its edition a bit later, using either a copy of the typed manuscript or, more
  200. likely, a copy of Macmillan's proof sheets. There are a large number of
  201. errors which the two editions had in common, a large number in the Mac-
  202. millan edition which were not in the Cambridge edition, and some few in
  203. the latter which were not in the former. Their distribution and their char-
  204. acter suggest the following observations : Macmillan provided poor proof-
  205. reading; the Cambridge editor did a much more rigorous job of catching
  206. typographical errors; the Cambridge editor also initiated certain sorts of
  207. editorial changes, which primarily involved punctuation, though these were
  208. not consistently applied throughout the entire text; finally, the types of
  209. errors unique to the Cambridge edition seem not to be due to carelessness,
  210. but to deliberate attempts to make the text more intelligible— attempts
  211. which fell short of their goal because the Cambridge editor did not under-
  212. stand Whitehead's technical concepts.
  213.  
  214. There is independent evidence that Whitehead himself saw proofs.
  215. Lowe has published a letter from Whitehead to his son, dated August 12,
  216. 1929, which reads in part: "At last I have got through with my Gifford
  217. Lectures — final proofs corrected, Index Printed, and the last corrections
  218. put in/' 5 The deplorable state of the text, plus Whitehead's lack of
  219. enthusiasm for this sort of work, make it virtually certain that he did not
  220. do much careful proofreading, Lowe reports 6 that Whitehead, after dis-
  221. cussions with C. I. Lewis, decided to change the adjectival form of "cate-
  222. gory" from "categorical" to "categoreal" and made this change throughout
  223. the galleys. We strongly suspect that Whitehead's work on the proofs was
  224. limited for the most part to very particular, specific corrections of this sort.
  225.  
  226. It would have been useful in the preparation of this corrected edition to
  227. have had Whitehead's manuscript and/or typescript. Unfortunately, all
  228. efforts to locate them have been unsuccessful— both are probably no longer
  229. extant. We do have some corrections, additions, and marginalia which
  230. Whitehead himself added to his Cambridge and Macmillan copies. In
  231. addition there is a one-page list entitled "Misprints" (evidently given to
  232. Whitehead by someone else) with an endorsement in Whitehead's hand-
  233. writing: "Corrections all inserted." This data was given to us by Lowe,
  234. who is writing the authorized biography of Whitehead and has been given
  235. access to family materials, and to whom we express our deep appreciation.
  236.  
  237. 4 Lowe, op. cii. y 334, fn. 14.
  238.  
  239. *Ibid., 338.
  240.  
  241. Q Ibid., fn. 19; as Lowe reports, he received this information from H. N. Lee.
  242.  
  243.  
  244.  
  245. viii Editors' Preface
  246.  
  247. Finally, in 1966 Lowe was allowed by Mrs. Henry Copley Greene to see a
  248. typescript of Part V, which was inscribed: "Rosalind Greene with his love
  249. From Alfred Whitehead Oct. 12, 1928." This typescript had some correc-
  250. tions in Whitehead's hand on it; Lowe reports that, with one exception,
  251. the published texts contained these corrections (e.g., the capitalization of
  252. 'Creature' and 'Itself' in the last paragraph).
  253.  
  254. It was on the basis of the above evidence and interpretations that we
  255. arrived at the principles that guided our editorial work in regard to both
  256. the more trivial and the more significant issues.
  257.  
  258. The most difficult and debatable editorial decisions had to be made,
  259. ironically, concerning relatively trivial matters, especially those involving
  260. punctuation. We tried to steer a middle course between two unacceptable
  261. extremes.
  262.  
  263. On the one hand, the editors of a "corrected edition" might have intro-
  264. duced into the text all the changes which they would have suggested to a
  265. still-living author. The obvious problem with this alternative is that, since
  266. the author is no longer living, he would have no chance to veto these "im-
  267. provements" as being inconsistent with his own meaning or stylistic prefer-
  268. ences.
  269.  
  270. On the other hand, to avoid this problem the editors might have decided
  271. to remove only the most obvious and egregious errors, otherwise leaving
  272. the text as it was. One problem with this alternative is that this important
  273. work would again be published without benefit of the kind of careful edi-
  274. torial work Whitehead had every right to expect— work which the Cam-
  275. bridge editor began but did not carry out consistently. Another problem is
  276. that there are over three hundred divergencies between the two original
  277. editions. In these places it is impossible simply to leave the text as it was—
  278. a choice must be made. And clearly, in most of these places the Cambridge
  279. punctuation is preferable and must be followed— it would be totally irre-
  280. sponsible to revert to Macmillan's punctuation. But once Cambridge's
  281. punctuation has been followed in these places, the question arises, How
  282. could one justify accepting Cambridge's improvements in these instances
  283. and yet not make similar improvements in parallel passages?
  284.  
  285. Accordingly, in trying to steer a middle course between these two ex-
  286. tremes we decided that the most responsible plan of action would be to
  287. take the changes introduced bv the Cambridge editor (which, of course,
  288. were made during Whitehead's life-time and could have been vetoed in his
  289. personal copies) as precedents for the kinds of changes to be carried out
  290. consistently. A prime example is provided by the fact that Cambridge
  291. deleted many, but not all, of the commas which often appeared between
  292. the subject and the verb in Macmillan. However, we left some other ques-
  293. tionable practices (e.g., the frequent use of a semicolon where grammatical
  294. rules would call for a comma) as they were, primarily because Cambridge
  295. did not provide sufficient precedents for changes, even though we would
  296.  
  297.  
  298.  
  299. Editors' Preface ix
  300.  
  301. ourselves have suggested changes to Whitehead had we been editing this
  302. book in 1929,
  303.  
  304. Working within these guidelines, the editors have sought to produce a
  305. text that is free not only of the hundreds of blatant errors found in the
  306. original, especially in the Macmillan edition, but also free of many of the
  307. minor sorts of inconsistencies recognized and addressed to some extent by
  308. the Cambridge editor.
  309.  
  310. It is in the matter of the more significant corrections involving word
  311. changes that editors must guard against the possibility that interpretative
  312. bias might lead to textual distortions. There were three factors which
  313. helped us guard against this possibility. First, we drew heavily upon a sub-
  314. stantial amount of previous work, coordinated by Sherburne, in which the
  315. suggested corrigenda lists of six scholars were collated and then circulated
  316. among eight scholars for opinions and observations. The publication of the
  317. results of these discussions, 7 plus the lengthy discussions that preceded and
  318. followed it, have established a consensus view about many items which
  319. provided guidance. Second, in their own work the two editors approach
  320. Whitehead's thought from different perspectives and focus their work
  321. around different sorts of interests. Third, we used the principle that no
  322. changes would be introduced into the text unless they were endorsed by
  323. both editors.
  324.  
  325. We note, finally, that there can be no purely mechanical guidelines to
  326. guarantee objectivity and prevent distortion. Ultimately, editors must rely
  327. upon their own judgment, their knowledge of their texts, and their com-
  328. mon sense. Recognizing this, we accept full responsibility for the decisions
  329. we have made.
  330.  
  331. Besides the issues discussed above, there were other editorial decisions
  332. to be made. There were substantial differences of format between the two
  333. original editions. Cambridge had a detailed Table of Contents at the be-
  334. ginning of the book, whereas Macmillan had only a brief listing of major
  335. divisions at the beginning with the detailed materials spread throughout
  336. the book as "Abstracts" prior to each of the five major Parts of the volume.
  337. Primarily because it is a nuisance to locate the various sections of this
  338. analytic Table of Contents in Macmillan, we have followed Cambridge in
  339. this matter. We have also followed the Cambridge edition in setting off
  340. some quotations and have let it guide us in regard to the question as to
  341. which quotations to set off (the Macmillan edition did not even set off
  342. page-length items).
  343.  
  344. Since most of the secondary literature on Process and Reality gives page
  345. references to the Macmillan edition, we considered very seriously the pos-
  346. sibility of retaining its pagination in this new edition. For several technical
  347.  
  348. 7 Donald W, Sherburne, "Corrigenda for Process and Reality" in Kline, ed.,
  349. op. cit, pp. 200-207.
  350.  
  351.  
  352.  
  353. x Editors' Preface
  354.  
  355. reasons this proved impractical. Consequently, we have inserted in this
  356. text, in brackets, the page numbers of the Macmillan edition, except in the
  357. Table of Contents.
  358.  
  359. In regard to certain minor differences between the texts, some of which
  360. reflect American vs. British conventions, we have followed Macmillan.
  361. Examples are putting periods and commas inside the quotation marks,
  362. numbering the footnotes consecutively within each chapter rather than on
  363. each page, and writing "Section" instead of using the symbol "$."
  364.  
  365. Except for those matters, which simply reflect different conventions, we
  366. have left a record of all of the changes which we have made. That is, in the
  367. Editors' Notes at the back of the book we have indicated all the diver-
  368. gencies (or, in a few cases, types of divergencies) from both original edi-
  369. tions, no matter how trivial, thereby giving interested scholars access to
  370. both previous readings through this corrected edition. We have indicated
  371. in the text, by means of single and double obelisks ( f and i ) , the places
  372. where these divergencies occur. The more exact meaning of these symbols,
  373. plus that of the single and double asterisks, is explained in the introductory
  374. statement to the Editors' Notes.
  375.  
  376. The original editions had woefully inadequate Indexes. For this volume,
  377. Griffin has prepared a totally new, enormously expanded Index. Sincere
  378. thanks are due to Professor Marjorie Suchocki, who correlated the Index
  379. items to the pagination in this new edition, and to Professor Bernard M.
  380. Loomer, who many years ago prepared an expanded Index which was made
  381. available to other scholars.
  382.  
  383. One other edition of Process and Reality has appeared which has not yet
  384. been mentioned. In 1969, The Free Press published a paperback edition.
  385. It should in no way be confused with the present corrected edition, pub-
  386. lished by the same company. The 1969 edition did not incorporate the
  387. corrigenda which had been published by Sherburne; it added some new-
  388. errors of its own; it introduced yet another pagination without indicating
  389. the previous standard pagination; and it did not contain a new Index. We
  390. wish to commend The Free Press for now publishing this corrected edition.
  391.  
  392. We acknowledge most gratefully the support of the Vanderbilt Uni-
  393. versity Research Council, which provided Sherburne with travel funds and
  394. released time to work on this project. We are also deeply indebted to the
  395. Center for Process Studies, which has supported this project extensively,
  396. and in turn to both the Claremont Graduate School and the School of
  397. Theology at Claremont, which give support to the Center. Finally, we
  398. express our warm appreciation to Rebecca Parker Beyer, who was a great
  399. help in comparing texts and reading proofs.
  400.  
  401. David Ray Griffin
  402. Center for Process Studies
  403.  
  404. Donald W. Sherburne
  405. Vanderbilt University
  406.  
  407.  
  408.  
  409. PREFACE
  410.  
  411. [v]* These lectures are based upon a recurrence to that phase of philo-
  412. sophic thought which began with Descartes and ended with Hume. The
  413. philosophic scheme which they endeavour to explain is termed the 'Phi-
  414. losophy of Organism/ There is no doctrine put forward which cannot cite
  415. in its defence some explicit statement of one of this group of thinkers,
  416. or of one of the two founders of all Western thought, Plato and Aristotle.
  417. But the philosophy of organism is apt to emphasize just those elements
  418. in the writings of these masters which subsequent systematizers have put
  419. aside. The writer who most fully anticipated the main positions of the
  420. philosophy of organism is John Locke in his Essay, especially x in its later
  421. books.
  422.  
  423. The lectures are divided into five parts. In the first part, the method is
  424. explained, and thet scheme of ideas, in terms of which the cosmology is to
  425. be framed, is stated summarily.
  426.  
  427. In the second part,* an endeavour is made to exhibit this scheme as ade-
  428. quate for the interpretation of the ideas and problems which form the
  429. complex texture of civilized thought. Apart from such an investigation the
  430. summary statement of Part I is practically unintelligible. Thus Part II at
  431. once gives meaning to the verbal phrases of the scheme by their use in
  432. discussion, and shows the power of the scheme to put the various elements
  433. of our experience into a consistent relation to each other. In order to ob-
  434. tain a reasonably complete account of human experience considered in
  435. relation to the philosophical [vi\ problems which naturally arise, the group
  436. of philosophers and scientists belonging to the seventeenth and eighteenth
  437. centuries has been considered, in particular Descartes, Newton, Locke,
  438. Hume, Kant. Any one of these writers is one-sided in his presentation of
  439. the groundwork of experience; but as a whole they give a general presenta-
  440. tion which dominates the development of subsequent philosophy. I started
  441. the investigation with the expectation of being occupied with the exposi-
  442. tion of the divergencies from every member of this group. But a careful
  443. examination of their exact statements disclosed that in the main the
  444. philosophy of organism is a recurrence to pre-Kantian modes of thought.
  445. These philosophers were perplexed by the inconsistent presuppositions
  446. underlying their inherited modes of expression. In so far as they, or their
  447.  
  448. 1 Cf. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Bk. IV, Ch. VI, Sect. 11.*
  449.  
  450. xi
  451.  
  452.  
  453.  
  454. xii Preface
  455.  
  456. successors, have endeavoured to be rigidly systematic, the tendency has
  457. been to abandon just those elements in their thought upon which the
  458. philosophy of organism bases itself. An endeavour has been made to point
  459. out the exact points of agreement and of disagreement.
  460.  
  461. In the second part, the discussions of modern thought have been con-
  462. fined to the most general notions of physics and biology, with a careful
  463. avoidance of all detail. Also, it must be one of the motives of a complete
  464. cosmology to construct a system of ideas which brings t the aesthetic,
  465. moral, and religious interests into relation with those concepts of the
  466. world which have their origin in natural science.
  467.  
  468. In the third and fourth parts, the cosmological scheme is developed in
  469. terms of its own categoreal notions, and without much regard to other
  470. systems of thought. For example, in Part II there is a chapter on the
  471. 'Extensive Continuum/ which is largely concerned with the notions of
  472. Descartes and Newton, compared with the way in which the organic phi-
  473. losophy must interpret this feature of the world. But in Part IV, this ques-
  474. tion is treated from the point of view of developing the detailed method
  475. [viz] in which the philosophy of organism establishes the theory of this
  476. problem. It must be thoroughly understood that the theme of these lec-
  477. tures is not a detached consideration of various traditional philosophical
  478. problems which acquire urgency in certain traditional systems of thought.
  479. The lectures are intended to state a condensed scheme of cosmological
  480. ideas, to develop their meaning by confrontation with the various topics
  481. of experience, and finally to elaborate an adequate cosmology in terms of
  482. which all particular topics find theirt interconnections. Thus the unity
  483. of treatment is to be looked for in the gradual development of the scheme,
  484. in meaning and in relevance, and not in the successive treatment of par-
  485. ticular topics. For example, the doctrines of time, of space, of perception,
  486. and of causality are recurred to again and again, as the cosmology de-
  487. velops. In each recurrence, these topics throw some new light on the
  488. scheme, or receive some new elucidation. At the end, in so far as the enter-
  489. prise has been successful, there should be no problem of space-time, or
  490. of epistemology, or of causality, left over for discussion. The scheme should
  491. have developed all those generic notions adequate for the expression of any
  492. possible interconnection of things.
  493.  
  494. Among the contemporary schools of thought, my obligations to the
  495. English and American Realists are obvious. In this connection, I should
  496. like especially to mention Professor T. P. Nunn, of the University of
  497. London. His anticipations, in the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, of
  498. some of the doctrines of recent Realism, do not appear to be sufficiently
  499. well known.
  500.  
  501. I am also greatly indebted to Bergson, William James, and John Dewey.
  502. One of my preoccupations has been to rescue their type of thought from
  503. the charge of anti-intellectualism, which rightly or wrongly has been asso-
  504. ciated with it. Finally, though throughout the main body of the work I
  505.  
  506.  
  507.  
  508. Preface xiii
  509.  
  510. am in sharp disagreement with Bradley, the final outcome is after all not
  511. so greatly different. I am particularly indebted to his chapter on the nature
  512. [viii] of experience, which appears in his Essays on Truth and Reality.
  513. His insistence on 'feeling' is very consonant with my own conclusions.
  514. This whole metaphysical position is an implicit repudiation of the doctrine
  515. of Vacuous actuality/
  516.  
  517. The fifth part is concerned with the final interpretation of the ultimate
  518. way in which the cosmological problem is to be conceived. It answers the
  519. question, What does it all come to? In this part, the approximation to
  520. Bradley is evident. Indeed, if this cosmology be deemed successful, it be-
  521. comes natural at this point to ask whether the type of thought involved
  522. be not a transformation of some main doctrines of Absolute Idealism onto
  523. a realistic basis.
  524.  
  525. These lectures will be best understood by noting the following list of
  526. prevalent habits of thought, which are repudiated, in so far as concerns
  527. their influence on philosophy:
  528.  
  529. (i) The distrust of speculative philosophy.
  530.  
  531. (ii) The trust in language as an adequate expression of propositions.
  532.  
  533. (iii) The mode of philosophical thought which implies, and is implied
  534. by, the faculty-psychology.
  535.  
  536. (iv) The subject-predicate form of expression.
  537.  
  538. (v) The sensationalist doctrine of perception.
  539.  
  540. (vi) The doctrine of vacuous actuality.
  541.  
  542. (vii) The Kantian doctrine of the objective world as a theoretical con-
  543. struct from purely subjective experience.
  544.  
  545. (viii) Arbitrary deductions in ex absurdo arguments.
  546.  
  547. (ix) Belief that logical inconsistencies can indicate anything else than
  548. some antecedent errors.
  549.  
  550. By reason of its ready acceptance of some, or all. of these nine myths
  551. and fallacious procedures, much nineteenth-century philosophy excludes
  552. itself from relevance to the ordinary stubborn facts of daily life.
  553.  
  554. The positive doctrine of these lectures is concerned with the becoming,
  555. the being, and the relatedness of 'actual entities/ An "actual entity' is a
  556. res vera in the [ix] Cartesian sense of that term; 2 it is a Cartesian 'sub-
  557. stance/ and not an Aristotelian 'primary substance/ But Descartes re-
  558. tained in his metaphysical doctrine the Aristotelian dominance of the
  559. category of 'quality' over that of 'relatedness/ In these lectures 'relatedness'
  560. is dominant over 'quality/ All relatedness has its foundation in the re-
  561. latedness of actualities; and such relatedness is wholly concerned with the
  562. appropriation of the dead by the living— that is to say, with 'objective im-
  563. mortality' whereby what is divested of its own living immediacy becomes
  564.  
  565. 2 1 derive my comprehension of this element in Descartes' thought from Pro-
  566. fessor Gilson of the Sorbonne. I believe that he is the first to insist on its im-
  567. portance. He is, of course, not responsible for the use made of the notion in
  568. these lectures.
  569.  
  570.  
  571.  
  572. xiv Preface
  573.  
  574. a real component in other living immediacies of becoming. This is the
  575. doctrine that the creative advance of the world is the becoming, the perish-
  576. ing, and the objective immortalities of those things which jointly con-
  577. stitute stubborn fact
  578.  
  579. The history of philosophy discloses two cosmologies which at different
  580. periods have dominated European thought, Plato's Timaeus, 3 and the
  581. cosmology of the seventeenth century, whose chief authors were Galileo,
  582. Descartes, Newton, Locke. In attempting an enterprise of the same kind,
  583. it is wise to follow the clue that perhaps the true solution consists in a
  584. fusion of the two previous schemes, with modifications demanded by self-
  585. consistency and the advance of knowledge. The cosmology explained in
  586. these lectures has been framed in accordance with this reliance on the
  587. positive value of the philosophical tradition. One test of success is ade-
  588. quacy in the comprehension of the variety of experience within the limits
  589. of one scheme of ideas. The endeavour to satisfy this condition is illus-
  590. trated by comparing Chapters III, VII, and X of Part II, respectively
  591. entitled The Order of Nature/ The Subjectivist Principle/ and Trocess/
  592. with Chapter [x] V of Part III, entitled The Higher Phases of Experience/
  593. and with Chapter V of Part IV, entitled 'Measurement/ and with Chap-
  594. ter II of Part V. entitled 'God and thet World/ These chapters should
  595. be recognizable as the legitimate outcome of the one scheme of ideas
  596. stated in the second chapter of Part I.
  597.  
  598. In these lectures I have endeavoured to compress the material derived
  599. from years of meditation. In putting out these results, four strong impres-
  600. sions dominate my mind: First, that the movement of historical, and
  601. philosophical, criticism of detached questions, which on the whole has
  602. dominated the last two centuries, has done its work, and requires to be
  603. supplemented by a more sustained effort of constructive thought. Sec-
  604. ondly, that the true method of philosophical construction is to frame a
  605. scheme of ideas, the best that one can, and unflinchingly to explore the
  606. interpretation of experience in terms of that scheme. Thirdly, that all
  607. constructive thought, on the various special topics of scientific interest, is
  608. dominated by some such scheme, unacknowledged, but no less influential
  609. in guiding the imagination. The importance of philosophy lies in its
  610. sustained effort to make such schemes explicit, and thereby capable of
  611. criticism and improvement.
  612.  
  613. There remains the final reflection, how shallow, puny, and imperfect are
  614. efforts to sound the depths in the nature of things. In philosophical dis-
  615. cussion, the merest hint of dogmatic certainty as to finality of statement
  616. is an exhibition of folly.
  617.  
  618. In the expansion of these lectures to the dimensions of the present book,
  619.  
  620. 3 1 regret that Professor A. E. Taylor's Commentary on Plato's Timaeus was
  621. only published after this work was prepared for the press. Thus, with the excep-
  622. tion of one small reference, no use could be made of it. I am very greatly in-
  623. debted to Professor Taylor's other writings.
  624.  
  625.  
  626.  
  627. Preface xv
  628.  
  629. I have been greatly indebted to the critical difficulties suggested by the
  630. members of my Harvard classes. Also this work would never have been
  631. written without the constant encouragement and counsel which I owe to
  632. my wife.
  633.  
  634. A. N. W.
  635. Harvard University
  636. January, 1929
  637.  
  638.  
  639.  
  640. CONTENTS
  641.  
  642. Editors' Preface v
  643.  
  644. Preface xi
  645.  
  646.  
  647.  
  648. PART I
  649. THE SPECULATIVE SCHEME
  650.  
  651. Chapter I. Speculative Philosophy
  652.  
  653.  
  654.  
  655. SECTION
  656.  
  657. I. Speculative Philosophy; Coherent, Logical, Necessary System
  658.  
  659. of Ideas; Interpretation of Experience.
  660. II. Defects of Insight and of Language; Conditions for Observa-
  661. tion; Rigid Empiricism, Imagination, Generalization; Co-
  662. herence and Incoherence; Creativity, the Ultimate.
  663.  
  664. III. Rationalism and Dogmatism; Scheme as a Matrix, False and
  665.  
  666. True Propositions, Use of the Matrix; Experimental Adven-
  667. ture.
  668.  
  669. IV. Philosophy and Science, Grades of Generality; Dogmatic Influ-
  670.  
  671. ence of Mathematics; Progress of Philosophy.
  672. V. Defects of Language; Propositions and Their Background;
  673. Metaphysical Presupposition; Excessive Trust in Language;
  674. Metaphysics and Practice; Metaphysics and Linguistic Ex-
  675. pression.
  676. VI. Speculative Philosophy and Overambition; Overambition,
  677. Dogmatism and Progress; Interpretation and Metaphysics;
  678. The Higher Elements of Experience, Subjectivity and the
  679. Metaphysical Correction; Morality, Religion, Science, Con-
  680. nected by Philosophy; Contrast between + Religion and Sci-
  681. ence; Conclusion.
  682.  
  683. Chapter II. The Categoreal Scheme 18
  684.  
  685. I. Four Notions, namely, Actual Entity, Prehension, Nexus, the
  686. Ontological Principle; Descartes and Locke; Philosophy
  687. Explanatory of Abstraction, Not of Concreteness.
  688. II. The Four Sets of Categories; The Category of the Ultimate;
  689.  
  690. xvii
  691.  
  692.  
  693.  
  694. xviii Contents
  695.  
  696. SECTION
  697.  
  698. Conjunction and Disjunction; Creativity, the Principle of
  699. Novelty, Creative Advance; Togetherness, Concrescence;
  700. Eight Categories of Existence; Twenty-Seven Categories of
  701. Explanation.
  702.  
  703. III. Nine Categoreal Obligations.
  704.  
  705. IV. Preliminary Notes; Complete Abstraction Self-Contradictory;
  706.  
  707. Principles of Unrest and of Relativity; Actual Entities never
  708. Change; Perishing of Occasions and Their Objective Im-
  709. mortality; Final Causation and Efficient Causation; Mul-
  710. tiplicities; Substance.
  711.  
  712. Chapter III. Some Derivative Notions 31
  713.  
  714. I. Primordial Nature of God; Relevance, the Divine Ordering;
  715. Consequent Nature of God; Creativity and Its Acquirement
  716. of Character; Creatures, Objective Immortality, Appetition,
  717. Novelty, Relevance; Appetition and Mentality, Conceptual
  718. Prehensions, Pure and Impure Prehensions; Synonyms and
  719. Analogies, namely, t Conceptual Prehension, Appetition, In-
  720. tuition, Physical Purpose, Vision, Envisagement.
  721. II. Social Order, Defining Characteristic, Substantial Form; Per-
  722. sonal Order, Serial Inheritance, Enduring Object; Corpus-
  723. cular Societies.
  724.  
  725. III. Classic Notion of Time, Unique Seriality; Continuity of Be-
  726.  
  727. coming, Becoming of Continuity, Zeno; Atomism and Con-
  728. tinuity; Corpuscular and Wave Theories of Light.
  729.  
  730. IV. Consciousness, Thought, Sense-Perception are Unessential Ele-
  731.  
  732. ments in an Instance of Experience.
  733.  
  734.  
  735.  
  736. PART II
  737. DISCUSSIONS AND APPLICATIONS
  738.  
  739. Chapter I. Fact and Form 39
  740.  
  741. I. Appeal to Facts, European Tradition; Plato, Aristotle, Des-
  742. cartes, Locke, Hume, Kant; Intrinsic Reasonableness; Foot-
  743. notes to Plato; This Cosmology Platonic; Participating
  744. Forms; Divine Ordering; Ontological Principle; Facts the
  745. only Reasons; Facts are Process; Prehension, Satisfaction.
  746. II. Rationalism a Faith, Adventure of Hope; Limits of Theory,
  747. Givenness,t Professor A. E. Taylor on Plato; Decision, the
  748.  
  749.  
  750.  
  751. Contents xix
  752.  
  753. SECTION
  754.  
  755. Ontological Principle; Entities and Process, Actual Entities
  756. and Decision; Stubborn Fact.
  757.  
  758. III. Platonic Form 7 Idea, Essence, Eternal Object; Potentiality and
  759.  
  760. Givenness; Exclusiveness of the Given; Subject-Superject,
  761. Becoming and Being; Evaporation of Indeterrnination in
  762. Concrescence, Satisfaction Determinate and Exclusive; Con-
  763. crescence Dipolar; Potentiality, Givenness, Impossibility;
  764. Subsistence.
  765.  
  766. IV. Actual Occasions Internally Determined,! Externally Free;
  767.  
  768. Course of History not Necessary, No Perfection; Efficient
  769. Causation and Final Reaction; God's Primordial Freedom;
  770. Each Concrescence between Definite Free Initiation and
  771. Definite Free Conclusion, the Former Macrocosmic, the
  772. Latter Microcosmic.
  773. V. Universals and Particulars, Unsuitable Terms with False Im-
  774. plication; Illustration from Descartes, also Hume; Des-
  775. cartes' Alternative Doctrine, Realitas Objective, Inspectio,
  776. Intuitio, Judicium; World not Describable in Terms of Sub-
  777. ject and Predicate. Substance and Quality, Particular and
  778. Universal; Universal Relativity.
  779. VI. Locke's Essay ,t Agreement of Organic Philosophy with It; Sub-
  780. stitute 'Experience 7 for 'Understanding'; Ideas and Prehen-
  781. sions; Locke's Two Doctrines of Ideas, Ideas of Particular
  782. Things; Representative Theory of Perception; Logical Sim-
  783. plicity and Genetic Priority not to be Identified; Substance,
  784. Exterior Things, Societies; Solidarity of the Universe.
  785. VII. Locke's Doctrine of Power, Power and Substance; Causal
  786. Objectification and Presentational Objectification; Change
  787. Means Adventures of Eternal Objects; Real Essence,
  788. Abstract Essence; Doctrine of Organism and Generation of
  789. Actual Entities.
  790.  
  791. Chapter II. The Extensive Continuum 61
  792.  
  793. I. Continuum and Real Potentiality, Atomized by Actual Occa-
  794. sions; How the Continuum is Experienced, Presentational
  795. Immediacy, Sensa; Real Chair and Chair-Image; Complex
  796. Ingression of Sensa.
  797. II. General Potentiality and Pxeal Potentiality; Standpoints of
  798. Actual Occasions, Determined by Initial Phase of Subjective
  799. Aim; Extensive Relationships; The Epochal Theory of
  800. Time, Zeno, William James.
  801. III. Newton's Scholium,
  802.  
  803.  
  804.  
  805. xx Contents
  806.  
  807. SECTION
  808.  
  809. IV. Newton's Scholium, Comparison with Philosophy of Organism
  810. and with Descartes; 'Withness of the Body/ Status of the
  811. Body in the Actual World; Ontological Status of Space for
  812. Newton, Descartes and the Organic Philosophy.
  813. V. Undifferentiated Endurance and the Passivity of Substance,
  814. Source of Errors.
  815.  
  816. VI. Summary.
  817.  
  818. Chapter III. The Order of Nature 83
  819.  
  820. I. Order and Givenness Contrasted; The Four Characteristics
  821. of Order; Attainment of End, Lure of** Feeling; Causa Sui.
  822. II. 'Society' Defined, Defining Characteristic and Genetic Inher-
  823. itance; Environment,! Social and Permissive; Cosmic Epoch,
  824. Social Hierarchy.
  825.  
  826. III. Evolution of Societies, Decay, Chaos, the Timaeus, the Schol-
  827.  
  828. ium, Milton.
  829.  
  830. IV. Societies in this Cosmic Epoch; The Extensive Society, the
  831.  
  832. Geometric Society. Electromagnetic Society; Waves. Elec-
  833. trons, Protons.
  834. V. Enduring Objects, Corpuscular Societies, Structured Societies.
  835. VI. Stability, Specialization.
  836.  
  837. VII. Problem of Stabilization, Exclusion of Detail, Conceptual Ini-
  838. tiative, Life.
  839. VIII. Inorganic Apparatus for Life.
  840. IX. Life a Reaction against Society, Originality.
  841. X. Life and Food, Life in Empty Space, Catalytic Agent.
  842. XL Living Persons, Canalization of Life, Dominant Personality
  843. only Partial.
  844.  
  845. Chapter IV. Organisms and Environment 110
  846.  
  847. I. Reaction of Environment on Actual Occasions; Narrowness
  848. and Width, Dependent on Societies, Orderly Element;
  849. Chaos, Triviality, Orderliness, Depth; Triviality,! Vagueness,
  850. Narrowness, Width; Incompatibility, Contrast; Triviality,
  851. Excess of Differentiation; Vagueness, Excess of Identifica-
  852. tion; Nexus as One, Vagueness, Narrowness, Depth; Coor-
  853. dination % of Chaos, Vagueness, Narrowness, Width.
  854. II. Intensity, Narrowness; Philosophy of Organism, Kant, Locke.
  855. III. Sensa, Lowest Category of Eternal Objects, Definition; Sensa,
  856. Contrasts of, Intensity; Contrasts in High and Low Cate-
  857. gories, Patterns; Eternal Objects, Simplicity, Complexity;
  858. Sensa Experienced Emotionally.
  859.  
  860.  
  861.  
  862. Contents xxi
  863.  
  864. SECTION
  865.  
  866. IV. Transmission, Diverse Routes, Inhibitions, Intensification;
  867.  
  868. Vector Character, Form of Energy; Physical Science.
  869. V. Environmental Data as in Perception; Visual Perception,
  870. Most Sophisticated Form; Originated by Antecedent State
  871. of Animal Body, Hume; Animal Body and External Envi-
  872. ronment, Amplifier.!
  873.  
  874. VI. Perception and Animal Body, Causal Efficacy.
  875. VII. Causal Efficacy, Viscera; Presentational Immediacy, Delusive
  876. Perceptions, Secondary Qualities, Extension, Withness of
  877. Body; Hume, Kant.
  878. VIII. Loci Disclosed by Perception; Contemporary Regions, Causal
  879. Past, Causal Future; Immediate Present, Unison of Becom-
  880. ing, Concrescent Unison, Duration; Differentiation between
  881. Immediate Present and Presented Duration; Presented
  882. Locus.
  883.  
  884. IX. Presented Locus and Unison of Becoming; Presented Locus,
  885. Systematic Relation to Animal Body, Strains, Independence
  886. of External Contemporary Happenings, Straight Lines,
  887. Measurement; Unison of Becoming, Duration.
  888. X. Summary.
  889.  
  890. Chapter V. Locke and Hume 130
  891.  
  892. I. Hume, Perceptions, Substance, Principle of Union; Ideas,
  893.  
  894. Copies of Impressions, Imaginative Freedom.
  895. II. Hume and 'Repetition/ Cause and Effect; Memory, Force
  896. and Vivacity.
  897.  
  898. III. Time, Hume, Descartes, Independence of Successive Occa-
  899.  
  900. sions; Objective Immortality.
  901.  
  902. IV. Influence of Subject-Predicate Notion; Hume, Descartes,
  903.  
  904. Locke, Particular Existence.
  905. V. Hume and Locke, Process and Morphology; False Derivation
  906. of Emotional Feelings; Sensationalist Doctrine; Santayana.
  907.  
  908. Chapter VI. From Descartes to Kant 144
  909.  
  910. I. Descartes, Three Kinds of Substance: Extended, Mental,
  911. God's; Three Kinds of Change, of Accidents, Origination,
  912. Cessation; Accidental Relations, Representative Ideas; Un-
  913. essential Experience of External World.
  914. II. Locke, Empiricism, Adequacy, Inconsistency; Particular Exis-
  915. tent, Substance, Power; Relativity, Perpetually Perishing.
  916.  
  917. III. Analogy and Contrast with Philosophy of Organism.
  918.  
  919. IV. Hume and Process, Kant, Santayana.
  920.  
  921. V. Contrasted Procedures of Philosophy of Organism and Kant.
  922.  
  923.  
  924.  
  925. xxii Contents
  926.  
  927. Chapter VII. The Subjectivist Principle 157
  928.  
  929. SECTION
  930.  
  931. I. The Subjectivist Principle and the Sensationalist Principle;
  932. The Sensationalist Doctrine Combines Both; Locke, Hume,
  933. Kant; Statement of the Principles; The Three Premises
  934. for the Subjectivist Principle; Philosophy of Organism
  935. Denies the Two Principles and the Three Premises; Des-
  936. cartes; 'That Stone as Grey/ Substance and Quality, Organs
  937. of Sensation; Descartes' Subjectivist Modification; 'Percep-
  938. tion of that Stone as Grey'; Failure to Provide Revised
  939. Categories; Hume.
  940. II. Knowledge, Its Variations, Vaguenesses; Negative Perception
  941. the General Case, Consciousness is the Feeling of Negation,
  942. Novelty; Consciousness a Subjective Form, Only Present in
  943. Late Derivative Phases of Complex Integrations; Conscious-
  944. ness only Illuminates the Derivative Types of Objective
  945. Data, Philosophy Misled by Clearness and Distinctness.
  946.  
  947. III. Primitive Type of Physical Experience is Emotional; Vector
  948.  
  949. Transmission of Feeling, Pulses of Emotion, Wave-Length;
  950. Human Emotion is Interpreted Emotion, Not Bare Emo-
  951. tional Feeling.
  952.  
  953. IV. Decision Regulating Ingression of Eternal Objects, Old Meet-
  954.  
  955. ing New; The Three Phases of Feeling:! Conformal, Con-
  956. ceptual, Comparative; Eternal Objects and Subjective
  957. Forms; Continuity of the Phases; Category of Objective
  958. Unity.
  959. V. Reformed Subjectivist Principle is Another Statement of Prin-
  960. ciple of Relativity; Process is the Becoming of Experience;
  961. Hume's Principle Accepted, This Method only Errs in
  962. Detail; 'Law' for 'Causation' no Help; Modern Philosophy
  963. Uses Wrong Categories; Two Misconceptions:! (i) Vacuous
  964. Actuality, (ii) Inherence of Quality in Substance.
  965.  
  966. Chapter VIII. Symbolic Reference 168
  967.  
  968. I. Two Pure Modes of Perception, Symbolic Reference; Com-
  969. mon Ground, Integration, Originative Freedom, Error;
  970. Common Ground, Presented Locus, Geometrical Indistinct-
  971. ness in Mode of Causal Efficacy; Exceptions, Animal Body,
  972. Withness of Body.
  973. II. Common Ground, Common Sensa; Modern Empiricism,
  974. Make-Believe, Hume; Sensa Derived from Efficacy of Body;
  975. Projection.
  976. HI. Mistaken Primacy of Presentational Immediacy, Discussion,
  977. Causal Efficacy Primitive.
  978.  
  979.  
  980.  
  981. Contents xxiii
  982.  
  983. section
  984. IV, Further Discussion; Causation and Sense-Perception,
  985. V. Comparison of Modes; Integration in Symbolic Reference.
  986. VI. Principles of Symbolism, Language.
  987.  
  988. Chapter IX. The Propositions? 184
  989.  
  990. I. Impure Prehensions by Integration of Pure Conceptual and
  991. Pure Physical Prehensions; Physical Purposes and Propo-
  992. sitions Discriminated; Theory, Not Primarily for Judgment,
  993. Lures for Feeling; Objective Lure; Final Cause; General
  994. and Singular Propositions; Logical Subjects, Complex Pred-
  995. icate; Propositions True or False; Lure to Novelty; Felt
  996. 'Contrary' is Consciousness in Germ; Judgment and Enter-
  997. tainment; Graded Envisagement.
  998. II. Truth and Falsehood, Experiential Togetherness of Propo-
  999. sitions and Fact; Correspondence and Coherence Theory;
  1000. Propositions True or False, Judgments Correct or Incor-
  1001. rect or Suspended; Intuitive and Derivative Judgments;
  1002. Logic Concerned with Derivative Judgments; Error.
  1003.  
  1004. III. Systematic Background Presupposed by Each Proposition; Re-
  1005.  
  1006. lations, Indicative Systems of Relations; Propositions and
  1007. Indicative Systems; Illustration, Inadequacy of Words.
  1008.  
  1009. IV, Metaphysical Propositions; One and One Make Two,
  1010.  
  1011. V. Induction, Probability, Statistical Theory, Ground, Sampling,
  1012.  
  1013. Finite Numbers.
  1014. VI. Suppressed Premises in Induction, Presupposition of Defi-
  1015. nite Type of Actuality Requiring Definite Type of Envi-
  1016. ronment; Wider Inductions Invalid; Statistical Probability
  1017. within Relevant Environment.
  1018.  
  1019. VII. Objectification Samples Environment.*
  1020.  
  1021. VIII. Alternative Non-Statistical Ground; Graduated Appetitions,
  1022. Primordial Nature of God; Secularization of Concept of
  1023. God's Functions.
  1024.  
  1025. Chapter X. Process 208
  1026.  
  1027. I. Fluency and Permanence; Generation and Substance; Spa-
  1028. tialization; Two Kinds of Fluency:! Macroscopic and Micro-
  1029. scopic, from Occasion to Occasion and within Each Occa-
  1030. sion.
  1031. II. Concrescence, Novelty, Actuality; Microscopic Concrescence.
  1032. III. Three Stages of Microscopic Concrescence; Vector Charac-
  1033. ters Indicate Macroscopic Transition; Emotion, and Sub-
  1034. jective Form Generally, is Scalar in Microscopic Origina-
  1035. tion and is the Datum for Macroscopic Transition.
  1036.  
  1037.  
  1038.  
  1039. xxiv Contents
  1040.  
  1041. SECTION
  1042.  
  1043. IV. Higher Phases of Microscopic Concrescence.
  1044. V. Summary.
  1045.  
  1046.  
  1047.  
  1048. PART III
  1049. THE THEORY OF PREHENSIONS
  1050.  
  1051. Chapter I. The Theory of FEELiNGst 219
  1052.  
  1053. I. Genetic and Morphological Analysis; Genetic Consideration
  1054. is Analysis of the Concrescence, the Actual Entity Forma-
  1055. liter; Morphological Analysis is Analysis of the Actual
  1056. Entity as Concrete, Spatialized, Objective A
  1057. II. Finite Truth, Division into Prehensions; Succession of Phases,
  1058. Integral Prehensions in Formation; Five Factors: Subject,
  1059. Initial Data, Elimination, Objective Datum, Subjective
  1060. Form; Feeling is Determinate.
  1061.  
  1062. III. Feeling Cannot be Abstracted from Its Subject; Subject, Aim
  1063.  
  1064. at the Feeler, Final Cause, Causa Sui.
  1065.  
  1066. IV. Categories of Subjective Unity, of Objective Identity, of
  1067.  
  1068. Objective Diversity.
  1069.  
  1070. V. Category of Subjective Unity; The One Subject is the Final
  1071. End Conditioning Each Feeling, Episode in Self-Produc-
  1072. tion; Pre-established Harmony, Self-Consistency of a Prop-
  1073. osition, Subjective Aim; Category of Objective Identity,
  1074. One Thing has one R61e, No Duplicity, One Ground of
  1075. Incompatibility; Category of Objective Diversity, No Di-
  1076. verse Elements with Identity of Function, Another Ground
  1077. of Incompatibility.
  1078.  
  1079. VI. World as a Transmitting Medium; Explanation; Negative
  1080.  
  1081. Prehensions, with Subjective Forms.
  1082. VII. Application of the Categories.
  1083. VIII. Application (continued) A
  1084.  
  1085. IX. Nexus.
  1086.  
  1087. X. Subjective Forms; Classification of Feelings According to Data;
  1088. Simple Physical Feelings, Conceptual Feelings, Transmuted
  1089. Feelings; Subjective Forms not Determined by Data, Con-
  1090. ditioned by Them.
  1091.  
  1092. XL Subjective Form, Qualitative Pattern, Quantitative Pattern; In-
  1093. tensity; Audition of Sound.
  1094. XII. Prehensions not Atomic, Mutual Sensitivity; Indefinite Num-
  1095. ber of Prehensions; Prehensions as Components in the Sat-
  1096. isfaction and Their Genetic Growth; Justification of the
  1097.  
  1098.  
  1099.  
  1100. Contents xxv
  1101.  
  1102. section
  1103.  
  1104. Analysis of the Satisfaction, Eighth and Ninth Categories
  1105. of Explanation.
  1106.  
  1107. Chapter II. The Primary Feelings 236
  1108.  
  1109. I. Simple Physical Feeling, Initial Datum is one Actual Entity,
  1110. Objective Datum is one Feeling Entertained by that one
  1111. Actual Entity; Act of Causation, Objective Datum the
  1112. Cause, Simple Physical Feeling the Effect; Synonymously
  1113. 'Causal Feelings'; Primitive Act of Perception, Initial Datum
  1114. is Actual Entity Perceived, Objective Datum is the Per-
  1115. spective, In General not Conscious Perception; Reason for
  1116. 'Perspective'; Vector Transmission of Feeling, Re-enaction,
  1117. Conformal; Irreversibility of Time; Locke; Eternal Objects
  1118. Relational, Two- Way R61e, Vector-Transference, Reproduc-
  1119. tion, Permanence; Quanta of Feeling Transferred, Quantum-
  1120. Theory in Physics, Physical Memory; Atomism, Continuity,
  1121. Causation, Memory, Perception, Quality, Quantity, Ex-
  1122. tension.
  1123. II. Conceptual Feelings, Positive and Negative Prehensions; Cre-
  1124. ative Urge Dipolar; Datum is an Eternal Object; Exclu-
  1125. siveness of Eternal Objects as Determinants, Definiteness,
  1126. Incompatibility.
  1127.  
  1128. III. Subjective Form of Conceptual Prehension is Valuation; Inte-
  1129.  
  1130. gration Introduces Valuation into Impure Feelings, Inten-
  1131. siveness; Three Characteristics of Valuation: (i) Mutual
  1132. Sensitivity of Subjective Forms, (ii) Determinant of Pro-
  1133. cedure of Integration, (iii) Determinant of Intensive Em-
  1134. phasis.
  1135.  
  1136. IV. Consciousness is Subjective Form; Requires Its Peculiar Da-
  1137.  
  1138. tum; Recollection, Plato, Hume; Conscious Feelings always
  1139. Impure, Requires Integration of Physical and Conceptual
  1140. Feelings; Affirmation and Negative Contrast; Not all Im-
  1141. pure Feelings Conscious.
  1142.  
  1143. Chapter III. The Transmission of Feelings 244
  1144.  
  1145. I. Ontological Principle, Determination of Initiation of Feeling;
  1146. Phases of Concrescence; God, Inexorable Valuation, Sub-
  1147. jective Aim; Self-Determination Imaginative in Origin, Re-
  1148. enaction.
  1149. II. Pure Physical Feelings, Hybrid Physical Feelings; Hybrid Feel-
  1150. ings Transmuted into Pure Physical Feelings; Disastrous
  1151. Separation of Body and Mind Avoided; Hume's Principle,
  1152. Hybrid Feelings with God as Datum.
  1153.  
  1154.  
  1155.  
  1156. xxvi Contents
  1157.  
  1158. section
  1159.  
  1160. III. Application of First Categoreal Obligation: Supplementary
  1161.  
  1162. Phase Arising from Conceptual Origination; Application of
  1163. Fourth and Fifth Categoreal Obligations; Conceptual
  1164. Reversion; Ground of Identity, Aim at Contrast.
  1165.  
  1166. IV. Transmutation; Feeling a Nexus as One, Transmuted Physi-
  1167.  
  1168. cal Feeling; R61e of Impartial Conceptual Feeling in Trans-
  1169. mutation, Category of Transmutation, Further Explana-
  1170. tions; Conceptual Feelings Modifying Physical Feelings;
  1171. Negative Prehensions Important.
  1172. V. Subjective Harmony, the Seventh Categoreal Obligation.
  1173.  
  1174. Chapter IV. Propositions and Feelings 256
  1175.  
  1176. I. Consciousness, Propositional Feelings, Not Necessarily Con-
  1177. scious; Propositional Feeling is Product of Integration of
  1178. Physical Feeling with a Conceptual Feeling; Eternal Objects
  1179. Tell no Tales of Actual Occasions, Propositions are Tales
  1180. That Might be\ Told of Logical Subjects; Proposition, True
  1181. or False, Tells no Tales about Itself, Awaits Reasons; Con-
  1182. ceptual Feeling Provides Predicative Pattern, Physical Feel-
  1183. ing Provides Logical Subjects, Integration; Indication of
  1184. Logical Subjects, Element of Givenness Required for Truth
  1185. and Falsehood.
  1186. II. Proposition not Necessarily Judged, Propositional Feelings not
  1187. Necessarily Conscious; New Propositions Arise; Possible
  1188. Percipient Subjects within the 'Scope of a Proposition/
  1189.  
  1190. III. Origination of Propositional Feeling, Four (or Five) Stages,
  1191.  
  1192. Indicative Feeling, Physical Precognition, Predicative Pat-
  1193. tern (Predicate), Predicative Feeling; Propositional Feeling
  1194. Integral of Indicative and Predicative Feelings.
  1195.  
  1196. IV. Subjective Forms of Propositional Feelings, Dependent on
  1197.  
  1198. Phases of Origination; Case of Identity of Indicative Feel-
  1199. ing with the Physical Recognition, Perceptive Feelings;t
  1200. Case of Diversity, Imaginative Feelings; Distinction not
  1201. Necessarily Sharp-Cut; The Species of Perceptive Feelings:
  1202. Authentic, Direct Authentic, Indirect Authentic, Unau-
  1203. thentic; Tied Imagination.
  1204. V. Imaginative Feelings, Indicative Feeling and Physical Recog-
  1205. nition Diverse, Free Imagination; Subjective Form Depends
  1206. on Origination, Valuation rather than Consciousness; Lure
  1207. to Creative Emergence; Criticism of Physical Feelings,
  1208. Truth, Critical Conditions.
  1209. VI. Language, Its Functionjf Origination of the Necessary Train
  1210. of Feelings.
  1211.  
  1212.  
  1213.  
  1214. Contents xxvii
  1215.  
  1216. Chapter V. The Higher Phases of Experience 266
  1217.  
  1218. section
  1219.  
  1220. I. Comparative Feelings, Conscious Perceptions, Physical Pur-
  1221. poses; Physical Purposes More Primitive than Proposi-
  1222. tional Feelings.
  1223. II. Intellectual Feelings, Integration of Propositional Feeling with
  1224. Physical Feeling of a Nexus Including the Logical Subjects;
  1225. Category of Objective Identity, Affirmation-Negation Con-
  1226. trast; Consciousness is a Subjective Form.
  1227.  
  1228. III. Belief, Certainty, Locke, Immediate Intuition.
  1229.  
  1230. IV. Conscious Perception, Recapitulation of Origin; Direct and
  1231.  
  1232. Indirect Authentic Feelings, Unauthentic Feelings; Trans-
  1233. mutation; Perceptive Error, Novelty; Tests, Force and
  1234. Vivacity, Analysis of Origination; Tests Fallible.
  1235. V. Judgment, Yes-Form, No-Form, Suspense-Form; In Yes-Form
  1236. Identity of Patterns, In No-Form Diversity and Incompati-
  1237. bility, In Suspense-Form t Diversity and Compatibility; In-
  1238. tuitive Judgment, Conscious Perception.
  1239. VI. Affirmative Intuitive Judgment Analogous to Conscious Per-
  1240. ception, Difference Explained; Inferential Judgment; Diver-
  1241. gence from Locke's Nomenclature; Suspended Judgment.
  1242. VII. Physical Purposes, Primitive Type of Physical Feeling; Retain-
  1243. ing Valuation and Purpose, Eliminating Indeterminate-
  1244. ness of Complex Eternal Object; Responsive Re-enaction;
  1245. Decision.
  1246. VIII. Second Species of Physical Purposes, Reversion Involved;
  1247. Eighth Categoreal Obligation, Subjective Intensity; Imme-
  1248. diate Subject, Relevant Future; Balance, Conditions for
  1249. Contrast; Reversion as Condition for Balanced Contrast;
  1250. Rhythm, Vibration; Categoreal Conditions; Physical Pur-
  1251. poses and Propositional Feelings Compared.
  1252.  
  1253.  
  1254.  
  1255. PART IV
  1256. THE THEORY OF EXTENSION
  1257.  
  1258. Chapter I. Coordinate Division 283
  1259.  
  1260. I. Genetic Division is Division of the Concrescence, Coordinate
  1261. Division is Division of the Concrete; Physical Time Arises
  1262. in the Coordinate Analysis of the Satisfaction; Genetic
  1263. Process not the Temporal Succession; Spatial and Temporal
  1264. Elements in the Extensive Quantum; The Quantum is the
  1265. Extensive Region; Coordinate Divisibility; Subjective Unity
  1266.  
  1267.  
  1268.  
  1269. xxviii Contents
  1270.  
  1271. SECTION
  1272.  
  1273. Indivisible; Subjective Forms Arise from Subjective Aim;
  1274. World as a Medium, Extensively Divisible; Indecision as to
  1275. Selected Quantum.
  1276. II. Coordinate Divisions and Feelings; Mental Pole Incurably
  1277. One; Subjective Forms of Coordinate Divisions Depend on
  1278. Mental Pole, Inexplicable Otherwise; A Coordinate Division
  1279. is a Contrast, a Proposition, False, but Useful Matrix.
  1280.  
  1281. III. Coordinate Division, the World as an Indefinite Multiplicity;
  1282.  
  1283. Extensive Order, Routes of Transmission; External Exten-
  1284. sive Relationships, Internal Extensive Division, One Basic
  1285. Scheme; Pseudo Sub-organisms, Pseudo Super-organisms,
  1286. Professor de Laguna's 'Extensive Connection/
  1287.  
  1288. IV. Extensive Connection is the Systematic Scheme Underlying
  1289.  
  1290. Transmission of Feelings and Perspective; Regulative Con-
  1291. ditions; Descartes; Grades of Extensive Conditions, Dimen-
  1292. sions.
  1293. V. Bifurcation of Nature; Publicity and Privacy.
  1294. VI. Classification of Eternal Objects; Mathematical Forms, Sensa.
  1295. VII. Elimination of the Experient Subject, Concrescent Immediacy.
  1296.  
  1297. Chapter II. Extensive Connection 294
  1298.  
  1299. I. Extensive Connection, General Description.
  1300. II. Assumptions, i.e., Postulates, i.e.,* Axioms and Propositions
  1301. for a Deductive System.
  1302.  
  1303. III. Extensive Abstraction. Geometrical Elements, Points, Seg-
  1304.  
  1305. ments.
  1306.  
  1307. IV. Points, Regions, Loci; Irrelevance of Dimensions.
  1308.  
  1309. Chapter III. Flat Loci 302
  1310.  
  1311. I. Euclid's Definition of 'Straight Line/
  1312.  
  1313. II. Weakness of Euclidean Definition; Straight Line as Shortest
  1314. Distance, Dependence on Measurement; New Definition of
  1315. Straight Lines, Ovals.
  1316.  
  1317. III. Definition of Straight Lines, Flat Loci, Dimensions.
  1318.  
  1319. IV. Contiguity.
  1320.  
  1321. V. Recapitulation.
  1322.  
  1323. Chapter IV. Strains 310
  1324.  
  1325. I. Definition of a Strain, Feelings Involving Flat Loci among the
  1326. Forms of Definiteness of Their Objective Data; 'Seat' of a
  1327.  
  1328.  
  1329.  
  1330. Contents xxix
  1331.  
  1332. SECTION
  1333.  
  1334. Strain; Strains and Physical Behaviour; Electromagnetic
  1335. Occasions Involve Strains.
  1336. II. Presentational Immediacy Involves Strains; Withness of the
  1337. Body, Projection, Focal Region; Transmission of Bodily
  1338. Strains, Transmutation, Ultimate Percipient, Emphasis; Pro-
  1339. jection of the Sensa, Causal Efficacy Transmuted in Pre-
  1340. sentational Immediacy; Massive Simplification; Types of
  1341. Energy; Hume; Symbolic Transference, Physical Purpose.
  1342.  
  1343. III. Elimination of Irrelevancies, Massive Attention to Systematic
  1344.  
  1345. Order; Design of Contrasts; Importance of Contemporary
  1346. Independence; Advantage to Enduring Objects.
  1347.  
  1348. IV. Structural Systems, Discarding Individual Variations; Physi-
  1349.  
  1350. cal Matter Involves Strain-Loci.
  1351. V. The Various Loci Involved :t Causal Past, Causal Future, Con-
  1352. temporaries, Durations, Part of a Duration, Future of a
  1353. Duration, Presented Duration, Strain-Locus.
  1354.  
  1355. Chapter V. Measurement 322
  1356.  
  1357. I. Identification of Strain-Loci with Durations only Approximate;
  1358. Definitions Compared; Seat of Strain, Projectors; Strain-
  1359. Loci and Presentational Immediacy.
  1360. II. Strain-Locus Wholly Determined by Experient; Seat and Pro-
  1361. jectors Determine Focal Region; Animal Body Sole Agent
  1362. in the Determination; Vivid Display of Real Potentiality of
  1363. Contemporary World; New Definition of Straight Lines
  1364. Explains this Doctrine; Ways of Speech, Interpretation of
  1365. Direct Observation; Descartes' Inspectio. Realitas Objective,
  1366. Judicium.
  1367.  
  1368. III. Modern Doctrine of Private Psychological Fields; Secondary
  1369.  
  1370. Qualities, Sensa; Abandons Descartes' Realitas Objectiva;
  1371. Difficulties for Scientific Theory, AH Observation in Pri-
  1372. vate Psychological Fields; Illustration, Hume; Conclusion,
  1373. Mathematical Form, Presentational Immediacy in one
  1374. Sense Barren, in Another Sense has Overwhelming Signifi-
  1375. cance.
  1376.  
  1377. IV. Measurement Depends on Counting and on Permanence;
  1378.  
  1379. What Counted, What Permanent; Yard-Measure Perma-
  1380. nent, Straight; Infinitesimals no Explanation; Approximation
  1381. to Straightness, Thus Straightness Presupposed; Inches
  1382. Counted, Non-Coincident; Modern Doctrine is Possibility of
  1383. Coincidence, Doctrine Criticized; Coincidence is Test of
  1384. Congruence, Not Meaning; Use of Instrument Presupposes
  1385.  
  1386.  
  1387.  
  1388. xxx Contents
  1389.  
  1390. section
  1391.  
  1392. Its Self-Congruence: Finally all Measurement Depends on
  1393. Direct Intuition of Permanence of Untested Instrument;
  1394. Theory of Private Psychological Fields Makes Scientific
  1395. Measurement Nonsense.
  1396. V. Meaning of Congruence in Terms of Geometry of Straight
  1397. Lines; Systems of Geometry; Sets of Axioms: Equivalent
  1398. Sets, Incompatible Sets; Three Important Geometries :t El-
  1399. liptic Geometry, Euclidean Geometry, Hyperbolic Geome-
  1400. try; Two Definitions of a Plane; Characteristic Distinction
  1401. between the Three Geometries; Congruence Depends on
  1402. Systematic Geometry.
  1403. VI. Physical Measurement, Least Action, Presupposes Geometrical
  1404. Measurement; Disturbed by Individual Peculiarities; Phys-
  1405. ical Measurement Expressible in Terms of Differential
  1406. Geometry; Summary of Whole Argument.
  1407.  
  1408.  
  1409.  
  1410. PART V
  1411. FINAL INTERPRETATION
  1412.  
  1413. Chapter I. The Ideal Opposites 337
  1414.  
  1415. I. Danger to Philosophy is Narrowness of Selection; Variety of
  1416. Opposites :t Puritan Self-Restraint and Aesthetic Joy, Sor-
  1417. row and Joy; Religious Fervour and Sceptical Criticism,
  1418. Intuition and Reason.
  1419. II. Permanence and Flux, Time and Eternity.
  1420.  
  1421. III. Order as Condition for Excellence, Order as Stifling Excel-
  1422.  
  1423. lence; Tedium, Order Entering upon Novelty is Required;
  1424. Dominant Living Occasion is Organ of Novelty for Animal
  1425. Body.
  1426.  
  1427. IV. Paradox:! Craving for Novelty, Terror at Loss; Final Religious
  1428.  
  1429. Problem; Ultimate Evil is Time as 'Perpetually Perishing';
  1430. Final Opposites :t Joy and Sorrow, Good and Evil, Disjunc-
  1431. tion and Conjunction, Flux and Permanence, Greatness and
  1432. Triviality, Freedom and Necessity, God and the World;
  1433. These Pairs Given in Direct Intuition, except the Last Pair
  1434. Which is Interpretive.
  1435.  
  1436. Chapter II. God and the World 342
  1437.  
  1438. I. Permanence and Fiux, God as Unmoved Mover; Conceptions
  1439. of God:t Imperial Ruler, Moral Energy, Philosophical Prin-
  1440. ciple.
  1441. II. Another Speaker to Hume's Dialogues Concerningf Natural
  1442.  
  1443.  
  1444.  
  1445. Contents xxxi
  1446.  
  1447. SECTION
  1448.  
  1449. Religion; Primordial Nature Deficiently Actual, Neither
  1450. Love nor Hatred for Actualities, Quotation from Aristotle.
  1451.  
  1452. III. God's Nature Dipolar, Conceptual and Physical; This Physical
  1453.  
  1454. Nature Derived from the World; Two Natures Compared.
  1455.  
  1456. IV. God's Consequent Nature, Creative Advance Retaining Uni-
  1457.  
  1458. son of Immediacy, Everlastingness; Further Analysis, Ten-
  1459. derness, Wisdom, Patience; Poet of the World, Vision of
  1460. Truth, Beauty, Goodness.
  1461. V. Permanence and Flux, Relation of God to the World; Group
  1462. of Antitheses: God and the World Each the Instrument of
  1463. Novelty for the Other.
  1464. VI. Universe Attaining Self-Expression of Its Opposites.
  1465. VII. God as the Kingdom of Heaven; Objective Immortality At-
  1466. taining Everlastingness, Reconciliation of Immediacy with
  1467. Objective Immortality.
  1468.  
  1469. Index 353
  1470.  
  1471. Editors 7 Notes 389
  1472.  
  1473.  
  1474.  
  1475. PARTI
  1476. THE SPECULATIVE SCHEME
  1477.  
  1478.  
  1479.  
  1480. CHAPTER I
  1481. SPECULATIVE PHILOSOPHY
  1482.  
  1483. SECTION I
  1484.  
  1485. [4] This course of lectures is designed as an essay in Speculative Philos-
  1486. ophy. Its first task must be to define 'speculative philosophy/ and to de-
  1487. fend it as a method productive of important knowledge.
  1488.  
  1489. Speculative Philosophy is the endeavour to frame a coherent, logical,
  1490. necessary system of general ideas in terms of which every element of our
  1491. experience can be interpreted. By this notion of 'interpretation' I mean
  1492. that everything of which we are conscious, as enjoyed, perceived, willed,
  1493. or thought, shall have the character of a particular instance of the general
  1494. scheme. Thus the philosophical scheme should be coherent, logical, and,
  1495. in respect to its interpretation, applicable and adequate. Here 'applicable'
  1496. means that some items of experience are thus interpretable, and 'ade-
  1497. quate' means that there are no items incapable of such interpretation.
  1498.  
  1499. [5] 'Coherence,' as here employed, means that the fundamental ideas, in
  1500. terms of which the scheme is developed, presuppose each other so that in
  1501. isolation they are meaningless. This requirement does not mean that they
  1502. are definable in terms of each other; it means that what is indefinable in
  1503. one such notion cannot be abstracted from its relevance to the other
  1504. notions. It is the ideal of speculative philosophy that its fundamental no-
  1505. tions shall not seem capable of abstraction from each other. In other words,
  1506. it is presupposed that no entity can be conceived in complete abstraction
  1507. from the system of the universe, and that it is the business of speculative
  1508. philosophy to exhibit this truth. This character is its coherence.
  1509.  
  1510. The term 'logical' has its ordinary meaning, including 'logical' con-
  1511. sistency, or lack of contradiction, the definition of constructs in logical
  1512. terms, the exemplification of general logical notions in specific instances,
  1513. and the principles of inference. It will be observed that logical notions must
  1514. themselves find their places in the scheme of philosophic notions.
  1515.  
  1516. It will also be noticed that this ideal of speculative philosophy has its
  1517. rational side and its empirical side. The rational side is expressed by the
  1518. terms 'coherent' and 'logical/ The empirical side is expressed by the terms
  1519. 'applicable' and 'adequate.' But the two sides are bound together by
  1520. clearing away an ambiguity which remains in the previous explanation of
  1521. the term 'adequate.' The adequacy of the scheme over every item does not
  1522. mean adequacy over such items as happen to have been considered. It
  1523.  
  1524.  
  1525.  
  1526. 4 The Speculative Scheme
  1527.  
  1528. means that the texture of observed experience, as illustrating the philo-
  1529. sophic scheme, is such that all related experience must exhibit the same
  1530. texture. Thus the philosophic scheme should be 'necessary/ in the sense of
  1531. bearing in itself its own warrant of universality throughout all experience,
  1532. provided that we confine ourselves to that which communicates with im-
  1533. mediate matter of fact. But what does not so communicate is [6] unknow-
  1534. able, and the unknowable is unknown; x and so this universality defined by
  1535. 'communication' can suffice.
  1536.  
  1537. This doctrine of necessity in universality means that there is an essence
  1538. to the universe which forbids relationships beyond itself, as a violation of
  1539. its rationality. Speculative philosophy seeks that essence.
  1540.  
  1541. SECTION II
  1542.  
  1543. Philosophers can never hope finally to formulate these metaphysical
  1544. first principles. Weakness of insight and deficiencies of language stand in
  1545. the way inexorably. Words and phrases must be stretched towards a gen-
  1546. erality foreign to their ordinary usage; and however such elements of lan-
  1547. guage be stabilized as technicalities, they remain metaphors mutely ap-
  1548. pealing for an imaginative leap.
  1549.  
  1550. There is no first principle which is in itself unknowable, not to be cap-
  1551. tured by a flash of insight. But, putting aside the difficulties of language,
  1552. deficiency in imaginative penetration forbids progress in any form other
  1553. that that of an asymptotic approach to a scheme of principles, only de-
  1554. finable in terms of the ideal which they should satisfy.
  1555.  
  1556. The difficulty has its seat in the empirical side of philosophy. Our datum
  1557. is the actual world, including ourselves; and this actual world spreads itself
  1558. for observation in the guise of the topic of our immediate experience. The
  1559. elucidation of immediate experience is the sole justification for any
  1560. thought; and the starting-point* for thought is the analytic observation of
  1561. components of this experience. But we are not conscious of any clear-cut
  1562. complete analysis of immediate experience, in terms of the various details
  1563. which comprise its definiteness. We habitually observe by the method of -~
  1564. difference. Sometimes we see an elephant, and sometimes we do not. The
  1565. result is that an elephant, when present, is noticed. [7] Facility of observa-
  1566. tion depends on the fact that the object observed is important when
  1567. present, and sometimes is absent. ^
  1568.  
  1569. The metaphysical first principles can never fail of exemplification. We
  1570. can never catch the actual world taking a holiday from their sway. Thus,
  1571. for the discovery of metaphysics, the method of pinning down thought to
  1572. the strict systematization of detailed discrimination, already effected by
  1573. antecedent observation, breaks down. This collapse of the method of rigid
  1574. empiricism is not confined to metaphysics. It occurs whenever we seek the
  1575.  
  1576. 1 This doctrine is a paradox. Indulging in a species of false modesty, 'cautious'
  1577. philosophers undertake its definition.
  1578.  
  1579.  
  1580.  
  1581. Speculative Philosophy 5
  1582.  
  1583. larger generalities. In natural science this rigid method is the Baconian
  1584. method of induction, a method which, if consistently pursued, would have
  1585. left science where it found it. What Bacon omitted was the play of a
  1586. free imagination, controlled by the requirements of coherence and logic.
  1587. The true method of discovery is like the flight of an aeroplane. It starts
  1588. from the ground of particular observation; it makes a flight in the thin air
  1589. of imaginative generalization; and it again lands for renewed observation
  1590. rendered acute by rational interpretation. The reason for the success of
  1591. this method of imaginative rationalization is that, when the method of
  1592. difference fails, factors which are constantly present may yet be observed
  1593. under the influence of imaginative thought. Such thought supplies the
  1594. differences which the direct observation lacks. It can even play with in-
  1595. consistency; and can thus throw light on the consistent, and persistent,
  1596. elements in experience by comparison with what in imagination is incon-
  1597. sistent with them. The negative judgment is the peak of mentality. But
  1598. the conditions for the success of imaginative construction must be rigidly
  1599. adhered to. In the first place, this construction must have its origin in the
  1600. generalization of particular factors discerned in particular topics of human
  1601. interest; for example, in physics, or in physiology, or in psychology, or in
  1602. aesthetics, or in ethical beliefs, or in sociology, or in languages conceived
  1603. as storehouses of human experience. In [8] this way the prime requisite, that
  1604. anyhow there shall be some important application, is secured. The success
  1605. of the imaginative experiment is always to be tested by the applicability
  1606. of its results beyond the restricted locus from which it originated. In de-
  1607. fault of such extended application, a generalization started from physics,
  1608. for example, remains merely an alternative expression of notions appli-
  1609. cable to physics. The partially successful philosophic generalization will,
  1610. if derived from physics, find applications in fields of experience beyond
  1611. physics. It will enlighten observation in those remote fields, so that gen-
  1612. eral principles can be discerned as in process of illustration, which in
  1613. the absence of the imaginative generalization are obscured by their per-
  1614. sistent exemplification.
  1615.  
  1616. Thus the first requisite is to proceed by the method of generalization
  1617. so that certainly there is some application; and the test of some success
  1618. is application beyond the immediate origin. In other words, some synop-
  1619. tic vision has been gained.
  1620.  
  1621. In this description of philosophic method, the term 'philosophic gen-
  1622. eralization' has meant 'the utilization of specific notions, applying to a
  1623. restricted group of facts, for the divination of the generic notions which
  1624. apply to all facts/
  1625.  
  1626. In its use of this method natural science has shown a curious mixture
  1627. of rationalism and irrationalism. Its prevalent tone of thought has been
  1628. ardently rationalistic within its own borders, and dogmatically irrational
  1629. beyond those borders. In practice such an attitude tends to become a dog-
  1630. matic denial that there are any factors in the world not fully expressible
  1631.  
  1632.  
  1633.  
  1634. 6 The Speculative Scheme
  1635.  
  1636. in terms of its own primary notions devoid of further generalization. Such
  1637. a denial is the self-denial of thought.
  1638.  
  1639. The second condition for the success of imaginative construction is un-
  1640. flinching pursuit of the two rationalistic ideals, coherence and logical per-
  1641. fection.
  1642.  
  1643. Logical perfection does not here require any detailed [9] explanation. An
  1644. example of its importance is afforded by the role of mathematics in the re-
  1645. stricted field of natural science. The history of mathematics exhibits the
  1646. generalization of special notions observed in particular instances. In any
  1647. branches of mathematics, the notions presuppose each other. It is a re-
  1648. markable characteristic of the history of thought that branches of math-
  1649. ematics,! developed under the pure imaginative impulse, thus controlled,
  1650. finally receive their important application. Time may be wanted. Conic
  1651. sections had to wait for eighteen hundred years. In more recent years, the
  1652. theory of probability, the theory of tensors, the theory of matrices are
  1653. cases in point.
  1654.  
  1655. The requirement of coherence is the great preservative of rationalistic
  1656. sanity. But the validity of its criticism is not always admitted. If we con-
  1657. sider philosophical controversies, we shall find that disputants tend to re-
  1658. quire coherence from their adversaries, and to grant dispensations to them-
  1659. selves. It has been remarked that a system of philosophy is never refuted;
  1660. it is only abandoned. The reason is that logical contradictions, except as
  1661. temporary slips of the mind— plentiful, though temporary— are the most
  1662. gratuitous of errors; and usually they are trivial. Thus, after criticism, sys-
  1663. tems do not exhibit mere illogicalities. They suffer from inadequacy and
  1664. incoherence. Failure to include some obvious elements of experience in
  1665. the scope of the system is met by boldly denying the facts. Also while a
  1666. philosophical system retains any charm of novelty, it enjoys a plenary
  1667. indulgence for its failures in coherence. But after a system has acquired
  1668. orthodoxy, and is taught with authority, it receives a sharper criticism.
  1669. Its denials and its incoherences are found intolerable, and a reaction sets
  1670. in.
  1671.  
  1672. Incoherence is the arbitrary disconnection of first principles. In modern
  1673. philosophy Descartes' two kinds of substance, corporeal and mental, illus-
  1674. trate incoherence. There is, in Descartes 7 philosophy, no reason why there
  1675. should not be a one-substance world, only corporeal, or [10] a one-substance
  1676. world, only mental. According to Descartes, a substantial individual 're-
  1677. quires nothing but itself in order to exist/ Thus this system makes a virtue
  1678. of its incoherence. But,t on the other hand, the facts seem connected, while
  1679. Descartes' system does not; for example, in the treatment of the body-
  1680. mind problem. The Cartesian system obviously says something that is
  1681. true. But its notions are too abstract to penetrate into the nature of things.
  1682.  
  1683. t
  1684. The attraction of Spinoza's philosophy lies in its modification of Des-
  1685. cartes' position into greater coherence. He starts with one substance,
  1686.  
  1687.  
  1688.  
  1689. Speculative Philosophy 7
  1690.  
  1691. causa sui, and considers its essential attributes and its individualized modes,
  1692. i.e., the 'affectiones substantial The gap in the system is the arbitrary in-
  1693. troduction of the 'modes/ And yet, a multiplicity of modes is a fixed
  1694. requisite, if the scheme is to retain any direct relevance to the many oc-
  1695. casions in the experienced world.
  1696.  
  1697. The philosophy of organism is closely allied to Spinoza's scheme of
  1698. thought. But it differs by the abandonment of the subject-predicate forms
  1699. of thought, so far as concerns the presupposition that this form is a direct
  1700. embodiment of the most ultimate characterization of fact. The result is
  1701. that the 'substance-quality' concept is avoided; and that morphological
  1702. description is replaced by description of dynamic process. Also Spinoza's
  1703. 'modes' now become the sheer actualities; so that, though analysis of them
  1704. increases our understanding, it does not lead us to the discovery of any
  1705. higher grade of reality. The coherence, which the system seeks to preserve,
  1706. is the discovery that the process, or concrescence, of any one actual entity
  1707. involves the other actual entities among its components. In this way the
  1708. obvious solidarity of the world receives its explanation.
  1709.  
  1710. In all philosophic theory there is an ultimate which is actual in virtue
  1711. of its accidents. It is only then capable of characterization through its
  1712. accidental" embodiments, and apart from these accidents is devoid of [11]
  1713. actuality. In the philosophy of organism this ultimate is termed 'creativity';
  1714. and God is its primordial, non-temporal accident.* In monistic philoso-
  1715. phies, Spinoza's or absolute idealism, this ultimate is God, who is also
  1716. equivalently termed 'The Absolute.' In such monistic schemes, the ulti-
  1717. mate is illegitimately allowed a final, 'eminent' reality, beyond that ascribed
  1718. to any of its accidents. In this general position the philosophy of organ-
  1719. ism seems to approximate more to some strains of Indian, or Chinese,
  1720. thought, than to western Asiatic, or European, thought. One side makes
  1721. process ultimate; the other side makes fact ultimate.
  1722.  
  1723. SECTION Hit
  1724.  
  1725. In its turn every philosophy will suffer a deposition. But the bundle
  1726. of philosophic systems expresses a variety of general truths about the
  1727. universe, awaiting coordination and assignment of their various spheres
  1728. of validity. Such progress in coordination is provided by the advance of
  1729. philosophy; and in this sense philosophy has advanced from Plato onwards.
  1730. According to this account of the achievement of rationalism, the chief
  1731. error in philosophy is overstatement. The aim at generalization is sound,
  1732. but the estimate of success is exaggerated. There are two main forms of
  1733. such overstatement. One form is what I have termed, f elsewhere, 2 the
  1734. 'fallacy of misplaced concreteness. 7 This fallacy consists in neglecting the
  1735. degree of abstraction involved when an actual entity is considered merely
  1736.  
  1737. 2 Cf. Science and the Modem World, Ch. III.
  1738.  
  1739.  
  1740.  
  1741. 8 The Speculative Scheme
  1742.  
  1743. so far as it exemplifies certain categories of thought. There are aspects of
  1744. actualities which are simply ignored so long as we restrict thought to these
  1745. categories. Thus the success of a philosophy is to be measured by its com-
  1746. parative avoidance of this fallacy, when thought is restricted within its
  1747. categories.
  1748.  
  1749. The other form of overstatement consists in a false estimate of logical
  1750. procedure in respect to certainty, and in respect to premises. Philosophy
  1751. has been haunted by the unfortunate notion that its method is dogmati-
  1752. cally to indicate premises which are severally clear, distinct, and [12] cer-
  1753. tain; and to erect upon those premises a deductive system of thought.
  1754.  
  1755. But the accurate expression of the final generalities is the goal of dis-
  1756. — cussion and not its origin. Philosophy has been misled by the example of
  1757. mathematics; and even in mathematics the statement of the ultimate
  1758. logical principles is beset with difficulties, as yet insuperable. 3 The verifi-
  1759. cation of a rationalistic scheme is to be sought in its general success, and
  1760. not in the peculiar certainty, or initial clarity, of its first principles. In
  1761. this connection the misuse of the ex absurdo argument has to be noted;
  1762. much philosophical reasoning is vitiated by it. The only logical conclusion
  1763. to be drawn, when a contradiction issues from a train of reasoning, is that
  1764. at least one of the premises involved in the inference is false. It is rashly
  1765. assumed without further question that the peccant premise can at once
  1766. be located. In mathematics this assumption is often justified, and phi-
  1767. losophers have been thereby misled. But in the absence of a well-defined
  1768. categoreal scheme of entities, issuing in a satisfactory metaphysical system,
  1769. every premise in a philosophical argument is under suspicion.
  1770.  
  1771. Philosophy will not regain its proper status until the gradual elaboration
  1772. of categoreal schemes, definitely stated at each stage of progress, is recog-
  1773. nized as its proper objective. There may be rival schemes, inconsistent
  1774. among themselves; each with its own merits and its own failures. It will
  1775. then be the purpose of research to conciliate the differences. Metaphysical
  1776. categories are not dogmatic statements of the obvious; they are tentative
  1777. formulations of the ultimate generalities.
  1778.  
  1779. If we consider any scheme of philosophic categories as one complex
  1780. assertion, and apply to it the logician's alternative, true or false, the answer
  1781. must be that the scheme is false. The same answer must be given to a like
  1782. ques- [13] tion respecting the existing formulated principles of any science.
  1783.  
  1784. The scheme is true with unformulated qualifications, exceptions, limita-
  1785. tions, and new interpretations in terms of more general notions. We do
  1786. not yet know how to recast the scheme into a logical truth. But the scheme
  1787. is a matrix from which true propositions applicable to particular circum-
  1788. stances can be derived. We can at present only trust our trained instincts
  1789.  
  1790. 3 Cf. Principia Mathematica, by Bertrand Russell and A. N. Whitehead, Vol.
  1791. I, Introduction and Introduction to the Second Edition. These introductory
  1792. discussions are practically due to Russell, and in the second edition wholly so.
  1793.  
  1794.  
  1795.  
  1796. Speculative Philosophy 9
  1797.  
  1798. as to the discrimination of the circumstances in respect to which the
  1799. scheme is valid.
  1800.  
  1801. The use of such a matrix is to argue from it boldly and with rigid logic.
  1802. The scheme should therefore be stated with the utmost precision and
  1803. definiteness, to allow of such argumentation. The conclusion of the argu-
  1804. ment should then be confronted with circumstances to which it should
  1805. apply.
  1806.  
  1807. The primary advantage thus gained is that experience is not interrogated
  1808. with the benumbing repression of common sense. The observation acquires
  1809. an enhanced penetration by reason of the expectation evoked by the con-
  1810. clusion of the argument. The outcome from this procedure takes one of
  1811. three forms: (i) the conclusion may agree with the observed facts; (ii) the
  1812. conclusion may exhibit general agreement, with disagreement in detail;
  1813. (iii) the conclusion may be in complete disagreement witht the facts.
  1814.  
  1815. In the first case, the facts are known with more adequacy and the ap-
  1816. plicability of the system to the world has been elucidated. In the second
  1817. case, criticisms of the observation of the facts and of the details of the
  1818. scheme are both required. The history of thought shows that false inter-
  1819. pretations of observed facts enter into the records of their observation.
  1820. Thus both theory, and received notions as to fact, are in doubt. In the
  1821. third case, a fundamental reorganization of theory is required either by
  1822. way of limiting it to some special province, or by way of entire abandon-
  1823. ment of its main categories of thought.
  1824.  
  1825. [14] After the initial basis of a rational life, with a civilized language, has
  1826. been laid, all productive thought has proceeded either by the poetic insight
  1827. of artists, or by the imaginative elaboration of schemes of thought capable
  1828. of utilization as logical premises. In some measure or other, progress is
  1829. always a transcendence of what is obvious.
  1830.  
  1831. Rationalism never shakes off its status of an experimental adventure.
  1832. The combined influences of mathematics and religion, which have so
  1833. greatly contributed to the rise of philosophy, have also had the unfortunate
  1834. effect of yoking it with static dogmatism. Rationalism is an adventure in
  1835. the clarification of thought, progressive and never final. But it is an ad-
  1836. venture in which even partial success has importance.
  1837.  
  1838. SECTION IV
  1839.  
  1840. The field of a special science is confined to one genus of facts, in the
  1841. sense that no statements are made respecting facts which lie outside that
  1842. genus. The very circumstance that a science has naturally arisen concerning
  1843. a set of facts secures that facts of that type have definite relations among
  1844. themselves which are very obvious to all mankind. The common obvious-
  1845. ness of things arises when their explicit apprehension carries immediate
  1846. importance for purposes of survival, or of enjoyment— that is to say, for
  1847. purposes of 'being' and of 'well-being/ Elements in human experience,
  1848.  
  1849.  
  1850.  
  1851. 10 The Speculative Scheme
  1852.  
  1853. singled out in this way, are those elements concerning which language is
  1854. copious and. within its limits, precise. The special sciences, therefore, deal
  1855. with topics which lie open to easy inspection and are readily expressed by
  1856. words.
  1857.  
  1858. The study of philosophy is a voyage towards the larger generalities.
  1859. For this reason in the infancy of science, when the main stress lay in the
  1860. discovery of the most general ideas usefully applicable to the subject-
  1861. matter in question, philosophy was not sharply distinguished from science.
  1862. To this day, a new science with any substantial novelty in its notions is
  1863. considered to be in some way [15] peculiarly philosophical. In their later
  1864. stages, apart from occasional disturbances, most sciences accept without
  1865. question the general notions in terms of which they develop. The main
  1866. stress is laid on the adjustment and the direct verification of more special
  1867. statements. In such periods scientists repudiate philosophy; Newton, justly
  1868. satisfied with his physical principles, disclaimed metaphysics.
  1869.  
  1870. The fate of Newtonian physics warns us that there is a development in
  1871. scientific first principles, and that their original forms can only be saved
  1872. by interpretations of meaning and limitations of their field of application-
  1873. interpretations and limitations unsuspected during the first period of
  1874. successful employment. One chapter in the history of culture is concerned
  1875. with the growth of generalities. In such a chapter it is seen that the older
  1876. generalities, like the older hills, are worn down and diminished in height,
  1877. surpassed by younger rivals.
  1878.  
  1879. Thus one aim of philosophy is to challenge the half-truths constituting
  1880. the scientific first principles. The systematization of knowledge cannot be
  1881. conducted in watertight compartments. All general truths condition each
  1882. other; and the limits of their application cannot be adequately defined
  1883. apart from their correlation by yet wider generalities. The criticism of
  1884. principles must chiefly take the form of determining the proper meanings
  1885. to be assigned to the fundamental notions of the various sciences, when
  1886. these notions are considered in respect to their status relatively to each
  1887. other. The determination of this status requires a generality transcending
  1888. any special subject-matter.
  1889.  
  1890. If we may trust the Pythagorean tradition, the rise of European philoso-
  1891. phy was largely promoted by the development of mathematics into a
  1892. science of abstract generality. But in its subsequent development the
  1893. method of philosophy has also been vitiated by the example of mathe-
  1894. matics. The primary method of mathematics is deduction; the primary
  1895. method of philosophy is descrip- \16] tive generalization. Under the in-
  1896. fluence of mathematics, deduction has been foisted onto philosophy as its
  1897. standard method, instead of taking its true place as an essential auxiliary
  1898. mode of verification whereby to test the scope of generalities. This mis-
  1899. apprehension of philosophic method has veiled the very considerable suc-
  1900. cess of philosophy in providing generic notions which add lucidity to our
  1901. apprehension of the facts of experience. The depositions of Plato, Aristotle,
  1902.  
  1903.  
  1904.  
  1905. Speculative Philosophy 11
  1906.  
  1907. Thomas Aquinas, Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, t Locke, Berkeley, Hume,
  1908. Kant, Hegel, merely mean that ideas which these men introduced into the
  1909. philosophic tradition must be construed with limitations, adaptations, and
  1910. inversions, either unknown to them, or even explicitly repudiated by them.
  1911. A new idea introduces a new alternative; and we are not less indebted to
  1912. a thinker when we adopt the alternative which he discarded. Philosophy
  1913. never reverts to its old position after the shock of a great philosopher.
  1914.  
  1915.  
  1916.  
  1917. SECTION V
  1918.  
  1919. Every science must devise its own instruments. The tool required for
  1920. philosophy is language. Thus philosophy redesigns language in the same
  1921. way that, in a physical science, pre-existing appliances are redesigned. It
  1922. is exactly at this point that the appeal to facts is a difficult operation. This
  1923. appeal is not solely to the expression of the facts in current verbal state-
  1924. ments. The adequacy of such sentences is the main question at issue. It
  1925. is true that the general agreement of mankind as to experienced facts is
  1926. best expressed in language. But the language of literature breaks down
  1927. precisely at the task of expressing in explicit form the larger generalities—
  1928. the very generalities which metaphysics seeks to express.
  1929.  
  1930. The point is that every proposition refers to a universe exhibiting some
  1931. general systematic metaphysical character. Apart from this background,
  1932. the separate entities which go to form the proposition, and the proposition
  1933. as a whole, are without determinate character. Nothing [17] has been de-
  1934. fined, because every definite entity requires a systematic universe to supply
  1935. its requisite status. Thus every proposition proposing a fact* must, in its
  1936. complete analysis, propose the general character of the universe required
  1937. for that fact. There are no self-sustained facts, floating in nonentity. This
  1938. doctrine, of the impossibility of tearing a proposition from its systematic
  1939. context in the actual world, is a direct consequence of the fourth and the
  1940. twentieth of the fundamental categoreal explanations which we shall be
  1941. engaged in expanding and illustrating. A proposition can embody partial
  1942. truth because it only demands a certain type of systematic environment,
  1943. which is presupposed in its meaning. It does not refer to the universe in
  1944. all its detail.
  1945.  
  1946. One practical aim of metaphysics is the accurate analysis of propositions;
  1947. not merely of metaphysical propositions, but of quite ordinary propositions
  1948. such as There is beef for dinner today/ and 'Socrates is mortal/ The one
  1949. genus of facts which constitutes the field of some special science requires
  1950. some common metaphysical presupposition respecting the universe. It is
  1951. merely credulous to accept verbal phrases as adequate statements of
  1952. propositions. The distinction between verbal phrases and complete propo-
  1953. sitions is one of the reasons why the logicians" rigid alternative, 'true or
  1954. false," is so largely irrelevant for the pursuit of knowledge.
  1955.  
  1956.  
  1957.  
  1958. 12 The Speculative Scheme
  1959.  
  1960. The excessive trust in linguistic phrases has been the well-known reason
  1961. vitiating so much of the philosophy and physics among the Greeks and
  1962. among the mediaeval thinkers who continued the Greek traditions. For
  1963. example John Stuart Mill writes:
  1964. They [the Greeks] t had great difficulty in distinguishing between
  1965. things which their language confounded, or in putting mentally to-
  1966. gether things which it distinguished,* and could hardly combine the
  1967. objects in nature into any classes but those which were made for
  1968. them by the popular phrases of their own country; or at least could
  1969. not help fancying those classes to be natural, and all others arbitrary
  1970. and artificial. Ac- [18] cordingly, scientific investigation among the
  1971. Greek schools of speculation and their followers in the Middle Ages,
  1972. was little more than a mere sifting and analysing of the notions at-
  1973. tached to common language. They thought that by determining the
  1974. meaning of words they could become acquainted with facts. 4
  1975. Mill then proceeds to quote from Whewell 5 a paragraph illustrating the
  1976. same weakness of Greek thought.
  1977.  
  1978. But neither Mill, nor Whewell, tracks this difficulty about language
  1979. down to its sources. They both presuppose that language does enunciate
  1980. well-defined propositions. This is quite untrue. Language is thoroughly in-
  1981. determinate, by reason of the fact that every occurrence presupposes some
  1982. systematic type of environment.
  1983.  
  1984. For example, the word 'Socrates/ referring to the philosopher, in one
  1985. sentence may stand for an entity presupposing a more closely defined back-
  1986. ground than the word 'Socrates/ with the same reference, in another sen-
  1987. tence. The word 'mortal' affords an analogous possibility. A precise lan-
  1988. guage must await a completed metaphysical knowledge.
  1989.  
  1990. The technical language of philosophy represents attempts of various
  1991. schools of thought to obtain explicit expression of general ideas pre-
  1992. supposed by the facts of experience. It follows that any novelty in meta-
  1993. physical doctrines exhibits some measure of disagreement with statements
  1994. of the facts to be found in current philosophical literature. The extent of
  1995. disagreement measures the extent of metaphysical divergence. It is, there-
  1996. fore, no valid criticism on one metaphysical school to point out that its
  1997. doctrines do not follow from the verbal expression of the facts accepted
  1998. by another school. The whole contention is that the doctrines in question
  1999. supply a closer approach to fully expressed propositions.
  2000.  
  2001. The truth itself is nothing else than how the composite natures of the
  2002. organic actualities of the world obtain ade- [19] quate representation in the
  2003. divine nature. Such representations compose the 'consequent nature 7 of
  2004. God, which evolves in its relationship to the evolving world without dero-
  2005.  
  2006.  
  2007.  
  2008. * tLogic, Book V, Ch. III.
  2009.  
  2010. 5 Cf. Whewell's History of the Inductive Sciences.
  2011.  
  2012.  
  2013.  
  2014. Speculative Philosophy 13
  2015.  
  2016. gation to the eternal completion of its primordial conceptual nature. In
  2017. this way the 'ontological principle' is maintained— since there can be no
  2018. determinate truth, correlating impartially the partial experiences of many
  2019. actual entities, apart from one actual entity to which it can be referred.
  2020. The reaction of the temporal world on the nature of God is considered
  2021. subsequently in Part V: it is there termed 'the consequent nature of God;
  2022.  
  2023. Whatever is found in 'practice' must lie within the scope of the meta-
  2024. physical description. When the description fails to include the 'practice/
  2025. the metaphysics is inadequate and requires revision. There can be no
  2026. appeal to practice to supplement metaphysics, so long as we remain con-
  2027. tented with our metaphysical doctrines. Metaphysics is nothing but the
  2028. description of the generalities which apply to all the details of practice.
  2029.  
  2030. No metaphysical system can hope entirely to satisfy these pragmatic
  2031. tests. At the best such a system will remain only an approximation to the
  2032. general truths which are sought. In particular, there are no precisely stated
  2033. axiomatic certainties from which to start. There is not even the language
  2034. in which to frame them. The only possible procedure is to start from verbal
  2035. expressions which, when taken by themselves with the current meaning of
  2036. their words, are ill-defined and ambiguous. These are not premises to be
  2037. immediately reasoned from apart from elucidation by further discussion;
  2038. they are endeavours to state general principles which will be exemplified
  2039. in the subsequent description of the facts of experience. This subsequent
  2040. elaboration should elucidate the meanings to be assigned to the words
  2041. and phrases employed. Such meanings are incapable of accurate appre-
  2042. hension apart from a correspondingly accurate apprehension of the meta-
  2043. physical background which the [20] universe provides for them. But no lan-
  2044. guage can be anything but elliptical, requiring a leap of the imagination to
  2045. understand its meaning in its relevance to immediate experience. The posi-
  2046. tion of metaphysics in the development of culture cannot be understood
  2047. without remembering that no verbal statement is the adequate expression
  2048. of a proposition.
  2049.  
  2050. An old established metaphysical system gains a false air of adequate
  2051. precision from the fact that its words and phrases have passed into current
  2052. literature. Thus propositions expressed in its language are more easily
  2053. correlated to our flitting intuitions into metaphysical truth. When we trust
  2054. these verbal statements and argue as though they adequately analysed
  2055. meaning, we are led into difficulties which take the shape of negations of
  2056. what in practice is presupposed. But when they are proposed as first prin-
  2057. ciples they assume an unmerited air of sober obviousness. Their defect is
  2058. that the true propositions which they do express lose their fundamental
  2059. character when subjected to adequate expression. For example consider
  2060. the type of propositions such as The grass is green/ and 'The whale is
  2061. big/ This subject-predicate form of statement seems so simple, leading
  2062. straight to a metaphysical first principle; and yet in these examples it con-
  2063. ceals such complex, diverse meanings.
  2064.  
  2065.  
  2066.  
  2067. 14 The Speculative Scheme
  2068.  
  2069. SECTION VI
  2070.  
  2071. It has been an objection to speculative philosophy that it is over-
  2072. ambitious. Rationalism, it is admitted, is the method by which advance
  2073. is made within the limits of particular sciences. It is, however, held that
  2074. this limited success must not encourage attempts to frame ambitious
  2075. schemes expressive of the general nature of things.
  2076.  
  2077. One alleged justification of this criticism is ill-success: European thought
  2078. is represented as littered with metaphysical systems, abandoned and un-
  2079. reconciled.
  2080.  
  2081. Such an assertion tacitly fastens upon philosophy the old dogmatic test.
  2082. The same criterion would fasten ill- [21] success upon science. We no more
  2083. retain the physics of the seventeenth century than we do the Cartesian
  2084. philosophy of that century. Yet within limits, both systems express im-
  2085. portant truths. Also we are beginning to understand the wider categories
  2086. which define their limits of correct application. Of course, in that century,
  2087. dogmatic views held sway; so that the validity both of the physical notions,
  2088. and of the Cartesian notions, was misconceived. Mankind never quite
  2089. knows what it is after. When we survey the history of thought, and like-
  2090. wise the history of practice, we find that one idea after another is tried out,
  2091. its limitations defined, and its core of truth elicited. In application to the
  2092. instinct for the intellectual adventures demanded by particular epochs,
  2093. there is much truth in Augustine's rhetorical phrase, Securus judicat orbis
  2094. terrarum. At the very least, men do what they can in the way of system-
  2095. atization, and in the event achieve something. The proper test is not that
  2096. of finality, but of progress.
  2097.  
  2098. But the main objection, dating from the sixteenth century and receiving
  2099. final expression from Francis Bacon, is the uselessness of philosophic spec-
  2100. ulation. The position taken by this objection is that we ought to describe
  2101. detailed matter of fact, and elicit the laws with a generality strictly limited
  2102. to the systcmatization of these described details. General interpretation,
  2103. it is held, has no bearing upon this procedure; and thus any system of gen-
  2104. eral interpretation, be it true or false, remains intrinsically barren. Un-
  2105. fortunately for this objection, there are no brute, self-contained matters of
  2106. fact, capable of being understood apart from interpretation as an element
  2107. in a system. Whenever we attempt to express the matter of immediate ex-
  2108. perience, we find that its understanding leads us beyond itself, to its con-
  2109. temporaries, to its past, to its future, and to the universals in terms of
  2110. which its definiteness is exhibited. But such universals, by their very charac-
  2111. ter of universality, embody the potentiality of other facts with variant
  2112. types of definiteness. Thus [22] the understanding of the immediate brute
  2113. fact requires its metaphysical interpretation as an item in a world with some
  2114. systematic relation to it. When thought comes upon the scene, it finds
  2115. the interpretations as matters of practice. Philosophy does not initiate
  2116. interpretations. Its search for a rationalistic scheme is the search for more
  2117.  
  2118.  
  2119.  
  2120. Speculative Philosophy 15
  2121.  
  2122. adequate criticism, and for more adequate justification, of the interpre-
  2123. tations which we perforce employ. Our habitual experience is a complex
  2124. of failure and success in the enterprise of interpretation. If we desire a
  2125. record of uninterpreted experience, we must ask a stone to record its auto-
  2126. biography. Every scientific memoir in its record of the 'facts' is shot
  2127. through and through with interpretation. The methodology of rational
  2128. interpretation is the product of the fitful vagueness of consciousness. Ele-
  2129. ments which shine with immediate distinctness, in some circumstances,
  2130. retire into penumbral shadow in other circumstances, and into black dark-
  2131. ness on other occasions. And yet all occasions proclaim themselves as ac-
  2132. tualities within the flux of a solid world, demanding a unity of interpre-
  2133. tation.
  2134.  
  2135. Philosophy is the self-correction by consciousness of its own initial ex-
  2136. cess of subjectivity. Each actual occasion contributes to the circumstances
  2137. of its origin additional formative elements deepening its own peculiar
  2138. individuality. Consciousness is only the last and greatest of such elements
  2139. by which the selective character of the individual obscures the external
  2140. totality from which it originates and which it embodies. An actual in-
  2141. dividual, of such higher grade, has truck with the totality of things by
  2142. reason of its sheer actuality; but it has attained its individual depth of being
  2143. by a selective emphasis limited to its own purposes. The task of philosophy
  2144. is to recover the totality obscured by the selection. It replaces in rational
  2145. experience what has been submerged in the higher sensitive experience
  2146. and has been sunk yet deeper by the initial operations of consciousness
  2147. itself. The selectiveness of individual experience is moral so far as it con-
  2148. [23] forms to the balance of importance disclosed in the rational vision; and
  2149. conversely the conversion of the intellectual insight into an emotional force
  2150. corrects the sensitive experience in the direction of morality. The correc-
  2151. tion is in proportion to the rationality of the insight.
  2152.  
  2153. Morality of outlook is inseparably conjoined with generality of outlook.
  2154. The antithesis between the general good and the individual interest can be
  2155. abolished only when the individual is such that its interest is the general
  2156. good, thus exemplifying the loss of the minor intensities in order to find
  2157. them again with finer composition in a wider sweep of interest.
  2158.  
  2159. Philosophy frees itself from the taint of ineffectiveness by its close rela-
  2160. tions with religion and with science, natural and sociological. It attains its
  2161. chief importance by fusing the two, namely, religion and science, into one
  2162. rational scheme of thought. Religion should connect the rational gen-
  2163. erality of philosophy with the emotions and purposes springing out of
  2164. existence in a particular society, in a particular epoch, and conditioned by
  2165. particular antecedents. Religion is the translation of general ideas into
  2166. particular thoughts, particular emotions, and particular purposes; it is di-
  2167. rected to the end of stretching individual interest beyond its self-defeating
  2168. particularity. Philosophy finds religion, and modifies it; and conversely
  2169. religion is among the data of experience which philosophy must weave into
  2170.  
  2171.  
  2172.  
  2173. 16 The Speculative Scheme
  2174.  
  2175. its own scheme. Religion is an ultimate craving to infuse into the insistent
  2176. particularity of emotion that non-temporal generality which primarily be-
  2177. longs to conceptual thought alone. In the higher organisms the differences
  2178. of tempo between the mere emotions and the conceptual experiences pro-
  2179. duce a life-tedium, unless this supreme fusion has been effected. The two
  2180. sides of the organism require a reconciliation in which emotional experi-
  2181. ences illustrate a conceptual justification, and conceptual experiences find
  2182. an emotional illustration.
  2183.  
  2184. [24] This demand for an intellectual justification of brute experience has
  2185. also been the motive power in the advance of European science. In this
  2186. sense scientific interest is only a variant form of religious interest. Any sur-
  2187. vey of the scientific devotion to 'truth/ as an ideal, will confirm this state-
  2188. ment. There is, however, a grave divergence between science and religion
  2189. in respect to the phases of individual experience with which they are con-
  2190. cerned. Religion is centered upon the harmony of rational thought with
  2191. the sensitive reaction to the percepta from which experience originates.
  2192. Science is concerned with the harmony of rational thought with the per-
  2193. cepta themselves. When science deals with emotions, the emotions in
  2194. question are percepta and not immediate passions— other people's emotion
  2195. and not our own: at least our own in recollection, and not in immediacy.
  2196. Religion deals with the formation of the experiencing subject; whereas
  2197. science deals with the objects, which are the data forming the primary
  2198. phase in this experience. The subject originates from, and amid, given
  2199. conditions; science conciliates thought with this primary matter of fact;
  2200. and religion conciliates the thought involved in the process with the sensi-
  2201. tive reaction involved in that same process. The process is nothing else
  2202. than the experiencing subject itself. In this explanation it is presumed that
  2203. an experiencing subject is one occasion of sensitive reaction to an actual
  2204. world. Science finds religious experiences among its percepta; and religion
  2205. finds scientific concepts among the conceptual experiences to be fused with
  2206. particular sensitive reactions.
  2207.  
  2208. The conclusion of this discussion is, first, the assertion of the old doctrine
  2209. that breadth of thought reacting with intensity of sensitive experience
  2210. stands out as an ultimate claim of existence; secondly, the assertion that
  2211. empirically the development of self-justifying thoughts has been achieved
  2212. by the complex process of generalizing! from particular topics, of imagi-
  2213. natively schematizing the generalizations, and finally by renewed compari-
  2214. son [25] of the imagined scheme with the direct experience to which it
  2215. should apply.
  2216.  
  2217. There is no justification for checking generalization at any particular
  2218. stage. Each phase of generalization exhibits its own peculiar simplicities
  2219. which stand out just at that stage, and at no other stage. There are sim-
  2220. plicities connected with the motion of a bar of steel which are obscured
  2221. if we refuse to abstract from the individual molecules; and there are certain
  2222. simplicities concerning the behaviour of men which are obscured if we
  2223.  
  2224.  
  2225.  
  2226. Speculative Philosophy 17
  2227.  
  2228. refuse to abstract from the individual peculiarities of particular specimens.
  2229. In the same way. there are certain general truths, about the actual things
  2230. in the common world of activity, which will be obscured when attention
  2231. is confined to some particular detailed mode of considering them. These
  2232. general truths, involved in the meaning of every particular notion respect-
  2233. ing the actions of things, are the subject-matter* for speculative philosophy.
  2234.  
  2235. Philosophy destroys its usefulness when it indulges in brilliant feats of
  2236. explaining away. It is then trespassing with the wrong equipment upon
  2237. the field of particular sciences. Its ultimate appeal is to the general con-
  2238. sciousness of what in practice we experience. Whatever thread of presup-
  2239. position characterizes social expression throughout the various epochs of
  2240. rational societyt must find its place in philosophic theory. Speculative bold-
  2241. ness must be balanced by complete humility before logic, and before fact.
  2242. It is a disease of philosophy when it is neither bold nor humble, but
  2243. merely a reflection of the temperamental presuppositions of exceptional
  2244. personalities.
  2245.  
  2246. Analogously, we do not trust any recasting of scientific theory depend-
  2247. ing upon a single performance of an aberrant experiment, unrepeated. The
  2248. ultimate test is always widespread, recurrent experience; and the more
  2249. general the rationalistic scheme, the more important is this final appeal.
  2250.  
  2251. The useful function of philosophy is to promote the [26] most general
  2252. systematization of civilized thought. There is a constant reaction between
  2253. specialism and common sense. It is the part of the special sciences to
  2254. modify common sense. Philosophy is the welding of imagination and com-
  2255. mon sense into a restraint upon specialists, and also into an enlargement
  2256. of their imaginations. By providing the generic notions philosophy should
  2257. make it easier to conceive the infinite variety of specific instances which
  2258. rest unrealized in the womb of nature.
  2259.  
  2260.  
  2261.  
  2262. CHAPTER II
  2263. THE CATEGOREAL SCHEME i
  2264.  
  2265. SECTION I
  2266.  
  2267. [27] This chapter contains an anticipatory sketch of the primary notions
  2268. which constitute the philosophy of organism. The whole of the subsequent
  2269. discussion in these lectures has the purpose of rendering this summary
  2270. intelligible, and of showing that it embodies generic notions inevitably
  2271. presupposed in our reflective experience— presupposed, but rarely expressed
  2272. in explicit distinction. Four notions may be singled out from this sum-
  2273. mary, by reason of the fact that they involve some divergence from
  2274. antecedent philosophical thought. These notions are, that of an 'actual
  2275. entity/ that of a 'prehension,' that of a 'nexus/ and that of the 'ontological
  2276. principle/ Philosophical thought has made for itself difficulties by dealing
  2277. exclusively in very abstract notions, such as those of mere awareness, mere
  2278. private sensation, mere emotion, mere purpose, mere appearance, mere
  2279. causation. These are the ghosts of the old 'faculties/ banished from
  2280. psychology, but still haunting metaphysics. There can be no 'mere' to-
  2281. getherness of such abstractions. The result is that philosophical discussion
  2282. is enmeshed in the fallacy of 'misplaced concreteness.' x In the three no-
  2283. tions—actual entity, prehension, nexus— an endeavour has been made to
  2284. base philosophical thought upon the most concrete elements in our ex-
  2285. perience.
  2286.  
  2287. 'Actual entities'- also termed 'actual occasions'— are the final real things -
  2288. of which the world is made up. There is no going behind actual entities
  2289. to find anything \28] more real. They differ among themselves: God is an
  2290. actual entity, and so is the most trivial puff of existence in far-off empty
  2291. space. But, though there are gradations of importance, and diversities of
  2292. function, yet in the principles which actuality exemplifies all are on the
  2293. same level. The final facts are, all alike, actual entities; and these actual
  2294. entities are drops of experience, coi iplex and interdependent.
  2295.  
  2296. In its recurrence to the notion oi a plurality of actual entities the phi-
  2297. losophy of organism is through and through Cartesian. t The 'ontological
  2298. principle' broadens and extends a general principle laid down by John
  2299. Locke in his Essay (Bk. II, Ch. XXIII, Sect. 7),t when he asserts that
  2300. "power" is "c? great part of our complex ideas of substances "\ The notion
  2301.  
  2302. 1 Cf. my Science and the Modern World, Ch. III.
  2303. 18
  2304.  
  2305.  
  2306.  
  2307. The Categoreal Scheme 19
  2308.  
  2309. of 'substance' is transformed into that of 'actual entity'; and the notion
  2310. of 'power' is transformed into the principle that the reasons for things are
  2311. always to be found in the composite nature of definite actual entities—
  2312. in the nature of God for reasons of the highest absoluteness, and in the
  2313. nature of definite temporal actual entities for reasons which refer to a
  2314. particular environment. The ontological principle can be summarized as:
  2315. no actual entity, then no reason.
  2316.  
  2317. Each actual entity is analysable in an indefinite number of ways. In
  2318. some modes of analysis the component elements are more abstract than
  2319. in other modes of analysis. The analysis of an actual entity into 'pre-
  2320. hensions' is that mode of analysis which exhibits the most concrete ele-
  2321. ments in the nature of actual entities. This mode of analysis will be termed
  2322. the 'division' of the actual entity in question. Each actual entity is 'divis-
  2323. ible' in an indefinite number of ways, and each way of 'division' yields its
  2324. definite quota of prehensions. A prehension reproduces in itself the general
  2325. characteristics of an actual entitv: it is referent to an external world, and
  2326. in this sense will be said to have a 'vector character'; it involves emotion,
  2327. and purpose, and valuation, and causation. In fact, any characteristic of
  2328. an actual entity is reproduced [29] in a prehension. It might have been a
  2329. complete actuality; but, by reason of a certain incomplete partiality, a pre-
  2330. hension is only a subordinate element in an actual entity. A reference to
  2331. the complete actuality is required to give the reason why such a prehension
  2332. is what it is in respect to its subjective form. This subjective form is
  2333. determined by the subjective aim at further integration, so as to obtain
  2334. the 'satisfaction' of the completed subject. In other words, final causation
  2335. and atomism are interconnected philosophical principles.
  2336.  
  2337. With the purpose of obtaining a one-substance cosmology, 'prehensions'
  2338. are a generalization from Descartes' mental 'cogitations,' and from
  2339. Locke's 'ideas,' to express the most concrete mode of analysis applicable
  2340. to every grade of individual actuality. Descartes and Locke maintained a
  2341. two-substance ontology— Descartes explicitly, Locke by implication. Des-
  2342. cartes, the mathematical physicist, emphasized his account of corporeal
  2343. substance; and Locke, the physician and the sociologist, confined himself
  2344. to an account of mental substance. The philosophy of organism, in its
  2345. scheme for one type of actual entities, adopts the view that Locke's ac-
  2346. count of mental substance embodies, in a very special form, a more pene-
  2347. trating philosophic description than does Descartes' account of corporeal
  2348. substance. Nevertheless, Descartes' account must find its place in the
  2349. philosophic scheme. On the whole, this is the moral to be drawn from
  2350. the Monadologyt of Leibniz. His monads are best conceived as generaliza-
  2351. tions of contemporary notions of mentality. The contemporary notions
  2352. of physical bodies only enter into his philosophv subordinately and deriv-
  2353. atively. The philosophy of organism endeavours to hold the balance more
  2354. evenly. But it does start with a generalization of Locke's account of mental
  2355. operations.
  2356.  
  2357.  
  2358.  
  2359. 20 The Speculative Scheme
  2360.  
  2361. Actual entities involve each other by reason of their prehensions of each
  2362. other. There are thus real individual facts of the togetherness of actual
  2363. entities, which are real, individual, and particular, in the same sense in
  2364. [30] which actual entities and the prehensions are real, individual, and par-
  2365. ticular. Any such particular fact of togetherness among actual entities is
  2366. called a *nexus ? (plural form is written 'nexus'). The ultimate facts of im-
  2367. mediate actual experience are actual entities, prehensions, and nexus. All
  2368. else is, for our experience, derivative abstraction.
  2369.  
  2370. The explanatory purpose of philosophy is often misunderstood. Its
  2371. business is to explain the emergence of the more abstract things from the
  2372. more concrete things. It is a complete mistake to ask how concrete par-
  2373. ticular fact can be built up out of universals. The answer is, In no way/
  2374. The true philosophic question 2 is, How can concrete fact exhibit entities
  2375. abstract from itself and yet participated in by its own nature?
  2376.  
  2377. In other words, philosophy is explanatory of abstraction, and not of
  2378. concreteness. It is by reason of their instinctive grasp of this ultimate truth
  2379. that, in spite of much association with arbitrary fancifulness and atavistic
  2380. mysticism, types of Platonic philosophy retain their abiding appeal; they
  2381. seek the forms in the facts. Each fact is more than its forms, and each
  2382. form 'participates' throughout the world of facts. The definiteness of fact
  2383. is due to its forms; but the individual fact is a creature, and creativity is
  2384. the ultimate behind all forms, inexplicable by forms, and conditioned by
  2385. its creatures.
  2386.  
  2387.  
  2388.  
  2389. SECTION II
  2390.  
  2391. The Categories
  2392.  
  2393. , I. The Category of the Ultimate.
  2394.  
  2395. II. Categories of Existence.
  2396.  
  2397. III. Categories of Explanation.
  2398.  
  2399. IV. Categoreal Obligations.
  2400.  
  2401. It is the purpose of the discussion in these lectures to make clear the
  2402. meaning of these categories, their appli- [31] cability, and their adequacy.
  2403. The course of the discussion will disclose how very far they are from
  2404. satisfying this ideal.
  2405.  
  2406. Every entity should be a specific instance of one category of existence,
  2407. every explanation should be a specific instance of categories of explanation,
  2408. and every obligation should be a specific instance of categoreal obliga-
  2409.  
  2410.  
  2411.  
  2412. 2 In this connection I may refer to the second chapter of my book The Princi-
  2413. ple of Relativity, Cambridge University Press, t 1922.
  2414.  
  2415.  
  2416.  
  2417. The Categoreal Scheme 21
  2418.  
  2419. tions. The Category^ of the Ultimate expresses the general principle pre-
  2420. supposed in the three more special categories.
  2421.  
  2422.  
  2423.  
  2424. The Category of the Ultimate
  2425.  
  2426. 'Creativity/ 'many/ 'one' are the ultimate notions involved in the mean-
  2427. ing of the synonymous terms 'thing/ 'being/ 'entity/ These three notions
  2428. complete the Category of the Ultimate and are presupposed in all the
  2429. more special categories.
  2430.  
  2431. The term "'one* does not stand for 'the integral number one/ which is
  2432. a complex special notion. It stands for the general idea underlying alike
  2433. the indefinite article 'a or an/ and the definite article 'the/ and the demon-
  2434. stratives 'this or that/ and the relatives 'which or what or how. 7 It stands
  2435. for the singularity of an entity. The term 'many' presupposes the term
  2436. 'one/ and the term 'one' presupposes the term 'many/ The term 'many'
  2437. conveys the notion of 'disjunctive diversity'; this notion is an essential*
  2438. element in the concept of 'being/ There are many 'beings' in disjunctive
  2439. diversity.
  2440.  
  2441. 'Creativity* is the universal of universals characterizing ultimate matter
  2442. of fact. It is that ultimate principle by which the many, which are the*
  2443. universe disjunctively, become the one actual occasion, which is the uni-
  2444. verse conjunctively. It lies in the nature of things that the many enter
  2445. into complex unity.
  2446.  
  2447. 'Creativity' is the principle of novelty. An actual occasion is a novel
  2448. entity diverse from any entity in the 'many' which it unifies. Thus 'creativ-
  2449. ity' introduces novelty into the content of the many, which are the [32]
  2450. universe disjunctively. The 'creative advance' is the application of this ul-
  2451. timate principle of creativity to each novel situation which it originates.
  2452.  
  2453. 'Together' is a generic term covering the various special ways in which
  2454. various sorts of entities are 'together' in any one actual occasion. Thus
  2455. 'together' presupposes the notions 'creativity/ 'many/ 'one/ 'identity' and
  2456. 'diversity/ The ultimate metaphysical principle is the advance from dis-
  2457. junction to conjunction, creating a novel entity other than the entities
  2458. given in disjunction. The novel entity is at once the togetherness of the
  2459. 'many' which it finds, and also it is one among the disjunctive 'many'
  2460. which it leaves; it is a novel entity, disjunctively among the many entities
  2461. which it synthesizes. The many become one, and are increased by one.
  2462. In their natures, entities are disjunctively 'many' in process of passage into
  2463. conjunctive unity. This Category of the Ultimate replaces Aristotle's
  2464. category of 'primary substance/
  2465.  
  2466. Thus the 'production of novel togetherness' is the ultimate notion em-
  2467. bodied in the term 'concrescence/ These ultimate notions of 'production
  2468. of novelty' and of 'concrete togetherness' are inexplicable either in terms of
  2469. higher universals or in terms of the components participating in the con-
  2470.  
  2471.  
  2472.  
  2473. 22 The Speculative Scheme
  2474.  
  2475. crescence. The analysis of the components abstracts from the concrescence.
  2476. The sole appeal is to intuition.
  2477.  
  2478. The Categories of Existence
  2479.  
  2480. There are eight Categories of Existence:
  2481.  
  2482. (i) Actual Entities (also termed Actual Occasions), or Final Realities,
  2483. or Res Verae.
  2484.  
  2485. (ii) Prehensions, or Concrete Facts of Relatedness.
  2486.  
  2487. (iii) Nexus (plural of Nexus), or Public Matters of Fact.
  2488.  
  2489. (iv) Subjective Forms, or Private Matters of Fact.
  2490.  
  2491. (v) Eternal Objects, or Pure Potentials for the Specific Determination
  2492. of Fact, or Forms of Definiteness.
  2493.  
  2494. (vi) Propositions, or Matters of Fact in Potential [33] Determination, or
  2495. Impure Potentials for the Specific Determination of Matters of Fact, or
  2496. Theories.
  2497.  
  2498. (vii) Multiplicities, or Pure Disjunctions of Diverse Entities.
  2499.  
  2500. (viii) Contrasts, or Modes of Synthesis of Entities in one Prehension,
  2501. or Patterned Entities. t
  2502.  
  2503. Among these eight categories of existence, actual entities and eternal
  2504. objects stand out with a certain extreme finality. The other types of exis-
  2505. tence have a certain intermediate character. The eighth category includes
  2506. an indefinite progression of categories, as we proceed from 'contrasts' to
  2507. 'contrasts of contrasts/ and on indefinitely to higher grades of contrasts.
  2508.  
  2509. The Categories of Explanation
  2510.  
  2511. There are twenty-seven Categories of Explanation:
  2512.  
  2513. (i) That the actual world is a process, and that the process is the be-
  2514. coming of actual entities. Thus actual entities are creatures; they are also
  2515. termed 'actual occasions/
  2516.  
  2517. (ii) That in the becoming of an actual entity, the potential unity of
  2518. many entities in disjunctive diversity*— actual and non-actual— acquires
  2519. the real unity of the one actual entity; so that the actual entity is the real
  2520. concrescence of many potentials.
  2521.  
  2522. (iii) That in the becoming of an actual entity, novel prehensions, nexus,
  2523. subjective forms, propositions, multiplicities, and contrasts, also become;
  2524. but there are no novel eternal objects.
  2525.  
  2526. (iv) That the potentiality for being an element in a real concrescence*
  2527. of many entities into one actuality! is the one general metaphysical char-
  2528. acter attaching to all entities, actual and non-actual; and that every item
  2529. in its universe is involved in each concrescence. In other words, it belongs
  2530. to the nature of a 'being' that it is a potential for every 'becoming/ This
  2531. is the 'principle of relativity/
  2532.  
  2533. (v) That no two actual entities originate from an iden- \34] tical uni-
  2534. verse; though the difference between the two universes only consists in
  2535.  
  2536.  
  2537.  
  2538. The Categoreal Scheme 23
  2539.  
  2540. some actual entities, included in one and not in the other, and in the sub-
  2541. ordinate entities which each actual entity introduces into the world. The
  2542. eternal objects are the same for all actual entities. The nexus of actual
  2543. entities in the universe correlate to a concrescencef is termed 'the actual
  2544. world' correlate to that concrescence.
  2545.  
  2546. (vi) That each entity in the universe of a given concrescence can, so far
  2547. as its own nature is concerned, be implicated in that concrescence in one
  2548. or other of many modes; but in fact it is implicated only in one mode:
  2549. that the particular mode of implication is only rendered fully determinate
  2550. by that concrescence, though it is conditioned by the correlate universe.
  2551. This indetermination, rendered determinate in the real concrescence, is
  2552. the meaning of 'potentiality.' It is a conditioned indetermination, and is
  2553. therefore called a 'real potentiality/
  2554.  
  2555. (vii) That an eternal object can be described only in terms of its poten-
  2556. tiality for 'ingression' into the becoming of actual entities; and that its
  2557. analysis only discloses other eternal objects. It is a pure potential. The
  2558. term 'ingression' refers to the particular mode in which the potentiality of
  2559. an eternal object is realized in a particular actual entity, contributing to
  2560. the definiteness of that actual entity.
  2561.  
  2562. (viii) That two descriptions are required for an actual entity: (a) one
  2563. which is analytical of its potentiality for 'objectiflcation' in the becoming
  2564. of other actual entities, and (b) another which is analytical of the process
  2565. which constitutes its own becoming.
  2566.  
  2567. The term 'objectification' refers to the particular mode in which the
  2568. potentiality of one actual entity is realized in another actual entity.
  2569.  
  2570. (ix) That how an actual entity becomes constitutes what that actual
  2571. entity is;t so that the two descriptions of an actual entity are not inde-
  2572. pendent. Its 'being' is [35] constituted by its 'becoming; This is the 'prin-
  2573. ciple of process/
  2574.  
  2575. (x) That the first analysis of an actual entity, into its most concrete
  2576. elements, discloses it to be a concrescence of prehensions, which have
  2577. originated in its process of becoming. All further analysis is an analysis
  2578. of prehensions. Analysis in terms of prehensions is termed 'division/
  2579.  
  2580. (xi) That every prehension consists of three factors: (a) the 'subject'
  2581. which is prehending, namely, the actual entity in which that prehension-
  2582. is a concrete element; (b) the 'datum' which is prehended; (c) the 'sub-
  2583. jective form' which is how that subject prehends that datum.
  2584.  
  2585. Prehensions of actual entities— i.e., prehensions whose data involve
  2586. actual entities — are termed 'physical prehensions'; and prehensions of
  2587. eternal objects are termed 'conceptual prehensions/ Consciousness is not
  2588. necessarily involved in the subjective forms of either type of prehension.
  2589.  
  2590. (xii) That there are two species of prehensions: (a) 'positive prehen-
  2591. sions' which are termed 'feelings,' and (b) 'negative prehensions' which
  2592. are said to 'eliminate from feeling.' Negative prehensions also have sub-
  2593. jective forms. A negative prehension holds its datum as inoperative in the
  2594.  
  2595.  
  2596.  
  2597. 24 The Speculative Scheme
  2598.  
  2599. progressive concrescence of prehensions constituting the unity of the
  2600. subject,
  2601.  
  2602. (xiii) That there are many species of subjective forms, such as emotions,
  2603. valuations, purposes, adversions, aversions, consciousness, etc.
  2604.  
  2605. (xiv) That a nexus is a set of actual entities in the unity of the related-
  2606. ness constituted by their prehensions of each other, or— what is the same
  2607. thing conversely expressed— constituted by their objectifications in each
  2608. other.
  2609.  
  2610. (xv) That a proposition is the unity of. certain actual entities in their
  2611. potentiality for forming a nexus, with its potential relatedness partially
  2612. defined by certain eternal objects which have the unity of one complex
  2613. eternal [36] object. The actual entities involved are termed the 'logical sub-
  2614. jects/ the complex eternal object is the 'predicate/
  2615.  
  2616. (xvi) That a multiplicity consists of many entities, and its unity is con-
  2617. stituted by the fact that all its constituent entities severally satisfy at least
  2618. one condition which no other entity satisfies.
  2619.  
  2620. Every statement about a particular multiplicity can be expressed as a
  2621. statement referent either (a) to all its members severally, or (b) to an
  2622. indefinite some of its members severally, or (c) as a denial of one of these
  2623. statements. Any statement, incapable of being expressed in this form, is
  2624. not a statement about a multiplicity, though it may be a statement about
  2625. an entity closely allied to some multiplicity, i.e., systematically allied to
  2626. each member of some multiplicity.
  2627.  
  2628. (xvii) That whatever is a datum for a feeling has a unity as felt Thus
  2629. the many components of a complex datum have a unity: this unity is a
  2630. 'contrast' of entities. In a sense this means that there are an endless num-
  2631. ber of categories of existence, since the synthesis of entities into a contrast
  2632. in general produces a new existential type. For example, a proposition is,
  2633. in a sense, a 'contrast/ For the practical purposes of 'human understand-
  2634. ing/ it is sufficient to consider a few basic types of existence, and to lump
  2635. the more derivative types together under the heading of 'contrasts/ The
  2636. most important of such 'contrasts' is the 'affirmation-negation' contrast
  2637. in which a proposition and a nexus obtain synthesis in one datum, the
  2638. members of the nexus being the 'logical subjects' of the proposition.
  2639.  
  2640. (xviii) That every condition to which the process of becoming conforms
  2641. in any particular instance! has its reason either in the character of some
  2642. actual entity in the actual world of that concrescence, or in the character
  2643. of the subject which is in process of concrescence. This category of ex-
  2644. planation is termed the 'ontological principle.' It could also be termed the
  2645. 'principle of efficient, [37] and final, causation/ This ontological principle
  2646. means that actual entities are the only reasons; so that to search for a
  2647. reason is to search for one or more actual entities. It follows that any
  2648. condition to be satisfied by one actual entity in its process expresses a fact
  2649. either about the 'real internal constitutions' of some other actual entities,
  2650. or about the 'subjective aim' conditioning that process.
  2651.  
  2652.  
  2653.  
  2654. The Categoreal Scheme 25
  2655.  
  2656. The phrase 'real internal constitution' is to be found in Locke's Essay
  2657. Concerning Human Understanding (III, III, 15): "And thus the real
  2658. internal (but generally in substances unknown) constitution of things,
  2659. whereon their discoverable qualities depend, may be called their 'es-
  2660. sence/ " Also the terms 'prehension' and 'feeling' are to be compared with
  2661. the various significations of Locke's term 'idea.' But they are adopted as
  2662. more general and more neutral terms than 'idea' as used by Locke, who
  2663. seems to restrict them to conscious mentality. Also the ordinary logical
  2664. account of 'propositions' expresses only a restricted aspect of their role in
  2665. the universe, namely, when they are the data of feelings whose subjective
  2666. forms are those of judgments. It is an essential doctrine in the philosophy
  2667. of organism that the primary function of a proposition is to be relevant as
  2668. a lure for feeling. For example, some propositions are the data of feelings
  2669. with subjective forms such as to constitute those feelings to be the enjoy-
  2670. ment of a joke. Other propositions are felt with feelings whose subjective
  2671. forms are horror, disgust, or indignation. The 'subjective aim,' which con-
  2672. trols the becoming of a subject, is that subject feeling a proposition with
  2673. the subjective form of purpose to realize it in that process of self-creation.
  2674.  
  2675. (xix) That the fundamental types of entities are actual entities, and
  2676. eternal objects; and that the other types of entities only express how all
  2677. entities of the two fundamental types are in community with each other,
  2678. in the actual world.
  2679.  
  2680. [38] (xx) That to 'function' means to contribute determination to the
  2681. actual entities in the nexus of some actual world. Thus the determinaie-
  2682. ness and self-identity of one entity cannot be abstracted from the com-
  2683. munity of the diverse functionings of all entities. 'Determination' is an-
  2684. alysable into 'definiteness' and 'position,' where 'definiteness't is the illus-
  2685. tration of select eternal objects, and 'position' is relative status in a nexus
  2686. of actual entities.
  2687.  
  2688. (xxi) An entity is actual, when it has significance for itself. By this it is
  2689. meant that an actual entity functions in respect to its own determination.
  2690. Thus an actual entity combines self-identity with self-diversity.
  2691.  
  2692. (xxii) That an actual entity by functioning in respect to itself plays
  2693. diverse roles in self-formation without losing its self-identity. It is self-
  2694. creative: and in its process of creation transforms its diversity of roles into
  2695. one coherent role. Thus 'becoming' is the transformation of incoherence
  2696. into coherence, and in each particular instance ceases with this attainment.
  2697.  
  2698. (xxiii) That this self-functioning is the real internal constitution of an
  2699. actual entity. It is the 'immediacy' of the actual entity. An actual entity
  2700. is called the 'subject' of its own immediacy.
  2701.  
  2702. (xxiv) The functioning of one actual entity in the self-creation of an-
  2703. other actual entity is the 'objectification' of the former for the latter actual
  2704. entity. The functioning of an eternal object in the self-creation of an ac-
  2705. tual entity is the 'ingression' of the eternal object in the actual entity.
  2706.  
  2707. (xxv) The final phase in the process of concrescence, constituting an
  2708.  
  2709.  
  2710.  
  2711. 26 The Speculative Scheme
  2712.  
  2713. actual entity, is one complex, fully determinate feeling. This final phase
  2714. is termed the 'satisfaction/ It is fully determinate (a) as to its genesis,
  2715. (b) as to its objective character for the transcendent creativity, and (c) as
  2716. to its prehension— positive or negative— of every item in its universe.
  2717.  
  2718. (xxvi) Each element in the genetic process of an actual [39] entity has
  2719. one self-consistent function, however complex, in the final satisfaction.
  2720.  
  2721. (xxvii) In a process of concrescence, there is a succession of phases in
  2722. which new prehensions arise by integration of prehensions in antecedent
  2723. phases. In these integrations 'feelings' contribute their 'subjective forms 7
  2724. and their 'data' to the formation of novel integral prehensions; but 'nega-
  2725. tive prehensions' contribute only their 'subjective forms/ The process con-
  2726. tinues till all prehensions are components in the one determinate integral
  2727. satisfaction.
  2728.  
  2729. SECTION III
  2730.  
  2731. There are nine Categoreal Obligations:
  2732.  
  2733. (i) The Category of Subjective Unity, The many feelings which belong
  2734. to an incomplete phase in the process of an actual entity, though unin-
  2735. tegrated by reason of the incompleteness of the phase, are compatible for
  2736. integration by reason of the unity of their subject.
  2737.  
  2738. (ii) The Category of Objective Identity. There can be no duplica-
  2739. tion of any element in the objective datum of the 'satisfaction' of an actual
  2740. entity, so far as concerns the function of that element in the 'satisfaction/
  2741.  
  2742. Here, as always, the term 'satisfaction' means the one complex fully
  2743. determinate feeling which is the completed phase in the process. This
  2744. category expresses that each element has one self-consistent function, how-
  2745. ever complex. Logic is the general analysis of self-consistency.
  2746.  
  2747. (iii) The Category of Objective Diversity. There can be no 'coalescence'
  2748. of diverse elements in the objective datum of an actual entity, so far as
  2749. concerns the functions of those elements in that satisfaction.
  2750.  
  2751. 'Coalescence' here means the notion of diverse elements exercising an
  2752. absolute identity of function, devoid of the contrasts inherent in their
  2753. diversities.
  2754.  
  2755. (iv) The Category of Conceptual Valuation. From each physical feel-
  2756. ing there is the derivation of a purely [40] conceptual feeling whose datum
  2757. is the eternal object determinant of the defmiteness of the actual entity, or
  2758. of the nexus, physically felt.
  2759.  
  2760. *(v) The Category of Conceptual Reversion. There is secondary orig-
  2761. ination of conceptual feelings with data which are partially identical with,
  2762. and partially diverse from, the eternal objects forming the data in the first
  2763. phase of the mental pole. The diversity is a relevant diversity determined
  2764. by the subjective aim.
  2765.  
  2766. Note that category (iv) concerns conceptual reproduction of physical
  2767. feeling, and category (v) concerns conceptual diversity from physical
  2768. feeling.
  2769.  
  2770.  
  2771.  
  2772. The Categoreal Scheme 27
  2773.  
  2774. (vi) The Category of Transmutation. When (in accordance with cate-
  2775. gory [iv], or with categories [iv] and [v])t one and the same conceptual
  2776. feeling is derived impartially by a prehending subject from its analogous
  2777. simplet physical feelings of various actual entities in its actual world, then,
  2778. in a subsequent phase of integration of these simple physical feelings to-
  2779. gether with the derivate conceptual feeling, the prehending subject may-
  2780. transmute the datum of this conceptual feeling into a characteristic of
  2781. some nexus containing those prehended actual entities among its mem-
  2782. bers, or of some part of that nexus. In this way the nexus (or its part),
  2783. thus characterized, is the objective datum of a feeling entertained by this
  2784. prehending subject.
  2785.  
  2786. It is evident that the complete datum of the transmuted feeling is a
  2787. contrast, namely ? 'the nexus, as one, in contrast with the eternal object/
  2788. This type of contrast is one of the meanings of the notion 'qualification
  2789. of physical substance by quality/
  2790.  
  2791. This category is the way in which the philosophy of organism, which is
  2792. an atomic theory of actuality, meets a perplexity which is inherent in all
  2793. monadic cosmologies. Leibniz in his Monadology meets the same diffi-
  2794. culty by a theory of 'confused' perception. But he fails to make clear how
  2795. 'confusion' originates.
  2796.  
  2797. (vii) The Category of Subjective Harmony. The val- [41] uations of con-
  2798. ceptual feelings are mutually determined by the adaptation of those feel-
  2799. ings to be contrasted elements congruent with the subjective aim.
  2800.  
  2801. Category (i) and category (vii) jointly express a pre-established harmony
  2802. in the process of concrescence of any one subject. Category (i) has to do
  2803. with data felt, and category (vii) with the subjective forms of the con-
  2804. ceptual feelings. This pre-established harmony is an outcome of the fact
  2805. that no prehension can be considered in abstraction from its subject, al-
  2806. though it originates in the process creative of its subject.
  2807.  
  2808. (viii) The Category of Subjective Intensity. The subjective aim, whereby
  2809. there is origination of conceptual feeling, is at* intensity of feeling (a) in
  2810. the immediate subject, and (/?) in the relevant future.
  2811.  
  2812. This double aim— at the immediate present and the relevant future-
  2813. is less divided than appears on the surface. For the determination of the
  2814. relevant future, and the anticipatory feeling respecting provision for its
  2815. grade of intensity, are elements affecting the immediate complex of feel-
  2816. ing. The greater part of morality hinges on the determination of relevance
  2817. in the future. The relevant future consists of those elements in the an-
  2818. ticipated future which are felt with effective intensity by the present sub-
  2819. ject by reason of the real potentiality for them to be derived from itself.
  2820.  
  2821. (ix) The Category of Freedom and Determination. The concrescence of
  2822. each individual actual entity is internally determined and is externally
  2823. free.
  2824.  
  2825. This category can be condensed into the formula, that in each con-
  2826. crescence whatever is determinable is determined, but that there is always
  2827.  
  2828.  
  2829.  
  2830. 28 The Speculative Scheme
  2831.  
  2832. a remainder for the decision of the subject-superject of that concrescence.
  2833. This subject-superject is the universe in that synthesis, and beyond it there
  2834. is nonentity. This final decision is the reaction of the unity of the whole
  2835. to its own internal determination. This reaction is the final modification
  2836. of emotion, appreciation, and purpose. But the decision [42] of the whole
  2837. arises out of the determination of the parts, so as to be strictly relevant
  2838. to it.
  2839.  
  2840. SECTION IV
  2841.  
  2842. The whole of thet discussion in the subsequent parts either leads up
  2843. to these categories (of the four types) or is explanatory of them, or is
  2844. considering our experience of the world in the light of these categories.
  2845. But a few preliminary notes may be useful.
  2846.  
  2847. It follows from the fourth category of explanation that the notion of
  2848. 'complete abstraction' is self-contradictory. For you cannot abstract the
  2849. universe from any entity, actual or non-actual, so as to consider that entity
  2850. in complete isolation. Whenever we think of some entity, we are asking,
  2851. What is it fit for here? In a sense, every entity pervades the whole world;
  2852. for this question has a definite answer for each entity in respect to any
  2853. actual entity or any nexus of actual entities.
  2854.  
  2855. It follows from the first category of explanation that 'becoming' is a
  2856. creative advance into novelty. It is for this reason that the meaning of the
  2857. phrase 'the actual world' is relative to the becoming of a definite actual
  2858. entity which is both novel and actual, relatively to that meaning, and to
  2859. no other meaning of that phrase. Thus, conversely, each actual entity
  2860. corresponds to a meaning of 'the actual world' peculiar to itself. This point
  2861. is dealt with more generally in categories of explanation (iii) and (v). An
  2862. actual world is a nexus; and the actual world of one actual entity sinks
  2863. to the level of a subordinate nexus in actual worlds beyond that actual
  2864. entity.
  2865.  
  2866. Trie first, the fourth, the eighteenth, and twenty-seventh categories state
  2867. different aspects of one and the same general metaphysical truth. The first
  2868. category states the doctrine in a general way: that every ultimate actuality
  2869. embodies in its own essence what Alexander 3 \43] terms 'a principle of un-
  2870. rest,' namely, its becoming. The fourth category applies this doctrine to the
  2871. very notion of an 'entity.' It asserts that the notion of an 'entity' means
  2872. 'an element contributory to the process of becoming.' We have in this
  2873. category the utmost generalization of the notion of 'relativity.' The eigh-
  2874. teenth category asserts that the obligations imposed on the becoming of
  2875. any particular actual entity arise from the constitutions of other actual
  2876. entities.
  2877.  
  2878. The four categories of explanation, (x) to (xiii), constitute the repudia-
  2879.  
  2880. 3 Cf. "Artistic Creation and Cosmic Creation," Proc. Brit. Acad., 1927 \ Vol.
  2881. XIII.
  2882.  
  2883.  
  2884.  
  2885. The Categoreal Scheme 29
  2886.  
  2887. tion of the notion of vacuous actuality, which haunts realistic philosophy.
  2888. The term Vacuous actuality' here means the notion of a res vera devoid of
  2889. subjective immediacy. This repudiation is fundamental for the organic
  2890. philosophy (cf. Part II, Ch. VII, 'The Subjectivist Principle'). The notion
  2891. of Vacuous actuality' is very closely allied to the notion of the 'inherence
  2892. of quality in substance/ Both notions— in their misapplication as funda-
  2893. mental metaphysical categories— find their chief support in a misunder-
  2894. standing of the true analysis of 'presentational immediacy' (cf. Part II,
  2895. Ch. II, Sects. I and V).
  2896.  
  2897. It is fundamental to the metaphysical doctrine of the philosophy of
  2898. organism, that the notion of an actual entity as the unchanging subject
  2899. of change is completely abandoned. An actual entity is at once the subject
  2900. experiencing and the superject of its experiences. It is subject-superject,
  2901. and neither half of this description can for a moment be lost sight of.
  2902. The term 'subject' will be mostly employed when the actual entity is
  2903. considered in respect to its own real internal constitution. But 'subject'
  2904. is always to be construed as an abbreviation of 'subject-super ject.'*
  2905.  
  2906. The ancient doctrine that 'no one crosses the same river twice' is ex-
  2907. tended. No thinker thinks twice; and, to put the matter more generally, no
  2908. subject experiences twice. This is what Locke ought to have meant by his
  2909. doctrine of time as a 'perpetual perishing.'
  2910.  
  2911. [44] This repudiation directly contradicts Kant's 'First Analogy of Expe-
  2912. rience' in either of its ways of phrasing (1st or 2ndt edition). In the phi-
  2913. losophy of organism it is not 'substance' which is permanent, but 'form.'
  2914. Forms suffer changing relations; actual entities 'perpetually perish' sub-
  2915. jectively, but are immortal objectively. Actuality in perishing acquires
  2916. objectivity, while it loses subjective immediacy. It loses the final causation
  2917. which is its internal principle of unrest, and it acquires efficient causation
  2918. whereby it is a ground of obligation characterizing the creativity.
  2919.  
  2920. Actual occasions in their 'formal' constitutions are devoid of all in-
  2921. determination. Potentiality has passed into realization. They are complete
  2922. and determinate matter of fact, devoid of all indecision. They form the
  2923. ground of obligation. But eternal objects, and propositions, and some more
  2924. complex sorts of contrasts, involve in their own natures indecision. They
  2925. are, like all entities, potentials for the process of becoming. Their ingres-
  2926. sion expresses the definiteness of the actuality in question. But their own
  2927. natures do not in themselves disclose in what actual entities this poten-
  2928. tiality of ingression is realized. Thus they involve indetermination in a
  2929. sense more complete than do the former set.
  2930.  
  2931. A multiplicity merely enters into process through its individual mem-
  2932. bers. The only statements to be made about a multiplicity express how
  2933. its individual members enter into the process of the actual world. Any
  2934. entity which enters into process in this way belongs to the multiplicity, and
  2935. no other entities do belong to it. It can be treated as a unity for this pur-
  2936. pose, and this purpose only. For example, each of the six kinds of entities
  2937.  
  2938.  
  2939.  
  2940. 30 The Speculative Scheme
  2941.  
  2942. just mentioned is a multiplicity t (i.e., not the individual entities of the
  2943. kinds, but the collective kinds of the entities). A multiplicity has solely
  2944. a disjunctive relationship to the actual world. The 'universe' comprising
  2945. the absolutely initial data for an actual entity is a multiplicity. The treat-
  2946. ment of a multiplicity as though it [45] had the unity belonging to an en-
  2947. tity of any one of the other six kinds produces logical errors. Whenever the
  2948. word 'entity' is used, it is to be assumed, unless otherwise stated, that it
  2949. refers to an entity of one of the six kinds, and not to a multiplicity.
  2950.  
  2951. There is no emergent evolution concerned with a multiplicity, so that
  2952. every statement about a multiplicity is a disjunctive statement about its
  2953. individual members. Entities of any of the first six kinds, and generic con-
  2954. trasts, will be called 'proper entities/
  2955.  
  2956. In its development the subsequent discussion of the philosophy of or-
  2957. ganism is governed by the belief that the subject-predicate form of propo-
  2958. sition is concerned with high abstractions, except in its application to sub-
  2959. jective forms. This sort of abstraction, apart from this exception, is rarely
  2960. relevant to metaphysical description. The dominance of Aristotelian logic
  2961. from the late classical period onwards has imposed on metaphysical
  2962. thought the categories naturally derivative from its phraseology. This dom-
  2963. inance of his logic does not seem to have been characteristic of Aristotle's
  2964. own metaphysical speculations. The divergencies, such as they are, in these
  2965. lectures from other philosophical doctrines mostly depend upon the fact
  2966. that many philosophers, who in their explicit statements criticize the
  2967. Aristotelian notion of 'substance/ yet implicitly throughout their discus-
  2968. sions presuppose that the 'subject-predicate' form of proposition embodies
  2969. the finally adequate mode of statement about the actual world. The evil
  2970. produced by the Aristotelian 'primary substance' is exactly this habit of
  2971. metaphysical emphasis upon the 'subject-predicate 7 form of proposition.
  2972.  
  2973.  
  2974.  
  2975. CHAPTER III
  2976. SOME DERIVATIVE NOTIONS
  2977.  
  2978. SECTION I
  2979.  
  2980. [46] The primordial created fact is the unconditioned conceptual valua-
  2981. tion of the entire multiplicity of eternal objects. This is the 'primordial
  2982. nature' of God. By reason of this complete valuation, the objectification of
  2983. God in each derivate actual entity results in a graduation of the relevance
  2984. of eternal objects to the concrescent phases of that derivate occasion. There
  2985. will be additional ground of relevance for select eternal objects by reason
  2986. of their ingression into derivate actual entities belonging to the actual
  2987. world of the concrescent occasion in question. But whether or no this be
  2988. the case, there is always the definite relevance derived from God. Apart
  2989. from God. eternal objects unrealized in the actual world would be rela-
  2990. tively non-existent for the concrescence in question. For effective relevance
  2991. requires agency of comparison, and agency belongs exclusively to actual
  2992. occasions.** This divine ordering is itself matter of fact, thereby condition-
  2993. ing creativity. Thus possibility which transcends realized temporal matter
  2994. of fact has a real relevance to the creative advance. God is the primordial
  2995. creature; but the description of his nature is not exhausted by this concep-
  2996. tual side of it. His 'consequent nature' results from his physical prehen-
  2997. sions of the derivative actual entities (cf. Part V).
  2998.  
  2999. 'Creativity' is another rendering of the Aristotelian 'matter/ and of the
  3000. modern 'neutral stuff/ But it is divested of the notion of passive recep-
  3001. tivity, either of 'form/ or of external relations; it is the pure notion of the
  3002. activity conditioned by the objective immortality of [47] the actual world—
  3003. a world which is never the same twice, though always with the stable ele-
  3004. ment of divine ordering. Creativity is without a character of its own in
  3005. exactly the same sense in which the Aristotelian 'matter' is without a char-
  3006. acter of its own. It is that ultimate notion of the highest generality at *
  3007. the base of actuality. It cannot be characterized, because all characters are
  3008. more special than itself. But creativity is always found under conditions,
  3009. and described as conditioned. The non-temporal act of all-inclusive un-
  3010. fettered valuation is at once a creature of creativity and a condition for
  3011. creativity. It shares this double character with all creatures. By reason of
  3012. its character as a creature, always in concrescence and never in the past, it
  3013. receives a reaction from the world; this reaction is its consequent nature.
  3014. It is here termed 'God'; because the contemplation of our natures, as
  3015.  
  3016. 31
  3017.  
  3018.  
  3019.  
  3020. 32 The Speculative Scheme
  3021.  
  3022. enjoying real feelings derived from the timeless source of all order, acquires
  3023. that 'subjective form' of refreshment and companionship at which reli-
  3024. gions aim.
  3025.  
  3026. This function of creatures, that they constitute the shifting character of
  3027. creativity, is here termed the 'objective immortality' of actual entities.
  3028. Thus God has objective immortality in respect to his primordial nature
  3029. and his consequent nature. The objective immortality of his consequent
  3030. nature is considered later (cf. Part V); we are now concerned with his
  3031. primordial nature.
  3032.  
  3033. God's immanence in the world in respect to his primordial nature is an
  3034. urge towards the future based upon an appetite in the present. Appetition
  3035. is at once the conceptual valuation of an immediate physical feeling com-
  3036. bined with the urge towards realization of the datum conceptually pre-
  3037. hended. For example, t 'thirst* is an immediate physical feeling integrated
  3038. with the conceptual prehension of its quenching.
  3039.  
  3040. Appetition x is immediate matter of fact including in itself a principle of
  3041. unrest, involving realization of what [48] is not and may be. The imme-
  3042. diate occasion thereby conditions creativity so as to procure, in the future,
  3043. physical realization of its mental pole, according to the various valuations
  3044. inherent in its various conceptual prehensions. All physical experience is
  3045. accompanied by an appetite for, or against, its continuance: an example is
  3046. the appetition of self-preservation. But the origination of the novel con-
  3047. ceptual prehension has, more especially, to be accounted for. Thirst is an
  3048. appetite towards a difference— towards something relevant, something
  3049. largely identical, but something with a definite novelty. This is an example
  3050. at a low level which shows the germ of a free imagination.
  3051.  
  3052. In what sense can unrealized abstract form be relevant? What is its basis
  3053. of relevance? 'Relevance' must express some real fact of togetherness
  3054. among forms. The ontological principle can be expressed as: All real to-
  3055. getherness is togetherness in the formal constitution of an actuality. So if
  3056. there be a relevance of what in the temporal world is unrealized, the rele-
  3057. vance must express a fact of togetherness in the formal constitution of a
  3058. non-temporal actuality. But by the principle of relativity there can only be
  3059. one non-derivative actuality, unbounded by its prehensions of an actual
  3060. world. Such a primordial superject of creativity achieves, in its unity of
  3061. satisfaction, the complete conceptual valuation of all eternal objects. This
  3062. is the ultimate, basic adjustment of the togetherness of eternal objects on
  3063. which creative order depends. It is the conceptual adjustment of all ap-
  3064. petites in the form of aversions and adversions. It constitutes the meaning
  3065. of relevance. Its status as an actual efficient fact is recognized by terming
  3066. it the 'primordial nature of God/
  3067.  
  3068. The word 'appetition' illustrates a danger which lurks in technical terms.
  3069. This same danger is also illustrated in the psychology derived from Freud.
  3070.  
  3071. 1 Cf . Leibniz's Monadology.
  3072.  
  3073.  
  3074.  
  3075. Some Derivative Notions 33
  3076.  
  3077. The mental poles of actualities contribute various grades of complex feel-
  3078. ings to the actualities including them as factors. The [49] basic operations
  3079. of mentality are 'conceptual prehensions.' These are the only operations of
  3080. 'pure' mentality. All other mental operations are 'impure/ in the sense
  3081. that they involve integrations of conceptual prehensions with the physical
  3082. prehensions of the physical pole. Since 'impurity* in prehension refers to
  3083. the prehension arising out of the integration of 'pure' physical prehensions
  3084. with 'pure' mental prehensions, it follows that an 'impure' t mental pre-
  3085. hension is also an 'impure' physical prehension and conversely. Thus the
  3086. term 'impure' applied to a prehension has a perfectly definite meaning;
  3087. and does not require the terms 'mental' or 'physical/ except for the direc-
  3088. tion of attention in the discussion concerned.
  3089.  
  3090. The technical term 'conceptual prehension' is entirely neutral, devoid
  3091. of all suggestiveness. But such terms present great difficulties to the under-
  3092. standing, by reason of the fact that they suggest no particular exemplifica-
  3093. tions. Accordingly, we seek equivalent terms which have about them the
  3094. suggestiveness of familiar fact. We have chosen the term 'appetition/
  3095. which suggests exemplifications in our own experience, also in lower forms
  3096. of life such as insects and vegetables. But even in human experience 'ap-
  3097. petition' suggests a degrading notion of this basic activity in its more in-
  3098. tense operations. We are closely concerned with what Bergson calls 'intui-
  3099. tion'— with some differences however. Bergson's 'intuition' t is an 'impure'
  3100. operation; it is an integral feeling derived from the synthesis of the con-
  3101. ceptual prehension with the physical prehension from which it has been
  3102. derived according to the 'Category of Conceptual Reproduction' (Cate-
  3103. goreal Obligation! IV). It seems that Bergson's term 'intuition' has the
  3104. same meaning as 'physical purpose' in Part III of these lectures. Also
  3105. Bergson's 'intuition' seems to abstract from the subjective form of emotion
  3106. and purpose. This subjective form is an essential element in the notion of
  3107. 'conceptual prehension,' as indeed in that of any prehension. It is an essen-
  3108. tial element in 'physical purpose' (cf. Part III), If we con- [SO] sider these
  3109. 'pure' mental operations in their most intense operations, we should choose
  3110. the term 'vision.' A conceptual prehension is a direct vision of some possi-
  3111. bility of good or oft evil— of some possibility as to how actualities may be
  3112. definite. There is no reference to particular actualities, or to any par-
  3113. ticular actual world. The phrase 'of good or of evil' has been added to in-
  3114. clude a reference to the subjective form; the mere word 'vision' abstracts
  3115. from this factor in a conceptual prehension. If we say that God's primor-
  3116. dial nature is a completeness of 'appetition,' f we give due weight to the
  3117. subjective form— at a cost. If we say that God's primordial nature is 'in-
  3118. tuition/ we suggest mentality which is 'impure' by reason of synthesis with
  3119. physical prehension. If we say that God's primordial nature is 'vision,' we
  3120. suggest a maimed view of the subjective form, divesting it of yearning
  3121. after concrete fact— no particular facts, but after some actuality. There is
  3122. deficiency in God's primordial nature which the term 'vision' obscures.
  3123.  
  3124.  
  3125.  
  3126. 34 The Speculative Scheme
  3127.  
  3128. One advantage of the term Vision' is that it connects this doctrine of God
  3129. more closely with philosophical tradition. 'Envisagement' is perhaps a safer
  3130. term than Vision/ To sum up: God's primordial nature' is abstracted from
  3131. his commerce with 'particulars/ and is therefore devoid of those 'impure'
  3132. intellectual cogitations which involve propositions (cf. Part III). It is God
  3133. in abstraction, alone with himself. As such it is a mere factor in God, de-
  3134. ficient in actuality.
  3135.  
  3136. SECTION II
  3137.  
  3138. The notions of 'social order' and of 'personal order' cannot be omitted
  3139. from this preliminary sketch. A 'society/ in the sense in which that term
  3140. is here used, is a nexus with social order; and an 'enduring object/ or 'en-
  3141. during creature/ is a society whose social order has taken the special form
  3142. of 'personal order.'
  3143.  
  3144. A nexus enjoys 'social order' where (i) there is a common element of
  3145. form illustrated in the definiteness [Si] of each of its included actual en-
  3146. tities, and (ii) this common element of form arises in each member of the
  3147. nexus by reason of the conditions imposed upon it by its prehensions of
  3148. some other members of the nexus, and (iii) these prehensions impose that
  3149. condition of reproduction by reason of their inclusion of positive feelings
  3150. of that* common form. Such a nexus is called a 'society/ and the common
  3151. form is the 'defining characteristic' of the society. The notion f of 'defining
  3152. characteristic' is allied to the Aristotelian notion oft 'substantial form/
  3153.  
  3154. The common element of form is simply a complex eternal object ex-
  3155. emplified in each member of the nexus. But the social order of the nexus
  3156. is not the mere fact of this common form exhibited by all its members. The
  3157. reproduction of the common form throughout the nexus is due to the
  3158. genetic relations of the members of the nexus among each other, and to
  3159. the additional fact that genetic relations include feelings of the common
  3160. form. Thus the defining characteristic is inherited throughout the nexus,
  3161. each member deriving it from those other members of the nexus which
  3162. are antecedent to its own concrescence.
  3163.  
  3164. A nexus enjoys 'personal order' when (a) it is a 'society/ and (/?) when
  3165. the genetic relatedness of its members orders these members 'serially/
  3166.  
  3167. By this 'serial ordering' arising from the genetic relatedness, it is meant
  3168. that any member of the nexus— excluding the first and the last, if there be
  3169. such— constitutes a 'cut' in the nexus, so that (a) this member inherits
  3170. from all members on one side of the cut, and from no members on the
  3171. other side of the cut, and (b) if A and B are two members of the nexus
  3172. and B inherits from A, then the side of B's+ cut, inheriting from B, forms
  3173. part of the side of A's cut, inheriting from A, and the side of A's cut from
  3174. which A inherits forms part of the side of B's cut from which B inherits.
  3175. Thus the nexus forms a single line of inheritance of its defining character-
  3176. istic. Such a nexus is called an 'enduring object/ It might have been
  3177.  
  3178.  
  3179.  
  3180. Some Derivative Notions 35
  3181.  
  3182. termed a 'person/ in the legal sense [52] of that term. But unfortunately
  3183. 'person' suggests the notion of consciousness, so that its use would lead to
  3184. misunderstanding. The nexus 'sustains a character/ and this is one of the
  3185. meanings of the Latin word persona. But an 'enduring object/ qua 'per-
  3186. son/ does more than sustain a character. For this sustenance arises out of
  3187. the special genetic relations among the members of the nexus. An ordinary
  3188. physical object, which has temporal endurance, is a society. In the ideally
  3189. simple case, it has personal order and is an 'enduring object. 7 A society may
  3190. (or may not) be analysable into many strands of 'enduring objects/ This
  3191. will be the case for most ordinary physical objects. These enduring objects
  3192. and 'societies/ analysable into strands of enduring objects, are the per-
  3193. manent entities which enjoy adventures of change throughout time and
  3194. space. For example, they form the subject-matter of the science of dy-
  3195. namics. Actual entities perish, but do not change; they are what they are.
  3196. A nexus which (i) enjoys social order, and (ii) is analysable into strands
  3197. of enduring objects may be termed a 'corpuscular society/ A society may
  3198. be more or less corpuscular, according to the relative importance of the
  3199. defining characteristics of the various enduring objects compared to that
  3200. of the defining characteristic of the whole corpuscular nexus.
  3201.  
  3202. SECTION III
  3203.  
  3204. There is a prevalent misconception that 'becoming' involves the notion
  3205. of a unique seriality for its advance into novelty. This is the classic notion
  3206. of 'time/ which philosophy took over from common sense. Mankind made
  3207. an unfortunate generalization from its experience of enduring objects. Re-
  3208. cently physical science has abandoned this notion. Accordingly we should
  3209. now purge cosmology of a point of view which it ought never to have
  3210. adopted as an ultimate metaphysical principle. In these lectures the term
  3211. 'creative advance' is not to be construed in the sense of a uniquely serial
  3212. advance.
  3213.  
  3214. [S3] Finally, the extensive continuity of the physical universe has usually
  3215. been construed to mean that there is a continuity of becoming. But if we
  3216. admit that 'something becomes/ it is easy, by employing Zeno's method, to
  3217. prove that there can be no continuity of becoming. 2 There is a becoming
  3218. of continuity, but no continuity of becoming. The actual occasions are the
  3219. creatures which become, and they constitute a continuously extensive
  3220. world. In other words, extensiveness becomes, but 'becoming' is not itself
  3221. extensive.
  3222.  
  3223. Thus the ultimate metaphysical truth is atomism. The creatures are
  3224. atomic. In the present cosmic epoch there is a creation of continuity. Per-
  3225. haps such creation is an ultimate metaphysical truth holding of all cosmic
  3226.  
  3227. 2 Cf. Part II, Ch. II, Sect. II; and also my Science and the Modern World,
  3228. Ch. VII, for a discussion of this argument.
  3229.  
  3230.  
  3231.  
  3232. 36 The Speculative Scheme
  3233.  
  3234. epochs; but this does not* seem to be a necessary conclusion. The more
  3235. likely opinion is that extensive continuity is a special condition arising
  3236. from the society of creatures which constitute our immediate epoch. But
  3237. atomism does not exclude complexityt and universal relativity. Each atom
  3238. is a system of all things.
  3239.  
  3240. The proper balance between atomism and continuity is of importance to
  3241. physical science. For example, the doctrine, here explained, conciliates
  3242. Newton's corpuscular theory of light with the wave theory. For both a
  3243. corpuscle, and an advancing element of at wave front, are merely a per-
  3244. manent form propagated from atomic creature to atomic creature. A cor-
  3245. puscle is in fact an 'enduring object.' The notion of an 'enduring object'
  3246. is, however, capable of more or less completeness of realization. Thus, in
  3247. different stages of its career, a wave of light may be more or less corpuscu-
  3248. lar. A train of such waves at all stages of its career involves social order;
  3249. but in the earlier stages this social order takes the more special form of
  3250. loosely related strands of personal order. This dominant personal order
  3251. gradually vanishes as the time advances. Its defining characteristics become
  3252. less and [54] less important, as their various features peter out. The waves
  3253. then become a nexus with important social order, but with no strands of
  3254. personal order. Thus the train of waves starts as a corpuscular society, and
  3255. ends as a society which is not corpuscular.
  3256.  
  3257. SECTION IV
  3258.  
  3259. Finally, in the cdsmological scheme here outlined one implicit assump-
  3260. tion of the philosophical tradition is repudiated. The assumption is that
  3261. the basic elements of experience are to be described in terms of one, or
  3262. all, of the three ingredients, consciousness, thought, sense-perception. The
  3263. last term is used in the sense of 'conscious perception in the mode of pre-
  3264. sentational immediacy/ Also in practice sense-perception is narrowed
  3265. down to visual perception. According to the philosophy of organism these
  3266. three components are unessential elements in experience, either physical
  3267. or mental. Any instance of experience is dipolar, whether that instance
  3268. be God or an actual occasion of the world. The origination of God is from
  3269. the mental pole, the origination of an actual occasion is from the physical
  3270. pole; but in either case these elements, consciousness, thought, sense-per-
  3271. ception, belong to the derivative 'impure 7 phases of the concrescence, if in
  3272. any effective sense they enter at all.
  3273.  
  3274. This repudiation is the reason why, in relation to the topic under discus-
  3275. sion, the status of presentational immediacy is a recurrent theme through-
  3276. out the subsequent Partst of these lectures.
  3277.  
  3278.  
  3279.  
  3280. PART II
  3281. DISCUSSIONS AND APPLICATIONS
  3282.  
  3283.  
  3284.  
  3285. CHAPTER I
  3286. FACT AND FORM
  3287.  
  3288. SECTION I
  3289.  
  3290. [62] All human discourse which bases its claim to consideration on the
  3291. truth of its statements must appeal to the facts. In none of its branches
  3292. can philosophy claim immunity to this rule. But in the case of philosophy
  3293. the difficulty arises that the record of the facts is in part dispersed vaguely
  3294. through the various linguistic expressions of civilized language and of
  3295. literature, and is in part expressed more precisely under the influence of
  3296. schemes of thought prevalent in the traditions of science and philosophy.
  3297.  
  3298. In this second part of these lectures, the scheme of [63] thought which is
  3299. the basis of the philosophy of organism is confronted with various interpre-
  3300. tations of the facts widely accepted in thet European tradition, literary,
  3301. philosophic, and scientific. So far as concerns philosophy only a selected
  3302. group can be explicitly mentioned. There is no point in endeavouring to
  3303. force the interpretations of divergent philosophers into a vague agreement.
  3304. What is important is that the scheme of interpretation here adopted can
  3305. claim for each of its main positions the express authority of one, or the
  3306. other, of some supreme master of thought—Plato, Aristotle, Descartes,
  3307. Locke, Hume, Kant. But ultimately nothing rests on authority; the final
  3308. court of appeal is intrinsic reasonableness.
  3309.  
  3310. The safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradi-
  3311. tion is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato. I do not mean the
  3312. systematic scheme of thought which scholars have doubtfully extracted
  3313. from his writings. I allude to the wealth of general ideas scattered through
  3314. them. His personal endowments, his wide opportunities for experience at
  3315. a great period of civilization, his inheritance of an intellectual tradition
  3316. not yet stiffened by excessive systematization, have made his writings t an
  3317. inexhaustible mine of suggestion. Thus in one sense by stating my belief
  3318. that the train of thought in these lectures is Platonic, I am doing no more
  3319. than expressing the hope that it falls within the European tradition. But I
  3320. do mean more: I mean that if we had to render Plato's general point of
  3321. view with the least changes made necessary by the intervening two thou-
  3322. sand years of human experience in social organization, in aesthetic attain-
  3323. ments, in science, and in religion, we should have to set about the con-
  3324. struction of a philosophy of organism. In such a philosophy the actualities
  3325. constituting the process of the world are conceived as exemplifying the
  3326.  
  3327. 39
  3328.  
  3329.  
  3330.  
  3331. 40 Discussions and Applications
  3332.  
  3333. ingression (or 'participation') of other things which constitute the poten-
  3334. tialities of definiteness for any actual existence. The things which are tem-
  3335. poral arise by their participation in the things which are eternal. The
  3336. [64] two sets are mediated by a thing which combines the actuality of what
  3337. is temporal with the timelessness of what is potential. This final entity is
  3338. the divine element in the world, by which the barren inefficient disjunction
  3339. of abstract potentialities obtains primordially the efficient conjunction of
  3340. ideal realization. This ideal realization of potentialities in a primordial
  3341. actual entity constitutes the metaphysical stability whereby the actual
  3342. process exemplifies general principles of metaphysics, and attains the ends
  3343. proper to specific types of emergent order. By reason of the actuality of this
  3344. primordial valuation of pure potentials, each eternal object has a definite,
  3345. effective relevance to each concrescent process. Apart from such orderings,**
  3346. there would be a complete disjunction of eternal objects unrealized in the
  3347. temporal world. Novelty would be meaningless, and inconceivable. We are
  3348. here extending and rigidly applying Hume's principle, that ideas of reflec-
  3349. tion are derived from actual facts.
  3350.  
  3351. By this recognition of the divine element the general Aristotelian princi-
  3352. ple is maintained that, apart from things that are actual, there is nothing
  3353. —nothing either in fact or in efficacy. This is the true general principle
  3354. which also underlies Descartes' dictum: "For this reason, when we per-
  3355. ceive any attribute, we therefore conclude that some existing thing or
  3356. substance to which it may be attributed, is necessarily present." *■ And
  3357. again: "for every clear and distinct conception (perceptio) is without
  3358. doubt something, and hence cannot derive its origin from what is
  3359. nought, . . ." 2 This general principle will be termed the 'ontological prin-
  3360. ciple. 7 It is the principle that everything is positively somewhere in ac-
  3361. tuality, and in potency everywhere. In one of its applications this principle
  3362. issues in the doctrine of 'conceptualising Thus [65] the search for a reason
  3363. is always the search for an actual fact which is the vehicle of the reason. The
  3364. ontological principle, as here defined, constitutes the first step in the de-
  3365. scription of the universe as a solidarity 3 of many actual entities. Each
  3366. actual entity is conceived as an act of experience arising out of data. It is
  3367. a process of 'feeling' the many data, so as to absorb them into the unity of
  3368. one individual 'satisfaction/ Here 'feeling' is the term used for the basic
  3369. generic operation of passing from the objectivity of the data to the sub-
  3370. jectivity of the actual entity in question. Feelings are variously specialized
  3371.  
  3372.  
  3373.  
  3374. 1 Principles of Philosophy, Part I, 52; translation by Haldane and Ross. All
  3375. quotations from Descartes are from this translation.*
  3376.  
  3377. 2 Meditation IV, towards the end.
  3378.  
  3379. 3 The word 'solidarity' has been borrowed from Professor Wildon Carr's Presi-
  3380. dential Address to the Aristotelian Society, Session 1917-1918. The address —
  3381. 'The Interaction of Body and Mind" — develops the fundamental principle sug-
  3382. gested by this word.
  3383.  
  3384.  
  3385.  
  3386. Fact and Form 41
  3387.  
  3388. operations, effecting a transition into subjectivity. They replace the 'neu-
  3389. tral stuff' of certain realistic philosophers. An actual entity is a process,
  3390. and is not describable in terms of the morphology of a 'stuff/ This use of
  3391. the term 'feeling' has a close analogy to Alexander's 4 use of the term
  3392. 'enjoyment'; and has also some kinship with Bergson's use of the term
  3393. 'intuition; A near analogy is Locke's use of the term 'idea/ including 'ideas
  3394. of particular things' (cf. his Essay, III, III, 2, 6, and 7). But the word
  3395. 'feeling/ as used in these lectures, is even more reminiscent of Descartes.
  3396. For example: "Let it be so; still it is at least quite certain that it seems to
  3397. me that I see light, that I hear noise and that I feel heat. That cannot be
  3398. false; properly speaking it is what is in me called feeling (sentire); and
  3399. used in this precise sense that is no other thing than thinking." 5
  3400.  
  3401. In Cartesian language, the essence of an actual entity consists solely in
  3402. the fact that it is a prehending thing (i.e., a substance whose whole essence
  3403. or nature is to prehend). 6 A 'feeling' belongs to the positive species [66] of
  3404. 'prehensions.' There are two species of prehensions, the 'positive species' and
  3405. the 'negative species.' An actual entity has a perfectly definite bond with
  3406. each item in the universe. This determinate bond is its prehension of that
  3407. item. A negative prehension is the definite exclusion of that item from
  3408. positive contribution to the subject's own real internal constitution. This
  3409. doctrine involves the position that a negative prehension expresses a
  3410. bond. A positive prehension is the definite inclusion of that item into posi-
  3411. tive contribution to the subject's own real internal constitution. This
  3412. positive inclusion is called its 'feeling' of that item. Other entities are re-
  3413. quired to express how any one item is felt. All actual entities in the actual
  3414. world, relatively to a given actual entity as 'subject,' are necessarily 'felt'
  3415. by that subject, though in general vaguely. An actual entity as felt is said
  3416. to be 'objectified' for that subject. Only a selection of eternal objects are
  3417. 'felt' by a given subject, and these eternal objects are then said to have
  3418. 'ingression' in that subject. But those eternal objects which are not felt are
  3419. not therefore negligible. For each negative prehension has its own sub-
  3420. jective form, however trivial and faint. It adds to the emotional complex,
  3421. though not to the objective data. The emotional complex is the subjective
  3422. form of the final 'satisfaction.' The importance of negative prehensions
  3423. arises from the fact, that (i) actual entities form a system, in the sense of
  3424. entering into each other's constitutions, (ii) that by the ontological
  3425. principle every entity is felt by some actual entity, (iii) that, as a conse-
  3426. quence of (i) and (ii), every entity in the actual world of a concrescent
  3427. actuality has some gradation of real relevance to that concrescence, (iv)
  3428. that, in consequence of (iii), the negative prehension of an entity is a
  3429.  
  3430. 4 Cf. his Space, Time and Deity, passim.
  3431.  
  3432. 5 Meditation II, Haldane and Ross translation.
  3433.  
  3434. 6 For the analogue to this sentence cf. Meditation VI; substitute 'Ens pre-
  3435. hendens" fort 'Ens cogitans. 7
  3436.  
  3437.  
  3438.  
  3439. 42 Discussions and Applications
  3440.  
  3441. positive fact with its emotional subjective form,t (v) there is a mutual
  3442. sensitivity of the subjective forms of prehensions, so that they are not in-
  3443. different to each other, (vi) the concrescence issues in one concrete feel-
  3444. ing, the satisfaction.
  3445.  
  3446. SECTION II
  3447.  
  3448. [67] That we fail to find in experience any elements intrinsically incapa-
  3449. ble of exhibition as examples of general theoryt is the hope of rationalism.
  3450. This hope is not a metaphysical premise. It is the faith which forms the
  3451. motive for the pursuit of all sciences alike, including metaphysics.
  3452.  
  3453. In so far as metaphysics enables us to apprehend the rationality of
  3454. things, the claim is justified. It is always open to us, having regard to the
  3455. imperfections of all metaphysical systems, to lose hope at the exact point
  3456. where we find ourselves. The preservation of such faith must depend on an
  3457. ultimate moral intuition into the nature of intellectual action— that it
  3458. should embody the adventure of hope. Such an intuition marks the point
  3459. where metaphysics— and indeed every science— gains assurance from reli-
  3460. gion and passes over into religion. But in itself the faith does not embody a
  3461. premise from which the theory starts: it is an ideal which is seeking satis-
  3462. faction. In so far as we believe that doctrine, we are rationalists.
  3463.  
  3464. There must, however, be limits to the claim that all the elements in
  3465. the universe are explicable by 'theory/ For 'theory' itself requires that there
  3466. be given' elements so as to form the material for theorizing. Plato himself
  3467. recognizes this limitation: I quote from Professor A. E. Taylor's summary
  3468. of the Timaeus:
  3469.  
  3470. In the real world there is always, over and above "law," a factor of
  3471. the "simply given" or "brute fact," not accounted for and to be ac-
  3472. cepted simply as given. It is the business of science never to acquiesce
  3473. in the merely given, to seek to "explain" it as the consequence, in virtue
  3474. of rational law, of some simpler initial "given." But, however far sci-
  3475. ence may carry this procedure, it is always forced to retain some ele-
  3476. ment of brute fact, the merely given, in its account of things. It is the
  3477. presence in nature of this element of the given, this surd or irrational
  3478. as it has [68] sometimes been called, which Timaeus appears to be per-
  3479. sonifying in his language about Necessity. 7
  3480.  
  3481. So far as the interpretation of Plato is concerned, I rely upon the au-
  3482. thority of Professor Taylor. But, apart from this historical question, a clear
  3483. understanding of the 'given' elements in the world is essential for any form
  3484. of Platonic realism.
  3485.  
  3486. For rationalistic thought, the notion of 'givenness' carries with it a
  3487. reference beyond the mere data in question. It refers to a 'decision'
  3488. whereby what is 'given' is separated off from what for that occasion is 'not
  3489.  
  3490. 7 Plato, The Man and His Work, Lincoln MacVeagh, New York, 1927.*
  3491.  
  3492.  
  3493.  
  3494. Fact and Form 43
  3495.  
  3496. given/ This element of 'givenness' in things implies some activity pro-
  3497. curing limitation. The word 'decision' does not here imply conscious judg-
  3498. ment, though in some 'decisions' consciousness will be a factor. The word
  3499. is used in its root sense of a 'cutting off/ The ontological principle declares
  3500. that every decision is referable to one or more actual entities, because in
  3501. separation from actual entities there is nothing, merely nonentity— 'The
  3502. rest is silence/
  3503.  
  3504. The ontological principle asserts the relativity of decision; whereby every
  3505. decision expresses the relation of the actual thing, for which a decision is
  3506. made, to an actual thing by which that decision is made. But 'decision'
  3507. cannot be construed as a casual adjunct of an actual entity. It constitutes
  3508. the very meaning of actuality. An actual entity arises from decisions for it,
  3509. and by its very existence provides decisions for other actual entities which
  3510. supersede it. Thus the ontological principle is the first stage in constituting
  3511. a theory embracing the notions of 'actual entity/ 'givenness,' and 'process/
  3512. Just as 'potentiality for process' is the meaning of the more general term
  3513. 'entity/ or 'thing; so 'decision' is the additional meaning imported by the
  3514. word 'actual' into the phrase 'actual entity/ 'Actuality' is the decision
  3515. amid 'potentiality/ It represents stubborn fact which cannot be evaded.
  3516. The real internal constitution of an actual [69] entity progressively consti-
  3517. tutes a decision conditioning the creativity which transcends that actuality.
  3518. The Castle Rock at Edinburgh exists from moment to moment, and from
  3519. century to century, by reason of the decision** effected by its own historic
  3520. route of antecedent occasions. And if, in some vast upheaval of nature, it
  3521. were shattered into fragments, that convulsion would still be conditioned
  3522. by the fact that it was the destruction of that rock. The point to be empha-
  3523. sized is the insistent particularity of things experienced and of the act of
  3524. experiencing. Bradley's doctrine 8 — Wolf-eating-Lamb as a universal quali-
  3525. fying the absolute— is a travesty of the evidence. That wolf eat* that lamb
  3526. at that spot at that time: the wolf knew it; the lamb knew it; and the
  3527. carrion birds knew it. Explicitly in the verbal sentence, or implicitly in the
  3528. understanding of the subject entertaining it, every expression of a proposi-
  3529. tion includes demonstrative elements. In fact each word, and each sym-
  3530. bolic phrase, is such an element, exciting the conscious prehension of some
  3531. entity belonging to one of the categories of existence.
  3532.  
  3533. SECTION III
  3534.  
  3535. Converselv. where there is no decision involving exclusion, there is no
  3536. givenness. For example, the total multiplicity of Platonic forms is not
  3537. 'given/ But in respect of each actual entity, there is givenness of such
  3538. forms . The determinate definiteness of each actuality is an expression of a
  3539. selection from these forms. It grades them in a diversity of relevance. This
  3540.  
  3541. 8 Cf. Logic, Bk. I, Ch. II, Sect. 42.
  3542.  
  3543.  
  3544.  
  3545. 44 Discussions and Applications
  3546.  
  3547. ordering of relevance starts from those forms which are, in the fullest
  3548. sense, exemplified, and passes through grades of relevance down to those
  3549. forms which in some faint sense are proximately relevant by reason of
  3550. contrast with actual fact. This whole gamut of relevance is 'given/ and
  3551. must be referred to the decision of actuality.
  3552.  
  3553. The term 'Platonic form' has here been used as the [70] briefest way of
  3554. indicating the entities in question. But these lectures are not an exegesis of
  3555. Plato's writings; the entities in question are not necessarily restricted to
  3556. those which he would recognize as 'forms/ Also the term 'idea' has a sub-
  3557. jective suggestion in modern philosophy, which is very misleading for my
  3558. present purposes; and in any case it has been used in many senses and has
  3559. become ambiguous. The term 'essence/ as used by the Critical Realists,
  3560. also suggests their use of it, which diverges from what I intend. Accord-
  3561. ingly, by way of employing a term devoid of misleading suggestions, I use
  3562. the phrase 'eternal object' for what in the preceding paragraph of this
  3563. section I have termed a 'Platonic form/ Any entity whose conceptual rec-
  3564. ognition does not involve a necessary reference to any definite actual en-
  3565. tities of the temporal world is called an 'eternal object/
  3566.  
  3567. In this definition the 'conceptual recognition' must of course be an
  3568. operation constituting a real feeling belonging to some actual entity. The
  3569. point is that the actual subject which is merely conceiving the eternal ob-
  3570. ject is not thereby in direct relationship to some other actual entity, apart
  3571. from any other peculiarity in the composition of that conceiving subject.
  3572. This doctrine applies also to thef primordial nature of God, which is his
  3573. complete envisagement of eternal objects; he+ is not thereby directly related
  3574. to the given course of history. The given course of history presupposes his
  3575. primordial nature, but his primordial nature does not presuppose it.
  3576.  
  3577. An eternal object is always a potentiality for actual entities; but in itself,
  3578. as conceptually felt, it is neutral as to the fact of its physical ingression in
  3579. any particular actual entity of the temporal world. 'Potentiality' is the cor-
  3580. relative of 'givenness/ The meaning of 'givenness' is that what is 'given'
  3581. * might not have been 'given'; and that what is not 'given' might have been
  3582. 'given.'
  3583.  
  3584. Further, in the complete particular 'givenness' for an actual entity there
  3585. is an element of exclusiveness. The [71] various primary data and the con-
  3586. crescent feelings do not form a mere multiplicity. Their synthesis in the
  3587. final unity of one actual entity is another fact of 'givenness.' The actual en-
  3588. tity terminates its becoming in one complex feeling involving a completely
  3589. determinate bond with every item in the universe, the bond being either a*
  3590. positive or a negative prehension. This termination is the 'satisfaction' of
  3591. the actual entity. Thus the addition of another component alters this
  3592. synthetic 'givenness.' Any additional component is therefore contrary to
  3593. this integral 'givenness' of the original. This principle may be illustrated by
  3594. our visual perception of a picture. The pattern of colours is 'given' for us.
  3595.  
  3596.  
  3597.  
  3598. Fact and Form 45
  3599.  
  3600. But an extra patch of red does not constitute a mere addition; it alters the
  3601. whole balance. Thus in an actual entity the balanced unity of the total
  3602. 'givenness' excludes anything that is not given.
  3603.  
  3604. This is the doctrine of the emergent unity of the superject. An actual
  3605. entity is to be conceived both as a subject presiding over its own immediacy
  3606. of becoming, and a superject which is the atomic creature exercising its
  3607. function of objective immortality. It has become a 'being'; and it belongs to
  3608. the nature of every 'being' that it is a potential for every 'becoming.'
  3609.  
  3610. This doctrine, that the final 'satisfaction' of an actual entity is intolerant
  3611. of any addition, expresses the fact that every actual entity— since it is
  3612. what it is— is finally its own reason for what it omits. In the real internal
  3613. constitution of an actual entity there is always some element which is con-
  3614. trary to an omitted element. Here 'contrary' means the impossibility of
  3615. joint entry in the same sense. In other words, indetermination has evap-
  3616. orated from 'satisfaction/ so that there is a complete determination of
  3617. 'feeling/ or of 'negation of feeling/ respecting the universe. This evapora-
  3618. tion of indetermination is merely another way of considering the process
  3619. whereby the actual entity arises from its data. Thus, in another sense, each
  3620. actual entity includes the uni- \72] verse, by reason of its determinate atti-
  3621. tude towards every element in the universe.
  3622.  
  3623. Thus the process of becoming is dipolar, (i) by reason of its qualification
  3624. by the determinateness of the actual world, and (ii) by its conceptual pre-
  3625. hensions of the indeterminateness of eternal objects. The process is con-
  3626. stituted by the influx of eternal objects into a novel determinateness of
  3627. feeling which absorbs the actual world into a novel actuality.
  3628.  
  3629. The 'formal' constitution of an actual entity is a process of transition
  3630. from indetermination towards terminal determination. But the indetermi-
  3631. nation is referent to determinate data. The 'objective 7 constitution of an*
  3632. actual entity is its terminal determination, considered as a complex of com-
  3633. ponent determinates by reason of which the actual entity is a datum for
  3634. the creative advance. The actual entity on its physical side is composed of
  3635. its determinate feelings of its actual world, and on its mental side is
  3636. originated by its conceptual appetitions.
  3637.  
  3638. Returning to the correlation of 'givenness' and 'potentiality/ we see that
  3639. 'givenness' refers to 'potentiality/ and 'potentiality' to 'givenness'; also we
  3640. see that the completion of 'givenness' in actual fact converts the 'not-given'
  3641. for that fact into 'impossibility' for that fact. The individuality of an actual
  3642. entity involves an exclusive limitation. This element of 'exclusive limita-
  3643. tion' is the definiteness essential for the synthetic unity of an actual entity.
  3644. This synthetic unity forbids the notion of mere addition to the included
  3645. elements.
  3646.  
  3647. It is evident that 'givenness' and 'potentiality' are both meaningless apart
  3648. from a multiplicity of potential entities. These potentialities are the
  3649. 'eternal objects.' Apart from 'potentiality' and 'givenness/ there can be no
  3650.  
  3651.  
  3652.  
  3653. 46 Discussions and Applications
  3654.  
  3655. nexus of actual things in process of supersession by novel actual things.
  3656. The alternative is a static monistic universe, without unrealized poten-
  3657. tialities; since 'potentiality* is then a meaningless term.
  3658.  
  3659. [73] The scope of the ontological principle is not exhausted by the corol-
  3660. lary that 'decision 7 must be referable to an actual entity. Everything must
  3661. be somewhere; and here "somewhere' means 'some actual entity/ Accord-
  3662. ingly the general potentiality of the universe must be somewhere; since it
  3663. retains its proximate relevance to actual entities for which it is unrealized.
  3664. This 'proximate relevance' reappears in subsequent concrescence as final
  3665. causation regulative of the emergence of novelty. This 'somewhere' is the
  3666. non- temporal actual entity. Thus 'proximate relevance' means 'relevance
  3667. as in the primordial mind of God.'t
  3668.  
  3669. It is a contradiction in terms to assume that some explanatory fact can
  3670. float into the actual world out of nonentity. Nonentity is nothingness.
  3671. Every explanatory fact refers to the decision and to the efficacy* of an
  3672. actual thing. The notion of 'subsistence' is merely the notion of how eternal
  3673. objects can be components of the primordial nature of God. This is a
  3674. question for subsequent discussion (cf. Part V). But eternal objects, as in
  3675. God's primordial nature, constitute the Platonic world of ideas.
  3676.  
  3677. There is not, however, one entity which is merely the class of all eternal
  3678. objects. For if we conceive any class of eternal objects, there are additional
  3679. eternal objects which presuppose that class but do not belong to it. For this
  3680. reason, at the beginning of this section, the phrase 'the multiplicity of
  3681. Platonic forms' was used, instead of the more natural phrase 'thet class of
  3682. Platonic forms.' A multiplicity is a type of complex thing which has the
  3683. unity derivative from some qualification which participates in each of its
  3684. components severally; but a multiplicity has no unity derivative merely
  3685. from its various components.
  3686.  
  3687. SECTION IV
  3688.  
  3689. The doctrine just stated— that every explanatory fact refers to the deci-
  3690. sion and to the efficacy of an actual [74} thing— requires discussion in ref-
  3691. erence to the ninth Categoreal Obligation. This category states that 'The
  3692. concrescence of each individual actual entity is internally determined and
  3693. is externally free.'
  3694.  
  3695. The peculiarity of the course of history illustrates the joint relevance of
  3696. the 'ontological principle' and of this categoreal obligation. The evolution
  3697. of history can be rationalized by the consideration of the determination
  3698. of successors by antecedents. But, on the other hand, the evolution of his-
  3699. tory is incapable of rationalization because it exhibits a selected flux of
  3700. participating forms. No reason, internal to history, can be assigned why
  3701. that flux of forms, rather than another flux, should have been illustrated.
  3702. It is true that any flux must exhibit the character of internal determina-
  3703. tion. So much follows from the ontological principle. But every instance of
  3704.  
  3705.  
  3706.  
  3707. Fact and Form 47
  3708.  
  3709. internal determination assumes that flux up to that point. There is no
  3710. reason why there could be no alternative flux exhibiting that principle of
  3711. internal determination. The actual flux presents itself with the character
  3712. of being merely 'given. 7 It does not disclose any peculiar character of 'per-
  3713. fection. 7 On the contrary, the imperfection of the world is the theme of
  3714. every religion which offers a way of escape, and of every sceptic who de-
  3715. plores the prevailing superstition. The Leibnizian theory of the 'best of
  3716. possible worlds 7 is an audacious fudge produced in order to save the face
  3717. of a Creator constructed by contemporary, and antecedent, theologians.
  3718. Further, in the case of those actualities whose immediate experience is
  3719. most completely open to us, namely, human beings, the final decision of
  3720. the immediate subject-superject, constituting the ultimate modification of
  3721. subjective aim, is the foundation of our experience of responsibility, of ap-
  3722. probation or of disapprobation, of self-approval or of self-reproach, of free-
  3723. dom, of emphasis. This element in experience is too large to be put aside
  3724. merely as misconstruction. It governs the whole tone of human life. It can
  3725. be illustrated+ by striking [75] instances from fact or from fiction. But
  3726. these instances are only conspicuous illustrations of human experience
  3727. during each hour and each minute. The ultimate freedom of things, lying
  3728. beyond all determinations, was whispered by Galileo— E pur si muove—
  3729. freedom for the inquisitors to think wrongly, for Galileo to think rightly,
  3730. and for the world to move in despite of Galileo and inquisitors.
  3731.  
  3732. The doctrine of the philosophy of organism is that, however far the
  3733. sphere of efficient causation be pushed in the determination of components
  3734. of a concrescence— its data, its emotions, its appreciations, its purposes, its
  3735. phases of subjective aim— beyond the determination of these components
  3736. there always remains the final reaction of the self-creative unity of the
  3737. universe. This final reaction completes the self-creative act by putting the
  3738. decisive stamp of creative emphasis upon the determinations of efficient
  3739. cause. Each occasion exhibits its measure of creative emphasis in propor-
  3740. tion to its measure of subjective intensity. The absolute standard of such
  3741. intensity is that of the primordial nature of God, which is neither great
  3742. nor small because it arises out of no actual world. It has within it no com-
  3743. ponents which are standards of comparison. But in the temporal world for
  3744. occasions of relatively slight experient intensity, their decisions of creative
  3745. emphasis are individually negligible compared to the determined com-
  3746. ponents which they receive and transmit. But the final accumulation of all
  3747. such decisions— the decision of God's nature and the decisions of all occa-
  3748. sions—constitutes that special element in the flux of forms in history, which
  3749. is given 7 and incapable of rationalization beyond the fact that within it
  3750. every component which is determinable is internally determined.
  3751.  
  3752. The doctrine is, that each concrescence is to be referred to a definite free
  3753. initiation and a definite free conclusion. The initial fact is macrocosmic, in
  3754. the sense of having equal relevance to all occasions; the final fact is micro-
  3755.  
  3756.  
  3757.  
  3758. 48 Discussions and Applications
  3759.  
  3760. [76] cosmic, in the sense of being peculiar to that occasion. Neither fact is
  3761. capable of rationalization, in the sense of tracing the antecedents which
  3762. determine it. The initial fact is the primordial appetition, and the final fact
  3763. is the decision of emphasis, finally creative of the 'satisfaction/
  3764.  
  3765. SECTION V
  3766.  
  3767. The antithetical terms 'universals 7 and 'particulars' are the usual words
  3768. employed to denote respectively entities which nearly, though not quite, 9
  3769. correspond to the entities here termed 'eternal objects/ and 'actual en-
  3770. tities. 7 These terms, 'universals 7 and 'particulars/ both in the suggestive-
  3771. ness of the two words and in their current philosophical use, are somewhat
  3772. misleading. The ontological principle, and the wider doctrine of universal
  3773. relativity, on which the present metaphysical discussion is founded, blur
  3774. the sharp distinction between what is universal and what is particular. The
  3775. notion of a universal is of that which can enter into the description of many
  3776. particulars; whereas the notion of a particular is that it is described by uni-
  3777. versal, and does not itself enter into the description of any other particu-
  3778. lar. According to the doctrine of relativity which is the basis of the meta-
  3779. physical system of the present lectures, both these notions involve a mis-
  3780. conception. An actual entity cannot be described, even inadequately, by
  3781. universals; because other actual entities do enter into the description of
  3782. any one actual entity. Thus every so-called 'universal 7 is particular in the
  3783. sense of being just what it is, diverse from everything else; and every so-
  3784. called 'particular 7 is universal in the sense of entering into the constitu-
  3785. tions of other actual entities. The contrary opinion led to the collapse of
  3786. Descartes 7 many substances into Spinoza's one substance; to Leibniz's
  3787. windowless monads with their pre-established harmony; to the sceptical
  3788. reduction of Hume's philosophy— a reduction first effected by Hume him-
  3789. self, \77] and reissued with the most beautiful exposition by Santayana in
  3790. his Scepticism and Animal Faith.
  3791.  
  3792. The point is that the current view of universals and particulars inevitably
  3793. leads to the epistemological position stated by Descartes:
  3794.  
  3795. From this I should conclude that I knew the wax by means of vision
  3796. and not simply by the intuition of the mind; unless by chance I re-
  3797. member that, when looking from a window and saying I see men who
  3798. pass in the street, I really do not see them, but infer that what I see
  3799. is men, just as I say that I see wax. And yet what do I see from the
  3800. window but hats and coats which may cover automatic machines?
  3801. Yet I judge these to be men. And similarly solely by the faculty of
  3802. judgment [judicandi] which rests in my mind, I comprehend that
  3803. which I believed I saw with my eyes. 10
  3804.  
  3805. 9 For example, prehensions and subjective forms are also 'particulars.'
  3806.  
  3807. 10 Meditation II.
  3808.  
  3809.  
  3810.  
  3811. Fact and Form 49
  3812.  
  3813. In this passage it is assumed 1X that Descartes— the Ego in question— is a
  3814. particular, characterized only by universals. Thus his impressions— to use
  3815. Hume's word— are characterizations by universals. Thus there is no percep-
  3816. tion of a particular actual entity. He arrives at the belief in the actual
  3817. entity by 'the faculty of judgment. 7 But on this theory he has absolutely
  3818. no analogy upon which to found any such inference with the faintest
  3819. shred of probability. Hume, accepting Descartes' account of perception (in
  3820. this passage), which also belongs to Locke in some sections of his Essay ;
  3821. easily draws the sceptical conclusion. Santayana irrefutably exposes the
  3822. full extent to which this scepticism must be carried. The philosophy of
  3823. organism recurs to Descartes 7 alternative theory of 'realties objectiva,' and
  3824. endeavours to interpret it in terms of a consistent ontology. Descartes en-
  3825. deavoured to combine the two theories; but his unquestioned acceptance
  3826. of the subject-predicate dogma forced him [78] into a representative theory
  3827. of perception, involving a 'judicium 7 validated by our assurance of the
  3828. power and the goodness of God. The philosophy of organism in its account
  3829. of prehension takes its stand upon the Cartesian terms 'realitas objectiva, 7
  3830. 'inspection and Hntuitio. 7 The two latter terms are transformed into the
  3831. notion of a 'positive prehension, 7 and into operations described in the
  3832. various categories of physical and conceptual origination. A recurrence to
  3833. the notion of 'God 7 is still necessary to mediate between physical and con-
  3834. ceptual prehensions, but not in the crude form of giving a limited letter
  3835. of credit to a 'judicium.'
  3836.  
  3837. Hume, in effect, agrees that 'mind 7 is a process of concrescence arising
  3838. from primary data. In his account, these data are 'impressions of sensa-
  3839. tion 7 ; and in such impressions no elements other than universals are dis-
  3840. coverable. For the philosophy of organism, the primary data are always
  3841. actual entities absorbed into feeling in virtue of certain universals shared
  3842. alike by the objectified actuality and the experient subject (cf. Part III).
  3843. Descartes takes an intermediate position. He explains perception in Hu-
  3844. mian terms, but adds an apprehension of particular actual entities in virtue
  3845. of an Hnspectio 7 and a 'judicium 7 effected by the mind (Meditations II and
  3846. IJJ).t Here he is paving the way for Kant, and for the degradation of the
  3847. world into 'mere appearance.'
  3848.  
  3849. AH modern philosophy hinges round the difficulty of describing the
  3850. world in terms of subject and predicate, substance and quality, particular
  3851. and universal. The result always does violence to that immediate experi-
  3852. ence which we express in our actions, our hopes, our sympathies, our pur-
  3853. poses, and which we enjoy in spite of our lack of phrases for its verbal
  3854.  
  3855.  
  3856.  
  3857. 11 Perhaps inconsistently with what Descartes says elsewhere: in other passages
  3858. the mental activity involved seems to be analysis which discovers 'realitas ob-
  3859. jectiva 7 as a component element of the idea in question. There is thus Hnspectio'
  3860. rather than 'judicium. 7
  3861.  
  3862.  
  3863.  
  3864. 50 Discussions and Applications
  3865.  
  3866. analysis. We find ourselves in a buzzing 12 world, amid a democracy of
  3867. fellow creatures; whereas, under some disguise or other orthodox philoso-
  3868. phy can only introduce us to solitary substances, each enjoying an illusory
  3869. experience: "O Bottom, thou [79] art changed! what do I see on thee?' 7 *
  3870. The endeavour to interpret experience in accordance with the overpowering
  3871. deliverance of common senset must bring us back to some restatement of
  3872. Platonic realism, modified so as to avoid the pitfalls which the philosophi-
  3873. cal investigations of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries have dis-
  3874. closed.
  3875.  
  3876. The true point of divergence is the false notion suggested by the contrast
  3877. between the natural meanings of the words 'particular' and 'universal/ The
  3878. 'particular 7 is thus conceived as being just its individual self with no neces-
  3879. sary relevance to any other particular. It answers to Descartes 7 definition
  3880. of substance: "And when we conceive of substance, we merely conceive an
  3881. existent thing which requires nothing but itself in order to exist. 77 13 This
  3882. definition is a true derivative from Aristotle's definition: A primary sub-
  3883. stance is "neither asserted of a subject nor present in a subject. 77 14 We
  3884. must add the title phrase of Descartes 7 The Second Meditation: "Of the
  3885. Nature of the Human Mind; and that it is more easily known than the
  3886. Body,' 7 together with his two statements: "... thought constitutes the
  3887. nature of thinking substance,' 7 and "everything that we find in mind is
  3888. but so many diverse forms of thinking. 77 15 This sequence of quotations
  3889. exemplifies the set of presuppositions which led to Locke's empiricism and
  3890. to Kant's critical philosophy— the two dominant influences from which
  3891. modern thought is derived. This is the side of seventeenth-century philoso-
  3892. phy which is here discarded.
  3893.  
  3894. The principle of universal relativity directly traverses Aristotle's dictum,
  3895. 'A substancet is not present in a subject.' On the contrary, according to
  3896. this principle an actual entity is present in other actual entities. In fact if
  3897. we allow for degrees of relevance, and for negligible relevance, we must
  3898. say that every actual entity is present in every other actual entity. The
  3899. philosophy of organism [80] is mainly devoted to the task of making clear
  3900. the notion of 'being present in another entity.' This phrase is here borrowed
  3901. from Aristotle: it is not a fortunate phrase, and in subsequent discussion
  3902. it will be replaced by the term 'objectification.' The Aristotelian phrase
  3903. suggests the crude notion that one actual entity is added to another sim-
  3904. pliciter. This is not what is meant. One role of the eternal objects is that
  3905. they are those elements which express how any one actual entity is con-
  3906. stituted by its synthesis of other actual entities, and how that actual entity
  3907. develops from the primary dative phase into its own individual actual
  3908.  
  3909. 12 This epithet is, of course, borrowed from William James.
  3910.  
  3911. 13 Principles of Philosophy, Part I, 51.*
  3912.  
  3913. 14 Aristotle by W. D. Ross, Ch. II.
  3914.  
  3915. 15 Principles of Philosophy , Part I, 53.
  3916.  
  3917.  
  3918.  
  3919. Fact and Form 51
  3920.  
  3921. existence, involving its individual enjoyments and appetitions. An actual
  3922. entity is concrete because it is such a particular concrescence of the
  3923. universe.
  3924.  
  3925. SECTION VI
  3926.  
  3927. A short examination of Locke's Essay Concerning^ Human Under-
  3928. standing will throw light on the presuppositions from which the philosophy
  3929. of organism originates. These citations from Locke are valuable as clear
  3930. statements of the obvious deliverances of common sense, expressed with
  3931. their natural limitations. They cannot be bettered in their character of pre-
  3932. sentations of facts which have to be accepted by any satisfactory system of
  3933. philosophy.
  3934.  
  3935. The first point to notice is that in some of his statements Locke comes
  3936. very near to the explicit formulation of an organic philosophy of the type
  3937. being developed here. It was only his failure to notice that his problem
  3938. required a more drastic revision of traditional categories than that which
  3939. he actually effected, that led to a vagueness of statement, and the intru-
  3940. sion of inconsistent elements. It was this conservative, other side of Locke
  3941. which led to his sceptical overthrow by Hume. In his turn. Hume (despite
  3942. his explicit repudiation in his Treatise, Part I, Sect. VI) was a thorough
  3943. conservative, and in his explanation of mentality and its content never
  3944. moved away from the subject-predicate habits of thought [81] which had
  3945. been impressed on the European mind by the overemphasis on Aristotle's
  3946. logic during the long mediaeval period. In reference to this twist of mind,
  3947. probably Aristotle was not an Aristotelian. But Hume's sceptical reduction
  3948. of knowledge entirely depends (for its arguments) on the tacit presupposi-
  3949. tion of the mind as subject and of its contents as predicates— a presuppo-
  3950. sition which explicitly he repudiates.
  3951.  
  3952. The merit of Locke's Essay Concerning^ Human Understanding is its
  3953. adequacy, and not its consistency. He gives the most dispassionate descrip-
  3954. tions of those various elements in experience which common sense never
  3955. lets slip. Unfortunately he is hampered by inappropriate metaphysical
  3956. categories which he never criticized. He should have widened the title
  3957. of his book into 'An Essay Concerningt Experience/ His true topic is the
  3958. analysis of the types of experience enjoyed by an actual entity. But this
  3959. complete experience is nothing other than what the actual entity is in it-
  3960. self, for itself. I will adopt the pre-Kantian phraseology, and say that the
  3961. experience enjoyed by an actual entity is that entity formaliter. By this I
  3962. mean that the entity, when considered 'formally,' is being described in re-
  3963. spect to those forms of its constitution whereby it is that individual entity
  3964. with its own measure of absolute self-realization. Its 'ideas of things' are
  3965. what other things are for it. In the phraseology of these lectures, they are
  3966. its 'feelings.' The actual entity is composite and analysable; and its 'ideas'
  3967. express how, and in what sense, other things are components in its own
  3968.  
  3969.  
  3970.  
  3971. 52 Discussions and Applications
  3972.  
  3973. constitution. Thus the form of its constitution is to be found by an analy-
  3974. sis of the Lockian ideas. Locke talks of 'understanding 7 and 'perception/
  3975. He should have started with a more general neutral term to express the
  3976. synthetic concrescence whereby the many things of the universe become
  3977. the one actual entity. Accordingly I have adopted the term 'prehension/
  3978. to express the activity whereby an actual entity effects its own concretion
  3979. of other things.
  3980.  
  3981. [82] The 'prehension 7 of one actual entity by another actual entity is the
  3982. complete transaction, analysable into the objectification of the former
  3983. entity as one of the data for the latter, and into the fully clothed feeling
  3984. whereby the datum is absorbed into the subjective satisfaction— 'clothed 7
  3985. with the various elements of its 'subjective form. 7 But this definition can be
  3986. stated more generally so as to include the case of the prehension of an
  3987. eternal object by an actual entity; namely, The 'positive prehension 7 of an
  3988. entity by an actual entity is the complete transaction analysable into the
  3989. ingression, or objectification, of that entity as a datum for feeling, and
  3990. into the feeling whereby this datum is absorbed into the subjective satis-
  3991. faction. I also discard Locke's term 'idea. 7 Instead of that term, the other
  3992. things, in their limited r61es as elements for the actual entity in question,
  3993. are called 'objects 7 for that thing. There are four main types of objects,
  3994. namely, 'eternal objects, 7 'propositions, 7 'objectified 7 actual entities and
  3995. nexus. These 'eternal objects 7 are Locke's ideas as explained in his Essay
  3996. (II, I, l),t where he writes:
  3997. Idea is the object of thinking. — Every man being conscious to himself
  3998. that he thinks, and that which his mind is applied about, whilst think-
  3999. ing, being the ideas that are there, it is past doubt that men have in
  4000. their mind several ideas, such as aret those expressed by the words,
  4001. "whiteness, hardness, sweetness, thinking, motion, man, elephant, army,
  4002. drunkenness, 77 and others.
  4003. But latert (III, III, 2), when discussing general terms (and subcon-
  4004. sciously, earlier in his discussion of 'substance 7 in II, XXIII), he adds par-
  4005. enthetically another type of ideas which are practically what I term 'ob-
  4006. jectified actual entities' and 'nexus. 7 He calls them 'ideas of particular
  4007. things 7 ; and he explains why, in general, such ideas cannot have their
  4008. separate names. The reason is simple and undeniable: there are too many
  4009. actual entities. He writes: "But it is beyond the power of human capacity
  4010. to frame and retain distinct ideas of all the particular things we meet with:
  4011. every bird and beast men saw, [83] every tree and plant that affected the
  4012. senses, could not find a place in the most capacious understanding. 77 The
  4013. context shows that it is not the impossibility of an 'idea 7 of any particular
  4014. thing which is the seat of the difficulty; it is solely their number. This no-
  4015. tion of a direct 'idea' (or 'feeling') of an actual entity is a presupposition of
  4016. all common sense; Santayana ascribes it to 'animal faith. 7 But it accords
  4017. very ill with the sensationalist theory of knowledge which can be derived
  4018.  
  4019.  
  4020.  
  4021. Fact and Form 53
  4022.  
  4023. from other parts of Locke's writings. Both Locke and Descartes wrestle
  4024. with exactly the same difficulty.
  4025.  
  4026. The principle that I am adopting is that consciousness presupposes ex-
  4027. perience, and not experience consciousness. It is a special element in the
  4028. subjective forms of some feelings. Thus an actual entity may, or may not,
  4029. be conscious of some part of its experience. Its experience is its complete
  4030. formal constitution, including its consciousness, if any. Thus, in Locke's
  4031. phraseology, its 'ideas of particular things' are those other things exercising
  4032. their function as felt components of its constitution. Locke would only term
  4033. them 'ideas' when these objectifications belong to that region of experience
  4034. lit up by consciousness. In Section 4t of the same chapter, he definitely
  4035. makes all knowledge to be "founded in particular things. 77 He writes:
  4036. ". . . yet a distinct name for every particular thing would not be of any
  4037. great use for the improvement of knowledge: which, though founded in
  4038. particular things, 1 * enlarges itself by general views; to which things reduced
  4039. into sortst under general names, are properly subservient/ 7 Thus for Locke,
  4040. in this passage, there are not first the qualities and then the conjectural
  4041. particular things; but conversely. Also he illustrates his meaning of a 'par-
  4042. ticular thing' by a leaf/ a 'crow, 7 a 'sheep, 7 a 'grain of sand. 7 So he is not
  4043. thinking of a particular patch of colour, or other sense-datum. 17 For ex-
  4044. ample, [84] in Section 7 of the same chapter, in reference to children he
  4045. writes: "The ideas of the nurse and the mother are well framed in their
  4046. minds; and, like pictures of them there, represent only those individuals. 77
  4047. This doctrine of Locke's must be compared with Descartes' doctrine of
  4048. 'realitas objectiva. 7 Locke inherited the dualistic separation of mind from
  4049. body. If he had started with the one fundamental notion of an actual en-
  4050. tity, '.he complex of ideas disclosed in consciousness would have at once
  4051. turned into the complex constitution of the actual entity disclosed in its
  4052. own consciousness, so far as it is conscious— fitfully, partially, or not at all.
  4053. Locke definitely states how ideas become general. In Section 6 of the
  4054. chapter he writes: ". . . and ideas become general by separating from
  4055. them the circumstances of time, and place, and any other ideas that may
  4056. determine them to this or that particular existence." Thus for Locke the
  4057. abstract idea is preceded by the 'idea of a particular existent'; "[children]
  4058. frame an idea which they find those many particulars do partake in. 7 ' This
  4059. statement of Locke's should be compared with the Category of Con-
  4060. ceptual Valuation, which is the fourth categoreal obligation.
  4061.  
  4062. Locke discusses the constitution of actual things under the term 'real
  4063. essences.' He writes (Section 15,t same chapter): "And thus the real in-
  4064.  
  4065. 16 My italics.
  4066.  
  4067. 17 As he is in I, II, 1 5, where he writes, "The senses at first let in particular
  4068. ideas, and furnish the yet empty cabinet; . . ." Note the distinction between
  4069. 'particular ideas' and 'ideas of particular things/
  4070.  
  4071.  
  4072.  
  4073. 54 Discussions and Applications
  4074.  
  4075. ternal (but generally in substances unknown) constitution of things,
  4076. whereon their discoverable qualities depend, may be called their 'essence/ "
  4077. The point is that Locke entirely endorses the doctrine that an actual entity
  4078. arises out of a complex constitution involving other entities, though, t by
  4079. his unfortunate use of such terms as 'cabinet/ he puts less emphasis on the
  4080. notion of 'process 7 than does Hume.
  4081.  
  4082. Locke has in fact stated in his work one main problem for the philosophy
  4083. of organism. He discovers that the mind is a unity arising out of the active
  4084. prehension of ideas into one concrete thing. Unfortunately, he presup-
  4085. poses both the Cartesian dualism whereby minds are one kind of par-
  4086. ticulars, and natural entities are another kind [85] of particulars, and also
  4087. the subject-predicate dogma. He is thus, in company with Descartes, driven
  4088. to a theory of representative perception. For example, in one of the quota-
  4089. tions already cited,t he writes: "and, like pictures of them there, represent
  4090. only those individuals. 77 This doctrine obviously creates an insoluble prob-
  4091. lem for epistemology, only to be solved either by some sturdy make-believe
  4092. of 'animal faith, 7 with Santayana, or by some doctrine of illusorinesst—
  4093. some doctrine of mere appearance, inconsistent if taken as real — with
  4094. Bradley. Anyhow 'representative perception 7 can never, within its own
  4095. metaphysical doctrines, produce the title deeds to guarantee the validity of
  4096. the representation of fact by idea.
  4097.  
  4098. Locke and the philosophers of his epoch— the seventeenth and eigh-
  4099. teenth centuries— are misled by one fundamental misconception. It is the
  4100. assumption, unconscious and uncriticized, that logical simplicity can be
  4101. identified with priority in the process constituting an experient occasion.
  4102. Locke founded the first two books of his Essay on this presupposition, with
  4103. thet exception of his early sections on 'substance, 7 which are quoted imme-
  4104. diately below. In the third and fourth books of the Essay he abandons this
  4105. presupposition, again unconsciously as it seems.
  4106.  
  4107. This identification of priority in logic with priority in practice has
  4108. vitiated thought and procedure from the first discovery of mathematics and
  4109. logic by the Greeks. For example, some of the worst defects in educational
  4110. procedure have been due to it. Locke's nearest approach to the philosophy
  4111. of organism, and— from the point of view of that doctrine— his main over-
  4112. sight, are best exemplified by the first section of his chapter, 'Of our Com-
  4113. plex Ideas of Substances 7 (II, XXIII, 1). He writes:
  4114.  
  4115. The mind, being, as I have declared, furnished with a great number
  4116. of the simple ideas conveyed in by the senses, as they are found in
  4117. exterior things, or by reflection on its own operations, takes notice,
  4118. also, that a certain number of these simple ideas go constantly to-
  4119. gether; [86] which being presumed to belong to one thing, and words
  4120. being suited to common apprehensions, and made use of for quick dis-
  4121. patch, are called, so united in one subject, by one name; which, by in-
  4122. advertency, we are apt afterward to talk of and consider as one simple
  4123. idea, which indeed is a complication of many ideas together: because,
  4124.  
  4125.  
  4126.  
  4127. Fact and Form 55
  4128.  
  4129. as I have said, not imagining how these simple ideas can subsist by
  4130. themselves, we accustom ourselves to suppose some substratum
  4131. wherein they do subsist, and from which they do result; which there-
  4132. fore we call "substance/'
  4133.  
  4134. In this section, Locke's first statement, which is the basis of the re-
  4135. mainder of the section, is exactly the primary assumption of the philosophy
  4136. of organism: "The mind, being . . . furnished with a great number of the
  4137. simple ideas conveyed in by the senses, as they are found in exterior
  4138. things, . . ." Here the last phrase, 'as they are found in exterior things/
  4139. asserted what later I shall call the vector character of the primary feelings.
  4140. The universals involved obtain that status by reason of the fact that 'they
  4141. are found in exterior things' This is Locke's assertion and it is the assertion
  4142. of the philosophy of organism. It can also be conceived as a development
  4143. of Descartes' doctrine of 'realitas objectiva. 7 The universals are the only
  4144. elements in the data describable by concepts, because concepts are merely
  4145. the analytic functioning of universals. But the 'exterior things/ although
  4146. they are not expressible by concepts in respect to their individual particu-
  4147. larity, are no less data for feeling; so that the concrescent actuality arises
  4148. from feeling their status of individual particularity; and thus that particu-
  4149. larity is included as an element from which feelings originate, and which
  4150. they concern.
  4151.  
  4152. The sentence later proceeds with, "a certain number of these simple
  4153. ideas go constantly together." This can only mean that in the immediate
  4154. perception 'a certain number of these simple ideas' are found together in an
  4155. exterior thing, and that the recollection of antecedent moments of experi-
  4156. ence discloses that the same fact, of [87] togetherness in an exterior thing,
  4157. holds for the same set of simple ideas. Again, the philosophy of organism
  4158. agrees that this description is true for moments of immediate experience.
  4159. But Locke, owing to the fact that he veils his second premise under the
  4160. phrase 'go constantly together,' omits to consider the question whether the
  4161. 'exterior things' of the successive moments are to be identified.
  4162.  
  4163. The answer of the philosophy of organism is that, in the sense in which
  4164. Locke is here speaking, the exterior things of successive moments are not
  4165. to be identified with each other. Each exterior thing is either one actual
  4166. entity, or (more frequently) is a nexus of actual entities with imme-
  4167. diacies mutually contemporary. For the sake of simplicity we will speak
  4168. only of the simpler case where the 'exterior thing' means one actual entity
  4169. at the moment in question. But what Locke is explicitly concerned with is
  4170. the notion of the self-identity of the one enduring physical body which lasts
  4171. for years, or for seconds, or for ages. He is considering the current philo-
  4172. sophical notion of an individualized particular substance (in the Aristot-
  4173. elian sense) which undergoes adventures of change, retaining its substantial
  4174. form amid transition oft accidents. Throughout his Essay, he in effect re-
  4175. tains this notion while rightly insisting on its vagueness and obscurity. The
  4176. philosophy of organism agrees with Locke and Hume, that the non-in-
  4177.  
  4178.  
  4179.  
  4180. 56 Discussions and Applications
  4181.  
  4182. dividualized substantial form is nothing else than the collectiqn of uni-
  4183. versal— or ? more accurately, the one complex universal— common to the
  4184. succession of 'exterior things' at successive moments respectively. In other
  4185. words, an 'exterior thing' is either one 'actual entity/ or is a 'society' with a
  4186. 'defining characteristic' For the organic philosophy, these 'exterior things'
  4187. (in the former sense) are the final concrete actualities. The individualized
  4188. substance (of Locke) must be construed to be the historic route constituted
  4189. by some society of fundamental 'exterior things,' stretching from the first
  4190. 'thing' to the last 'thing/
  4191.  
  4192. [88] But Locke, throughout his Essay, rightly insists that the chief ingre-
  4193. dient in the notion of 'substance' is the notion of 'power/ The philosophy
  4194. of organism holds that,t in order to understand 'power/ we must have a
  4195. correct notion of how each individual actual entity contributes to the
  4196. datum from which its successors arise and to which they must conform.
  4197. The reason why the doctrine of power is peculiarly relevant to the en-
  4198. during things, which the philosophy of Locke's day conceived as individual-
  4199. ized substances, is that any likeness between the successive occasions of
  4200. at historic route procures a corresponding identity between their contribu-
  4201. tions to the datum of any subsequent actual entity; and it therefore secures
  4202. a corresponding intensification in the imposition of conformity. The princi-
  4203. ple is the same as that which holds for the more sporadic occasions in
  4204. empty space; but the uniformity along the historic route increases the de-
  4205. gree of conformity which that route exacts from the future. In particular
  4206. each historic route of like occasions tends to prolong itself, by reason of the
  4207. weight of uniform inheritance derivable from its members. The philosophy
  4208. of organism abolishes the detached mind. Mental activity is one of the
  4209. modes of feeling belonging to all actual entities in some degree, but only
  4210. amounting to conscious intellectuality in some actual entities. This higher
  4211. grade of mental activity is the intellectual self analysis of the entity in an
  4212. earlier stage of incompletion, effected by intellectual feelings produced in
  4213. a later stage of concrescence. 18
  4214.  
  4215. The perceptive constitution of the actual entity presents the problem,
  4216. How can the other actual entities, each with its own formal existence, also
  4217. enter objectively into the perceptive constitution of the actual entity in
  4218. question? This is the problem of the solidarity of the universe. The classical
  4219. doctrines of universals and particulars, of subject and predicate, of individ-
  4220. ual substances not present in other individual substances, of [89] the exter-
  4221. nality of relations, alike render this problem incapable of solution. The
  4222. answer given by the organic philosophy is the doctrine of prehensions, in-
  4223. volved in concrescent integrations, and terminating in a definite, complex
  4224. unity of feeling. To be actual must mean that all actual things are alike ob-
  4225. jects, enjoying objective immortality in fashioning creative actions; and
  4226. that all actual things are subjects, each prehending the universe from which
  4227.  
  4228. 18 Cf. Part III, Ch. V.
  4229.  
  4230.  
  4231.  
  4232. Fact and Form 57
  4233.  
  4234. it arises. The creative action is the universe always becoming one in a par-
  4235. ticular unity of self-experience, and thereby adding to the multiplicity
  4236. which is the universe as many. This insistent concrescence into unity is
  4237. the outcome of the ultimate self-identity of each entity. No entity— be it
  4238. 'universal' or 'particular'— can play disjoined roles. Self-identity requires
  4239. that every entity have one conjoined, self-consistent function, whatever be
  4240. the complexity of that function.
  4241.  
  4242. SECTION VII
  4243.  
  4244. There is another side of Locke, which is his doctrine of power/ This
  4245. doctrine is a better illustration of his admirable adequacy than of his con-
  4246. sistency; there is no escape from Hume's demonstration that no such doc-
  4247. trine is compatible with a purely sensationalist philosophy. The establish-
  4248. ment of such a philosophy, though derivative from Locke, was not his
  4249. explicit purpose. Every philosophical school in the course of its history
  4250. requires two presiding philosophers. One of them under the influence of
  4251. the main doctrines of the school should survey experience with some ade-
  4252. quacy, but inconsistently. The other philosopher should reduce the doc-
  4253. trines of the school to a rigid consistency; he will thereby effect a reductio
  4254. ad absurdum. No school of thought has performed its full service to
  4255. philosophy until these men have appeared. In this way the school of sensa-
  4256. tionalist empiricism derives its importance from Locke and Hume.
  4257.  
  4258. Locke introduces his doctrine of 'power' as follows (II, XXI, L3t)*
  4259.  
  4260. This idea how got.— The mind being [90] every day informed, by
  4261. the senses, of the alteration of those simple ideas it observes in things
  4262. without, and taking notice how one comes to an end and ceases to
  4263. be, and another begins to exist which was not before; reflecting also on
  4264. what passes within itself, and observing a constant change of its ideas,
  4265. sometimes by the impression of outward objects on the senses, and
  4266. sometimes by the determination of its own choice; and concluding,
  4267. from what it has so constantly observed to have been, that the like
  4268. changes will for the future be made in the same things! by like agents,
  4269. and by the like ways; considers in one thing the possibility of having
  4270. any of its simple ideas changed, and in another the possibility of
  4271. making that change; and so comes by that idea which we call "power."
  4272. Thus we say, fire has a power to melt gold; . . . and gold has a power
  4273. to be melted: ... In which and thet like cases, the power we con-
  4274. sider is in reference to the change of perceivable ideas: for we cannot
  4275. observe any alteration to be made in, or operation upon, any thing,
  4276. but by the observable change of its sensible ideas; nor conceive any
  4277. alteration to be made, but by conceiving a change of some of its
  4278. ideas. . . .* Power thus considered is twofold; viz. as able to make, or
  4279. able to receive, any change: the one may be called "active," and the
  4280. other "passive," power. . . .* I confess power includes in it some kind
  4281.  
  4282.  
  4283.  
  4284. 58 Discussions and Applications
  4285.  
  4286. of relation,— a relation to action or change; as, indeed, which of our
  4287. ideas, of what kind soever, when attentively considered, does not?
  4288. For our ideas of extension, duration, and number, do they not all
  4289. contain in them a secret relation of the parts? Figure and motion have
  4290. something relative in them much more visibly. And sensible qualities,
  4291. as colours and smells, etc., what are they but the powers of different
  4292. bodies in relation to our perception? . . . Our idea therefore of power,
  4293. I think, may well have a place amongst other simple ideas, and be
  4294. considered as one of them, being one of those that make a principal
  4295. ingredient in our complex ideas of substances, as we shall hereafter
  4296. have occasion to observe.
  4297.  
  4298. [91] In this important passage, Locke enunciates the main doctrines of
  4299. the philosophy of organism, namely: the principle of relativity; the rela-
  4300. tional character of eternal objects, whereby they constitute the forms of
  4301. the objectifications of actual entities for each other; the composite char-
  4302. acter of an actual entity (i.e., a substance); the notion of 'power' as making
  4303. a principal ingredient in that of actual entity (substance). In this latter
  4304. notion, Locke adumbrates both the ontological principle, and also the
  4305. principle that the 'power' of one actual entity on the other is simply how
  4306. the former is objectified in the constitution of the other. Thus the prob-
  4307. lem of perception and the problem of power are one and the same, at least
  4308. so far as perception is reduced to mere prehension of actual entities. Per-
  4309. ception, in the sense of consciousness of such prehension, requires the ad-
  4310. ditional factor of the conceptual prehension of eternal objects, and a pro-
  4311. cess of integration of the two factors (cf. Part III).
  4312.  
  4313. Locke's doctrine of 'power' is reproduced in the philosophy of organism
  4314. by the doctrine of the two types of objectification, namely, (a) 'causal
  4315. objectification,' and (p) 'presentational objectification.'
  4316.  
  4317. In 'causal objectification' what is felt subjectively by the objectified ac-
  4318. tual entity is transmitted objectively to the concrescent actualities which
  4319. supersede it. In Locke's phraseology the objectified actual entity is then
  4320. exerting 'power.' In this type of objectification the eternal objects, rela-
  4321. tional between object and subject, express the formal constitution of the
  4322. objectified actual entity.
  4323.  
  4324. In 'presentational objectification' the relational eternal objects fall into
  4325. two sets, one set contributed by the 'extensive' perspective of the perceived
  4326. from the position of the perceiver, and the other set by the antecedent con-
  4327. crescent phases of the perceiver. What is ordinarily termed 'perception' is
  4328. consciousness of presentational objectification. But according to the phi-
  4329. losophy of organism there can be consciousness of both types of objectifi-
  4330. cation. There can be such consciousness of both [92] types because, ac-
  4331. cording to this philosophy, the knowable is the complete nature of the
  4332. knower, at least such phases of it as are antecedent to that operation of
  4333. knowing.
  4334.  
  4335. Locke misses one essential doctrine, namely, that the doctrine of interna 1
  4336.  
  4337.  
  4338.  
  4339. Fact and Form 59
  4340.  
  4341. relations makes it impossible to attribute 'change 7 to any actual entity.
  4342. Every actual entity is what it is, and is with its definite status in the
  4343. universe, determined by its internal relations to other actual entities.
  4344. 'Change' is the description of the adventures of eternal objects in the
  4345. evolving universe of actual things.
  4346.  
  4347. The doctrine of internal relations introduces another consideration
  4348. which cannot be overlooked without error. Locke considers the 'real es-
  4349. sence' and the 'nominal essence' of things. But on the theory of the gen-
  4350. eral relativity of actual things between each other, and of the internality of
  4351. these relations, there are two distinct notions hidden under the term 'real
  4352. essence/ both of importance. Locke writes (III, III, 15) :
  4353. Essence may be taken for the being of any thing, whereby it is what it
  4354. is. And thus the real internal (but generally in substances unknown)
  4355. constitution of things, whereon their discoverable qualities depend,
  4356. may be called their "essence/ 7 ... It is true, there is ordinarily supposed
  4357. a real constitution of the sorts of things: and it is past doubt there
  4358. must be some real constitution, on which any collection of simple
  4359. ideas co-existing must depend. But it being evident that things are
  4360. ranked under names into sorts or species only as they agree to certain
  4361. abstract ideas to which we have annexed those t names, the essence of
  4362. each genus or sort comes to be nothing but that abstract idea, which
  4363. the general or "sortal" (if I may have leave so to call it from "sort," as I
  4364. do "general" from genus) name stands for. And thist we shall find to
  4365. be that which the word "essence" imparts in its mostt familiar use.
  4366. These two sorts of essences, I suppose, may not unfitly be termed, the
  4367. one the "real," the other the "nominal," essence.
  4368.  
  4369. [93] The fundamental notion of the philosophy of organism is expressed
  4370. in Locke's phrase, "it is past doubt there must be some real constitution,
  4371. on which any collection of simple ideas co-existing must depend." Locke
  4372. makes it plain (cf. II, II, 1) that by a 'simple idea' he means the ingression
  4373. in the actual entity (illustrated by 'a piece of wax/ 'a piece of ice/ 'a rose')
  4374. of some abstract quality which is not complex (illustrated by 'softness/
  4375. 'warmth/ 'whiteness') . For Locke such simple ideas, coexisting^ in an actual
  4376. entity, require a real constitution for that entity. Now in the philosophy of
  4377. organism, passing beyond Locke's explicit statement, the notion of a real
  4378. constitution is taken to mean that the eternal objects function by intro-
  4379. ducing the multiplicity of actual entities as constitutive of the actual en-
  4380. tity in question. Thus the constitution is 'real' because it assigns its status
  4381. in the real world to the actual entity. In other words the actual entity, in
  4382. virtue of being what it is, is also where it is. It is somewhere because it is
  4383. some actual thing with its correlated actual world. This is the direct denial
  4384. of the Cartesian doctrine, ". . . an existent thing which requires nothing
  4385. but itself in order to exist." It is also inconsistent with Aristotle's phrase,
  4386. "neither asserted of a subject nor present in a subject."
  4387. I am certainly not maintaining that Locke grasped explicitly the impli-
  4388.  
  4389.  
  4390.  
  4391. 60 Discussions and Applications
  4392.  
  4393. cations of his words as thus developed for the philosophy of organism.
  4394. But it is a short step from a careless phrase to a flash of insight; nor is it un-
  4395. believable that Locke saw further into metaphysical problems than some
  4396. of his followers. But abandoning the question of what Locke had in his
  4397. own mind, the 'organic doctrine' demands a 'real essence 7 in the sense of a
  4398. complete analysis of the relations, and inter-relations of the actual entities
  4399. which are formative of the actual entity in question, and an 'abstract es-
  4400. sence' in which the specified actual entities are replaced by the notions of
  4401. unspecified entities in such a combination: this is the notion of an un-
  4402. specified actual entity. Thus the real [94] essence involves real objectifica-
  4403. tions of specified actual entities; the abstract essence is a complex eternal
  4404. object. There is nothing self-contradictory in the thought of many actual
  4405. entities with the same abstract essence; but there can only be one actual
  4406. entity with the same real essence. For the real essence indicates 'where'
  4407. the entity is, that is to say, its status in the real world; the abstract essence
  4408. omits the particularity of the status.
  4409.  
  4410. The philosophy of organism in its appeal to the facts can thus support
  4411. itself by an appeal to the insight of John Locke, who in British philosophy
  4412. is the analogue to Plato, in the epoch of his life, in personal endowments,
  4413. in width of experience, and in dispassionate statement of conflicting
  4414. intuitions.
  4415.  
  4416. This doctrine of organism is the attempt to describe the world as a
  4417. process of generation of individual actual entities, each with its own ab-
  4418. solute self-attainment. This concrete finality of the individual is nothing
  4419. else than a decision referent beyond itself. The 'perpetual perishing' (cf.
  4420. Locke, II, XIV, It) of individual absoluteness is thus foredoomed. But the
  4421. 'perishing' of absoluteness is the attainment of 'objective immortality.'
  4422. This last conception expresses the further element in the doctrine of or-
  4423. ganism—that the process of generation is to be described in terms of actual
  4424. entities.
  4425.  
  4426.  
  4427.  
  4428. CHAPTER II
  4429. THE EXTENSIVE CONTINUUM
  4430.  
  4431. SECTION I
  4432.  
  4433. [95] We must first consider the perceptive mode in which there is clear,
  4434. distinct consciousness of the 'extensive' relations of the world. These rela-
  4435. tions include the 'extensiveness' of space and the 'extensiveness' of time.
  4436. Undoubtedly, this clarity, at least in regard to space, is obtained only in
  4437. ordinary perception through the senses. This mode of perception is here
  4438. termed 'presentational immediacy/ In this 'mode' the contemporary world
  4439. is consciously prehended as a continuum of extensive relations.
  4440.  
  4441. It cannot be too clearly understood that some chief notions of European
  4442. thought were framed under the influence of a misapprehension, only par-
  4443. tially corrected by the scientific progress of the last century. This mistake
  4444. consists in the confusion of mere potentiality with actuality. Continuity
  4445. concerns what is potential; whereas actuality is incurably atomic.
  4446.  
  4447. This misapprehension is promoted by the neglect of the principle that,
  4448. so far as physicalt relations are concerned, contemporary events happen in
  4449. causal independence of each other. 1 This principle will have to be ex-
  4450. plained later, in connection with an examination of process and of time. It
  4451. receives an exemplification in the character of our perception of the world
  4452. of contemporary actual entities. That contemporary world is objectified
  4453. [96] for us as 'realitas objectiva, 7 illustrating bare extension with its various
  4454. parts discriminated by differences of sense-data, t These qualities, such as
  4455. colours, sounds, bodily feelings, tastes, smells, together with the perspec-
  4456. tives introduced by extensive relationships, are the relational eternal ob-
  4457. jects whereby the contemporary actual entities are elements in our consti-
  4458. tution. This is the type of objectification which (in Sect. VII of the
  4459. previous chapter) has been termed 'presentational objectification.'
  4460.  
  4461. In this way, by reason of the principle of contemporary independence,
  4462. the contemporary world is objectified for us under the aspect of passive
  4463. potentiality. The very sense-data by which its parts are differentiated are
  4464. supplied by antecedent states of our own bodies, and so is their distribution
  4465. in contemporary space. Our direct perception of the contemporary world
  4466. is thus reduced to extension, defining (i) our own geometrical perspectives,
  4467. and (ii) possibilities of mutual perspectives for other contemporary entities
  4468.  
  4469. 1 This principle lies on the surface of the fundamental Einsteinian formula for
  4470. the physical continuum.
  4471.  
  4472. 61
  4473.  
  4474.  
  4475.  
  4476. 62 Discussions and Applications
  4477.  
  4478. inter se, and (iii) possibilities of division. These possibilities of division con-
  4479. stitute the external world a continuum. For a continuum is divisible; so
  4480. far as the contemporary world is divided by actual entities, it is not a con-
  4481. tinuum, but is atomic. Thus the contemporary world is perceived with its
  4482. potentiality for extensive division, and not in its actual atomic division.
  4483.  
  4484. The contemporary world as perceived by the senses is the datum for
  4485. contemporary actuality, and is therefore continuous— divisible but not
  4486. divided. The contemporary world is in fact divided and atomic, being a
  4487. multiplicity of definite actual entities. These contemporary actual entities
  4488. are divided from each other, and are not themselves divisible into other
  4489. contemporary actual entities. This antithesis will have to be discussed later
  4490. (cf. Part IV). But it is necessary to adumbrate it here.
  4491.  
  4492. This limitation of the way in which the contemporary actual entities are
  4493. relevant to the 'formal' existence of the subject in question is the first
  4494. example of the general [97] principle, that objectification relegates into ir-
  4495. relevance, or into a subordinate relevance, the full constitution of the ob-
  4496. jectified entity. Some real component in the objectified entity assumes the
  4497. r61e of being how that particular entity is a datum in the experience of the
  4498. subject. In this case, the objectified contemporaries are only directly rele-
  4499. vant to the subject in their character of arising from a datum which is an
  4500. extensive continuum. They do, in fact, atomize this continuum; but the
  4501. aboriginal potentiality, which they include and realize, is what they con-
  4502. tribute as the relevant factor in their objectifications. They thus exhibit the
  4503. community of contemporary actualities as a common world with mathe-
  4504. matical relations— where the term 'mathematical' is used in the sense in
  4505. which it would have been understood by Plato, Euclid, and Descartes,
  4506. before the modern discovery of the true definition of pure mathematics.
  4507.  
  4508. The bare mathematical potentialities of the extensive continuum re-
  4509. quire an additional content in order to assume the role of real objects for
  4510. the subject. This content is supplied by the eternal objects t termed sense-
  4511. data. These objects are 'given' for the experience of the subject. Their
  4512. givenness does not arise from the 'decision' of the contemporary entities
  4513. which are thus objectified. It arises from the functioning of the antecedent
  4514. physical body of the subject; and this functioning can in its turn be ana-
  4515. lysed as representing the influence of the more remote past, a past com-
  4516. mon alike to the subject and to its contemporary actual entities. Thus
  4517. these sense-data are eternal objects playing a complex relational role;
  4518. they connect the actual entities of the past with the actual entities of the
  4519. contemporary world, and thereby effect objectifications of the contem-
  4520. porary things and of the past things. For instance, we see the contemporary
  4521. chair, but we see it with our eyes; and we touch the contemporary chair,
  4522. but we touch it with our hands. Thus colours objectify the chair in one
  4523. way, and objectify the eyes in another way, as elements in the experience
  4524. of the subject. [95] Also touch objectifies the chair in one way, and ob-
  4525.  
  4526.  
  4527.  
  4528. The Extensive Continuum 63
  4529.  
  4530. jectifies the hands in another way, as elements in the experience of the
  4531. subject. But the eyes and the hands are in the past (the almost immediate
  4532. past) and the chair is in the present The chair, thus objectified, is the
  4533. objectification of a contemporary nexus of actual entities in its unity as one
  4534. nexus. This nexus is illustrated as to its constitution by the spatial region,
  4535. with its perspective relations. This region is, in fact, atomized by the mem-
  4536. bers of the nexus. By the operation of the Category of Transmutation (cf.
  4537. Parts III and IV), in the objectification an abstraction is made from the
  4538. multiplicity of members and from all components of their formal consti-
  4539. tutions, except the occupation of this region. This prehension, in the
  4540. particular example considered, will be termed the prehension of a 'chair-
  4541. image/ Also the intervention of the past is not confined to antecedent eyes
  4542. and hands. There is a more remote past throughout nature external to the
  4543. body. The direct relevance of this remote past, relevant by reason of its
  4544. direct objectification in the immediate subject, is practically negligible, so
  4545. far as concerns prehensions of a strictly physical type.
  4546.  
  4547. But external nature has an indirect relevance by the transmission
  4548. through it of analogous prehensions. In this way there are in it various
  4549. historical routes of intermediate objectifications. Such relevant historical
  4550. routes lead up to various parts of the animal body, and transmit into it
  4551. prehensions which form the physical influence of the external environment
  4552. on the animal body. But this external environment which is in the past of
  4553. the concrescent subject is also, with negligible exceptions, in the past of
  4554. the nexus which is the objectified chair-image. If there be a 'real chair/
  4555. there will be another historical route of objectifications from nexus to
  4556. nexus in this environment. The members of each nexus will be mutually
  4557. contemporaries. Also the historical route will lead up to the nexus which
  4558. is the chair-image. The complete nexus, composed of this historical route
  4559. and the [99] chair-image, will form a 'corpuscular' society. This society is
  4560. the 'real chair/
  4561.  
  4562. The prehensions of the concrescent subject and the formal constitutions
  4563. of the members of the contemporary nexus which is the chair-image are
  4564. thus conditioned by the properties of the same environment in the past.
  4565. The animal body is so constructed that, with rough accuracy and in
  4566. normal conditions, important emphasis is thus laid upon those regions in
  4567. the contemporary world which are particularly relevant for the future
  4568. existence of the enduring object of which the immediate percipient is one
  4569. occasion.
  4570.  
  4571. A reference to the Category of Transmutation will show that perception
  4572. of contemporary 'images 7 in the mode of 'presentational immediacy' is an
  4573. 'impure' prehension. The subsidiary 'pure 7 physical prehensions are the
  4574. components which provide some definite information as to the physical
  4575. world; the subsidiary 'pure 7 mental prehensions are the components by
  4576. reason of which the theory of 'secondary qualities 7 was introduced into the
  4577.  
  4578.  
  4579.  
  4580. 64 Discussions and Applications
  4581.  
  4582. theory of perception. The account here given traces back these secondary
  4583. qualities to their root in physical prehensions expressed by the 'wiihness of
  4584. the body/
  4585.  
  4586. If the familiar correlations between physical paths and the life-histories
  4587. of a chair and of the animal body are not satisfied, we are apt to say that
  4588. our perceptions are delusive. The word 'delusive'" is all very well as a tech-
  4589. nical term; but it must not be misconstrued to mean that what we have
  4590. directly perceived, we have not directly perceived. Our direct perception,
  4591. via our senses, of an immediate extensive shape, in a certain geometrical
  4592. perspective to ourselves, and in certain general geometrical relations to the
  4593. contemporary world, remains an ultimate fact. Our inferences are at fault.
  4594. In Cartesian phraseology, it is a final 'inspectio' (also termed Hntuitio')
  4595. which, when purged of all 'judicium— i.e., of 'inference — is final for belief.
  4596. This whole question of 'delusive' perception must be considered later (cf.
  4597. Part III, Chs. Ill to V) in more [100] detail. We can, however, see at once
  4598. that there are grades of 'delusiveness.' There is the non-delusive case, when
  4599. we see a chair-image and there is a chair. There is the partially delusive case
  4600. when we have been looking in a mirror; in this case, the chair-image we
  4601. see is not the culmination of the corpuscular society of entities which we
  4602. call the real chair. Finally, we may have been taking drugs, so that the
  4603. chair-image we see has no familiar counterpart in any historical route of a
  4604. corpuscular society. Also there are other delusive grades where the lapse of
  4605. time is the main element. These cases are illustrated by our perceptions of
  4606. the heavenly bodies. In delusive cases we are apt, in a confusing way, to
  4607. say that the societies of entities which we did not see but correctly inferred
  4608. are the things that we 'really' saw.
  4609.  
  4610. The conclusion of this discussion is that the ingression of the eternal
  4611. objects termed 'sense-data' t into the experience of a subject cannot be
  4612. construed as the simple objectification of the actual entity to which, in-
  4613. ordinary speech, we ascribe that sense-datum as a quality. The ingression
  4614. involves a complex relationship, whereby the sense-datum emerges as the
  4615. 'given' eternal object by which some past entities are objectified (for ex-
  4616. ample, colour seen with the eyes and bad temper inherited from the
  4617. viscera) and whereby the sense-datum also enters into the objectification
  4618. of a society of actual entities in the contemporary world. Thus a sense-
  4619. datum has ingression into experience by reason of its forming the what of
  4620. a very complex multiple integration of prehensions within that occasion.
  4621. For example, the ingression of a visual sense-datum involves the causal
  4622. objectification of various antecedent bodily organs and the presentational
  4623. objectification of the shape seen, this shape being a nexus of contemporary
  4624. actual entities. In this account of the ingression of sense-data, the animal
  4625. body is nothing more than the most intimately relevant part of the ante-
  4626. cedent settled world. To sum up this account: When we perceive a con-
  4627. temporary extended shape which we term a 'chair/ the sense- [101} data in-
  4628. volved are not necessarily elements in the 'real internal constitution' of this
  4629.  
  4630.  
  4631.  
  4632. The Extensive Continuum 65
  4633.  
  4634. chair-image: they are elements— in some way of feeling— in the 'real in-
  4635. ternal constitutions' of those antecedent organs of the human body with
  4636. which we perceive the 'chair/ The direct recognition of such antecedent
  4637. actual entities, with which we perceive contemporaries, is hindered and,
  4638. apart from exceptional circumstances, rendered impossible by the spatial
  4639. and temporal vagueness which infect such data. Later (cf. Part III, Chs.
  4640. Ill to V) the whole question of this perception of a nexus vaguely, that is
  4641. to say, without distinction of the actual entities composing it, is discussed
  4642. in terms of the theory of prehensions, and in relation to the Category of
  4643. Transmutation.
  4644.  
  4645.  
  4646.  
  4647. SECTION II
  4648.  
  4649. This account of 'presentational immediacy' presupposes two metaphysi-
  4650. cal assumptions:
  4651.  
  4652. (i) That the actual world, in so far as it is a community of entities
  4653. which are settled, actual, and already become, conditions and limits the
  4654. potentiality for creativeness beyond itself. This 'given' world provides de-
  4655. terminate data in the form of those objectifications of themselves which
  4656. the characters of its actual entities can provide. This is a limitation laid
  4657. upon the general potentiality provided by eternal objects, considered
  4658. merely in respect to the generality of their natures. Thus, relatively to any
  4659. actual entity, there is a 'giver/ world of settled actual entities and a 'real'
  4660. potentiality, which is the datum for creativeness beyond that standpoint.
  4661. This datum, which is the primary phase in the process constituting an
  4662. actual entity, is nothing else than the actual world itself in its character
  4663. of a possibility for the process of being felt. This exemplifies the meta-
  4664. physical principle that every 'being' is a potential for a 'becoming/ The
  4665. actual world is the 'objective content' of each new creation.
  4666.  
  4667. Thus we have always to consider two meanings of [102] potentiality: (a)
  4668. the 'general' potentiality, which is the bundle of possibilities, mutually con-
  4669. sistent or alternative, provided by the multiplicity of eternal objects, and
  4670. (b) the 'real' potentiality, which is conditioned by the data provided by
  4671. the actual world. General potentiality is absolute, and real potentiality is
  4672. relative to some actual entity, taken as a standpoint whereby the actual
  4673. world is denned. It must be remembered that the phrase 'actual world' is
  4674. like 'yesterday' and 'tomorrow/ in that it alters its meaning according to
  4675. standpoint. The actual world must always mean the community of all
  4676. actual entities, including the primordial actual entity called 'God' and
  4677. the temporal actual entities.
  4678.  
  4679. Curiously enough, even at this early stage of metaphysical discussion,
  4680. the influence of the 'relativity theory' of modern physics is important.
  4681. According to the classical 'uniquely serial' view of time, two contemporary
  4682. actual entities define the same actual world. According to the modern view
  4683.  
  4684.  
  4685.  
  4686. 66 Discussions and Applications
  4687.  
  4688. no two actual entities define the same actual world. Actual entities are
  4689. called 'contemporary' when neither belongs to the given* actual world de-
  4690. fined by the other.
  4691.  
  4692. The differences between the actual worlds of a pair of contemporary
  4693. entities, which are in a certain sense 'neighbours/ are negligible for most
  4694. human purposes. Thus the difference between the 'classical' and the 'rela-
  4695. tivity' view of time only rarely has any important relevance. I shall always
  4696. adopt the relativity view; for one reason, because it seems better to accord
  4697. with the general philosophical doctrine of relativity which is presupposed
  4698. in the philosophy of organism; and for another reason, because with rare
  4699. exceptions the classical doctrine can be looked on as a special case of the
  4700. relativity doctrine— a case which does not seem to accord with experimental
  4701. evidence. In other words, the classical view seems to limit a general
  4702. philosophical doctrine; it is the larger assumption; and its consequences,
  4703. taken in conjunction with other scientific principles, seem to be false.
  4704.  
  4705. [J 03] (ii) The second metaphysical assumption is that the real poten-
  4706. tialities relative to all standpoints are coordinated as diverse determinations
  4707. of one extensive continuum. This extensive continuum is one relational
  4708. complex in which all potential objectifications find their niche. It underlies
  4709. the whole world, past, present, and future. Considered in its full generality,
  4710. apart from the additional conditions proper only to the cosmic epoch of
  4711. electrons, protons, molecules, and star-systems, the properties of this con-
  4712. tinuum are very few and do not include the relationships of metrical
  4713. geometry. An extensive continuum is a complex of entities united by the
  4714. various allied relationships of whole to part, and of overlapping so as to
  4715. possess common parts, and of contact, and of other relationships derived
  4716. from these primary relationships. The notion of a 'continuum' involves
  4717. both the property of indefinite divisibility and the property of unbounded
  4718. extension. There are always entities beyond entities, because nonentity is
  4719. no boundary. This extensive continuum expresses the solidarity of all pos-
  4720. sible standpoints throughout the whole process of the world. It is not a fact
  4721. prior to the world; it is the first determination of order— that is, of real
  4722. potentiality— arising out of the general character of the world. In its full
  4723. generality beyond the present epoch, it does not involve shapes, dimen-
  4724. sions, or measurability; these are additional determinations of real po-
  4725. tentiality arising from our cosmic epoch.
  4726.  
  4727. This extensive continuum is 'real/ because it expresses a fact derived
  4728. from the actual world and concerning the contemporary actual world. All
  4729. actual entities are related according to the determinations of this con-
  4730. tinuum; and all possible actual entities in the future must exemplify these
  4731. determinations in their relations with the already actual world. The reality
  4732. of the future is bound up with the reality of this continuum. It is the
  4733. reality of what is potential, in its character of a real component of what is
  4734. actual. Such a real component must be interpreted in \104] terms of the
  4735.  
  4736.  
  4737.  
  4738. The Extensive Continuum 67
  4739.  
  4740. relatedness of prehensions. This task will be undertaken in Chapter V of
  4741. Part IV of these lectures.
  4742.  
  4743. Actual entities atomize the extensive continuum. This continuum is in
  4744. itself merely the potentiality for division; an actual entity effects this
  4745. division. The objectification of the contemporary world merely expresses
  4746. that world in terms of its potentiality for subdivision and in terms of the
  4747. mutual perspectives which any such subdivision will bring into real ef-
  4748. fectiveness. These are the primary governing data for any actual entity;
  4749. for they express how all actual entities are in the solidarity of one world.
  4750. With the becoming of any actual entity what was previously potential in
  4751. the space-time continuum is now the primary real phase in something ac-
  4752. tual. For each process of concrescence a regional standpoint in the world,
  4753. defining a limited potentiality for objectifications, has been adopted. In
  4754. the mere extensive continuum there is no principle to determine what
  4755. regional quanta shall be atomized, so as to form the real perspective stand-
  4756. point for the primary data constituting the basic phase in the concrescence
  4757. of an actual entity. The factors in the actual world whereby this de-
  4758. termination is effected will be discussed at a later stage of this investiga-
  4759. tion. They constitute the initial phase of the 'subjective aim/ This initial
  4760. phase is a direct derivate from God's primordial nature. In this function,
  4761. as in every other, God is the organ of novelty, aiming at intensification.
  4762.  
  4763. In the mere continuum there are contrary potentialities; in the actual
  4764. world there are definite atomic actualities determining one coherent sys-
  4765. tem of real divisions throughout the region of actuality. Every actual entity
  4766. in its relationship to other actual entities is in this sense somewhere in
  4767. the continuum, and arises out of the data provided by this standpoint.
  4768. But in another sense it is everywhere throughout the continuum; for its
  4769. constitution includes the objectifications of the actual world and thereby
  4770. includes the continuum; also the [105] potential objectifications of itself
  4771. contribute to the real potentialities whose solidarity the continuum ex-
  4772. presses. Thus the continuum is present in each actual entity, and each
  4773. actual entity pervades the continuum.
  4774.  
  4775. This conclusion can be stated otherwise. Extension, apart from its
  4776. spatialization and temporalization, is that general scheme of relationships
  4777. providing the capacity that many objects can be welded into the real unity
  4778. of one experience. Thus, an act of experience has an objective scheme of
  4779. extensive order by reason of the double fact that its own perspective stand-
  4780. point has extensive content, and that the other actual entities are objecti-
  4781. fied with the retention of their extensive relationships. These extensive
  4782. relationships are more fundamental than their more special spatial and
  4783. temporal relationships. Extension is the most general scheme of real po-
  4784. tentiality, providing the background for all other organic relations. The
  4785. potential scheme does not determine its own atomization by actual en-
  4786. tities. It is divisible; but its real division by actual entities depends upon
  4787.  
  4788.  
  4789.  
  4790. 68 Discussions and Applications
  4791.  
  4792. more particular characteristics of the actual entities constituting the ante-
  4793. cedent environment. In respect to time, this atomization takes the special
  4794. form 2 of the 'epochal theory of time/ In respect to space, it means that
  4795. every actual entity in the temporal world is to be credited with a spatial
  4796. volume for its perspective standpoint. These conclusions are required by
  4797. the consideration 3 of Zeno's arguments, in connection with the presump-
  4798. tion that an actual entity is an act of experience. The authority of Wil-
  4799. liam James can be quoted in support of this conclusion. He writes: "Either
  4800. your experience is of no content, of no change, or it is of a perceptible
  4801. amount of content or change. Your acquaintance with reality grows liter-
  4802. ally by buds or drops of perception. Intellectually and on reflection you
  4803. can divide these into components, but as immediately given, [106] they
  4804. come totally or not at all." 4 James also refers to Zeno. In substance I agree
  4805. with his argument from Zeno; though I do not think that he allows suf-
  4806. ficiently for those elements in Zeno's paradoxes which are the product of
  4807. inadequate mathematical knowledge. But I agree that a valid argument
  4808. remains after the removal of the invalid parts.
  4809.  
  4810. The argument, so far as it is valid, elicits a contradiction from the two
  4811. premises: (i) that in a becoming something (res vera) becomes, and (ii)
  4812. that every act of becoming is divisible into earlier and later sections which
  4813. are themselves acts of becoming. Consider, for example, an act of becom-
  4814. ing during one second. The act is divisible into two acts, one during the
  4815. earlier half of the second, the other during the later half of the second.
  4816. Thus that which becomes during the whole second presupposes that
  4817. which becomes during the first half-second. Analogously, that which be-
  4818. comes during the first half-second presupposes that which becomes dur-
  4819. ing the first quarter-second, and so on indefinitely. Thus if we consider
  4820. the process of becoming up to the beginning of the second in question,
  4821. and ask what then becomes, no answer can be given. For, whatever creature
  4822. we indicate presupposes an earlier creature which became after the be-
  4823. ginning of the second and antecedently to the indicated t creature. There-
  4824. fore there is nothing which becomes, so as to effect a transition into the
  4825. second in question.
  4826.  
  4827. The difficulty is not evaded by assuming that something becomes at
  4828. each non-extensive instant of time. For at the beginning of the second of
  4829. time there is no next instant at which something can become.
  4830.  
  4831. Zeno in his 'Arrow in Its Flight' seems to have had an obscure grasp of
  4832. this argument. But the introduction of motion brings in irrelevant details.
  4833. The true difficulty is to understand how the arrow survives the lapse of
  4834.  
  4835.  
  4836.  
  4837. 2 Cf. my Science and the Modern World, Ch. VII.
  4838.  
  4839. 3 Cf. loc. cit.; and Part IV of the present work.
  4840.  
  4841. 4 Some Problems of Philosophy, Ch X; my attention was drawn to this pas-
  4842. sage by its quotation in Religion in thef Philosophy of William James, by Pro-
  4843. fessor J. S. Bixler.
  4844.  
  4845.  
  4846.  
  4847. The Extensive Continuum 69
  4848.  
  4849. time. [107] Unfortunately Descartes' treatment of 'endurance' is very
  4850. superficial, and subsequent philosophers have followed his example.
  4851.  
  4852. In his 'Achilles and the Tortoise' Zeno produces an invalid argument
  4853. depending on ignorance of the theory of infinite convergent numerical
  4854. series. Eliminating the irrelevant details of the race and of motion— de-
  4855. tails which have endeared the paradox to the literature of all ages— con-
  4856. sider the first half-second as one act of becoming, the next quarter-second
  4857. as another such act, the next eighth-second as yet another, and so on in-
  4858. definitely. Zeno then illegitimately assumes this infinite series of acts of
  4859. becoming can never be exhausted. But there is no need to assume that an
  4860. infinite series of acts of becoming, with a first act, and each act with an
  4861. immediate successor,! is inexhaustible in the process of becoming. Simple
  4862. arithmetic assures us that the series just indicated will be exhausted in the
  4863. period of one second. The way is then open for the intervention of a new
  4864. act of becoming which lies beyond the whole series. Thus this paradox of
  4865. Zeno is based upon a mathematical fallacy.
  4866.  
  4867. The modification of the *' Arrow' paradox, stated above, brings out the
  4868. principle that every act of becoming must have an immediate successor, if
  4869. we admit that something becomes. For otherwise we cannot point out
  4870. what creature becomes as we enter upon the second in question. But we
  4871. cannot, in the absence of some additional premise, infer that every act of
  4872. becoming must have had an immediate predecessor.
  4873.  
  4874. The conclusion is that in every act of becoming there is the becoming of
  4875. something with temporal extension; but that the act itself is not extensive,
  4876. in the sense that it is divisible into earlier and later acts of becoming which
  4877. correspond to the extensive divisibility of what has become.
  4878.  
  4879. In this section, the doctrine is enunciated that the creature is extensive,
  4880. but that its act of becoming is not extensive. This topic is resumed in Part
  4881. IV. How- [108] ever, some anticipation of Parts III and IV is now required.
  4882.  
  4883. The res vera, in its character of concrete satisfaction, is divisible into
  4884. prehensions which concern its first temporal half and into prehensions
  4885. which concern its second temporal half. This divisibility is what constitutes
  4886. its extensiveness. But this concern with a temporal and spatial sub-region
  4887. means that the datum of the prehension in question is the actual world,
  4888. objectified with the perspective due to that sub-region. A prehension, how-
  4889. ever, acquires subjective form, and this subjective form is only rendered
  4890. fully determinate by integration with conceptual prehensions belonging to
  4891. the mental pole of the res vera. The concrescence is dominated by a sub-
  4892. jective aim which essentially concerns the creature as a final superject. This
  4893. subjective aim is this subject itself determining its own self-creation as one
  4894. creature. Thus the subjective aim does not share in this divisibility. If we
  4895. confine attention to prehensions concerned with the earlier half, their sub-
  4896. jective forms have arisen from nothing. For the subjective aim which be-
  4897. longs to the whole is now excluded. Thus the evolution of subjective form
  4898. could not be referred to any actuality. The ontological principle has been
  4899.  
  4900.  
  4901.  
  4902. 70 Discussions and Applications
  4903.  
  4904. violated. Something has floated into the world from nowhere.
  4905.  
  4906. The summary statement of this discussion is, that the mental pole de-
  4907. termines the subjective forms and that this pole is inseparable from the
  4908. total res vera.
  4909.  
  4910. SECTION III
  4911.  
  4912. The discussion of the previous sections has merely given a modern
  4913. o>hape to the oldest of European philosophic doctrines. But as a doctrine
  4914. of common sense, it is older still— as old as consciousness itself. The most
  4915. general notions underlying the words 'space' and 'time' are those which
  4916. this discussion has aimed at expressing in their true connection with the
  4917. actual world. The alternative doctrine, which is the Newtonian cosmology,
  4918. emphasized the [109] 'receptacle' theory of space-time, and minimized the
  4919. factor of potentiality. Thus bits of space and time were conceived as being
  4920. as actual as anything else, and as being 'occupied' by other actualities
  4921. which were the bits of matter. This is the Newtonian absolute' theory of
  4922. space-time, which philosophers have never accepted, though at times some
  4923. have acquiesced. Newton's famous Scholium 5 to his first eight definitions
  4924. in his Principia expresses this point of view with entire clearness:
  4925.  
  4926. Hitherto I have laid down the definitions of such words as are less
  4927. known, and explained the sense in which I would have them to be
  4928. understood in the following discourse. I do not define time, space,
  4929. place, and motion, as being well known to all. Only I must observe,
  4930. that the vulgar conceive those quantities under no other notions but
  4931. from the relation they bear to sensible objects. And thence arise cer-
  4932. tain prejudices, for the removing of which, it will be convenient to dis-
  4933. tinguish them into absolute and relative, true and apparent, mathe-
  4934. matical and common.
  4935.  
  4936. I. Absolute, true, and mathematical time, of itself, and from its
  4937. own nature, flows equably without regard to anything external, and
  4938. by another name is called duration: relative, apparent, and common
  4939. time, is some sensible and external (whether accurate or unequable)
  4940. measure of duration by thet means of motion, which is commonly
  4941. used instead of true time; such as an hour, a day, a month, a year.
  4942.  
  4943. II. Absolute space, in its own nature, and without regard to any-
  4944. thing external, remains always similar and immovable. Relative space
  4945. is some movable dimension or measure of the absolute spaces; which
  4946. our senses determine by its position to bodies, and which is vulgarly
  4947. taken for immovable space; . . . Absolute and relative space are the
  4948. same in figure and magnitude; but they do not remain always nu-
  4949. merically the same. . . .
  4950.  
  4951. IV. ... As the order of the parts of time is [110] immutable, so
  4952. also is the order of the parts of space. Suppose those parts to be
  4953.  
  4954. 5 Andrew Motte's translation; new edition revised, London, 1803.
  4955.  
  4956.  
  4957.  
  4958. The Extensive Continuum 71
  4959.  
  4960. moved out of their places, and they will be moved (if the expression
  4961. may be allowed) out of themselves. For times and spaces are, as it
  4962. were, the places as well of themselves as of all other things. All things
  4963. are placed in time as to order of succession; and in space as to order oft
  4964. situation. It is from their essence or nature that they are places; and
  4965. that the primary places of things should be movable, is absurd. These
  4966. are, therefore, the absolute places; and translations out of those places
  4967. are the only absolute motions. . . . Now no other places are im-
  4968. movable but those that, from infinity to infinity, do all retain the
  4969. same given positions one to another; and upon this account must
  4970. ever remain unmoved; and do thereby constitute, what I call, im-
  4971. movable space. The causes by which true and relative motions are
  4972. distinguished, one from the other, are the forces impressed upon
  4973. bodies to generate motion. True motion is neither generated nor
  4974. altered, but by some force impressed upon the body moved: but
  4975. relative motion may be generated or altered without any force im-
  4976. pressed upon the body. For it is sufficient only to impress some force
  4977. on other bodies with which the former is compared, that by their
  4978. giving way, that relation may be changed, in which the relative rest
  4979. or motion of this other body did consist. . . . The effects which dis-
  4980. tinguish absolute from relative motion are, the forces of receding
  4981. from the axis of circular motion. For there are no such forces in a cir-
  4982. cular motion purely relative, but, in a true and absolute circular mo-
  4983. tion, they are greater or less, according to the quantity of motion. . . .
  4984. Wherefore relative quantities are not the quantities themselves,
  4985. whose names they bear, but those sensible measures of them (either
  4986. accurate or inaccurate) which are commonly used instead of the mea-
  4987. sured quantities themselves. . . .
  4988.  
  4989. I have quoted at such length from Newton's Scholium because this
  4990. document constitutes the clearest, most definite, and most influential
  4991. statement among the cos- [111] mological speculations of mankind, specu-
  4992. lations of a type which first assume scientific importance with the Py-
  4993. thagorean school preceding and inspiring Plato. Newton is presupposing
  4994. four types of entities which he does not discriminate in respect to their
  4995. actuality: for him minds are actual things, bodies are actual things, ab-
  4996. solute durations of time are actual things, and absolute places are actual
  4997. things. He does not use the word 'actual'; but he is speaking of matter
  4998. of fact, and he puts them all on the same level in that respect. The result
  4999. is to land him in a clearly expressed but complex and arbitrary scheme of
  5000. relationships between spaces inter se; between durations inter se; and be-
  5001. tween minds, bodies, times and places, for the conjunction of them all into
  5002. the solidarity of the one universe. For the purposes of science it was an
  5003. extraordinarily clarifying statement, that is to say, for all the purposes of
  5004. science within the next two hundred years, and for most of its purposes
  5005. since that period. But, as a fundamental statement, it lies completely open
  5006.  
  5007.  
  5008.  
  5009. 72 Discussions and Applications
  5010.  
  5011. to sceptical attack; and also, as Newton himself admits, diverges from
  5012. common sense— "the vulgar conceive those quantities under no other
  5013. notions but from the relation they bear to sensible objects/' Kant only
  5014. saved it by reducing it to the description of a construct by means of which
  5015. 'pure intuition' introduces an order for chaotic data; and for the schools of
  5016. transcendentalists derived from Kant this construct has remained in the
  5017. inferior position of a derivative from the proper ultimate substantial
  5018. reality. For them it is an element in 'appearance'; and appearance is to be
  5019. distinguished from reality. The philosophy of organism is an attempt,
  5020. with the minimum of critical adjustment, to return to the conceptions of
  5021. 'the vulgar/ f In the first place, the discussion must fasten on the notion of
  5022. a 'sensible object/ to quote Newton's phrase. We may expand Newton's
  5023. phrase, and state that the common sense of mankind conceives that all its
  5024. notions ultimately refer to actual entities, or as Newton terms them,
  5025. 'sensible objects.' Newton, basing himself upon [112] current physical
  5026. notions, conceived 'sensible objects' to be the material bodies to which
  5027. the science of dynamics applies. He was then left with the antithesis be-
  5028. tween 'sensible objects' and empty space. Newton, indeed, as a private
  5029. opinion, conjectured that there is a material medium pervading space.
  5030. But he also held that there might not be such a medium. For him the
  5031. notion 'empty space'— that is, mere spatiality — had sense, conceived as
  5032. an independent actual existence 'from infinity to infinity/ In this he
  5033. differed from Descartes. Modern physics sides with Descartes. It has in-
  5034. troduced the notion of the 'physical field.' Also the latest speculations tend
  5035. to remove the sharp distinction between the 'occupied' portions of the
  5036. field and the 'unoccupied' portion. Further, in these lectures (cf. Ch. Ill of
  5037. Part II), a distinction is introduced, not explicitly in the mind either of
  5038. 'the vulgar' or of Newton. This distinction is that between (i) an actual
  5039. entity, (ii) an enduring object, (hi) a corpuscular society, (iv) a non-
  5040. corpuscular society, (v) a non-social nexus. A non-social nexus is what
  5041. answers to the notion of 'chaos.' The extensive continuum is that general
  5042. relational element in experience whereby the actual entities experienced,
  5043. and that unit experience itself, are united in the solidarity of one common
  5044. world. The actual entities atomize it, and thereby make real what was
  5045. antecedently merely potential. The atomization of the extensive con-
  5046. tinuum is also its temporalization; that is to say, it is the process of the
  5047. becoming of actuality into what in itself is merely potential. The sys-
  5048. tematic scheme, in its completeness embracing the actual past and the
  5049. potential future, is prehended in the positive experience of each actual
  5050. entity. In this sense, it is Kant's 'form of intuition'; but it is derived from
  5051. the actual world qua datum, and thus is not 'pure' in Kant's sense of that
  5052. term. It is not productive of the ordered world, but derivative from it.
  5053. The prehension of this scheme is one more example that actual fact in-
  5054. cludes in its own constitution [113] real potentiality which is referent
  5055. beyond itself. The former example is 'appetition.'
  5056.  
  5057.  
  5058.  
  5059. The Extensive Continuum 73
  5060.  
  5061. SECTION IV
  5062.  
  5063. Newton in his description of space and time has confused what is 'real'
  5064. potentiality with what is actual fact. He has thereby been led to diverge
  5065. from the judgment of 'the vulgar' who "conceive those quantities under no
  5066. other notions but from the relation they bear to sensible objects."! The
  5067. philosophy of organism starts by agreeing with 'the vulgar' except that the
  5068. term 'sensible object' is replaced by 'actual entity'; so as to free our notions
  5069. from participation in an epistemologicalf theory as to sense-perception.
  5070. When we further consider how to adjust Newton's other descriptions to
  5071. the organic theory, the surprising fact emerges that we must identify the
  5072. atomized quantum of extension correlative to an actual entity, with New-
  5073. ton's absolute place and absolute duration. Newton's proof that motion
  5074. does not apply to absolute place, which in its nature is immovable, also
  5075. holds. Thus an actual entity never moves: it is where it is and what it is.
  5076. In order to emphasize this characteristic by a phrase connecting the notion
  5077. of 'actual entity' more closely with our ordinary habits of thought, I will
  5078. also use the term 'actual occasion' in the place of the term 'actual entity.'
  5079. Thus the actual world is built up of actual occasions; and by the oncologi-
  5080. cal principle whatever things there are in any sense of 'existence,' are de-
  5081. rived by abstraction from actual occasions. I shall use the term 'event' in
  5082. the more general sense of a nexus of actual occasions, inter-related in some
  5083. determinate fashion in one extensive quantum. An actual occasion is the
  5084. limiting type of an event with only one member.
  5085.  
  5086. It is quite obvious that meanings have to be found for the notions of
  5087. 'motion' and of 'moving bodies.' For the present, this enquiry must be
  5088. postponed to a later chapter [114] (cf. Part IV and also Ch. Ill of this
  5089. Part). It is sufficient to say that a molecule in the sense of a moving body,
  5090. with a history of local change, is not an actual occasion; it must therefore
  5091. be some kind of nexus of actual occasions. In this sense it is an event, but
  5092. not an actual occasion. The fundamental meaning of the notion of
  5093. 'change' is 'the difference between actual occasions comprised in some
  5094. determinate event.'
  5095.  
  5096. A further elucidation of the status of the extensive continuum in the
  5097. organic philosophy is obtained by comparison with Descartes' doctrine of
  5098. material bodies. It is at once evident that the organic theory is much
  5099. closer to Descartes' views than to Newton's, On this topic Spinoza is prac-
  5100. tically a logical systematization of Descartes, purging him of inconsis-
  5101. tencies. But this attainment of logical coherence is obtained by empha-
  5102. sizing just those elements in Descartes which the philosophy of organism
  5103. rejects. In this respect, Spinoza perforins the same office for Descartes that
  5104. Hume does for Locke. The philosophy of organism may be conceived as a
  5105. recurrence to Descartes and to Locke, in respect to just those elements in
  5106. their philosophies which are usually rejected by reason of their inconsis-
  5107. tency with the elements which their successors developed. Thus the phi-
  5108.  
  5109.  
  5110.  
  5111. 74 Discussions and Applications
  5112.  
  5113. losophy of organism is pluralistic in contrast with Spinoza's monism; and
  5114. is a doctrine of experience prehending actualities, in contrast with Hume's
  5115. sensationalist phenomenalism.
  5116.  
  5117. First let us recur to Descartes at the stage of thought antecedent to his
  5118. disastrous classification of substances into two species, bodily substance and
  5119. mental substance. At the beginning of Meditation i, he writes:
  5120. For example, there is the fact that I am here, seated by the fire,
  5121. attired in a dressing gown, having this paper in my hands and other
  5122. similar matters. And how could I deny that these hands and this body
  5123. are mine, were it not perhaps that I compare myself to certain per-
  5124. sons, devoid of sense. . . . But they are mad, and I should not [JJ5]
  5125. be any thef less insane were I to follow examples so extravagant.
  5126. At the same time I must remember that I am a man, and that con-
  5127. sequently I am in the habit of sleeping, and in my dreams represent-
  5128. ing to myself the same things or sometimes even less probable things,
  5129. than do those who are insane in their waking moments. ... At the
  5130. same time we must at least confess that the things which are repre-
  5131. sented to us in sleep are like painted representations which can only
  5132. have been formed as the counterparts of something real and true [ad
  5133. similiiudinem rerum verarum], and that in this way those general
  5134. things at least, i.e. eyes, a head, hands, and a whole body, are not
  5135. imaginary things, but things really existent. . . . And for the same
  5136. reason, although these general things, to wit, [a body], 6 eyes, a head,
  5137. hands, and such like, may be imaginary, we are bound at the same
  5138. time to confess that there are at least some other objects yet more
  5139. simple and more universal, which are real and true [vera esse]; and of
  5140. these just in the same way as with certain real colours, all these images
  5141. of things which dwell in our thoughts, whether true and real or false
  5142. and fantastic, are formed.
  5143.  
  5144. To such a class of things pertains corporeal nature in general, and
  5145. its extension, the figure of extended things, their quantity or magni-
  5146. tude and number, as also the place in which they are, the time which
  5147. measures their duration, and so on. . . .
  5148.  
  5149. In Meditation II, after a slight recapitulation, he continues, speaking of
  5150. God:
  5151. Then without doubt I exist also if he deceives me, and let him
  5152. deceive me as much as he will, he can never cause me to be nothing
  5153. so long as I think that I am something. So that after having reflected
  5154. well and carefully examined all things, we must come to the definite
  5155. conclusion that this proposition: I am, I exist, is necessarily true each
  5156. time that I pronounce it, or that I mentally conceive it.
  5157. [116} At the end of the quotation from Meditation J, Descartes uses the
  5158.  
  5159. 6 Haldane and Ross enclose in square brackets phrases appearing in the French
  5160. version, and not in the Latin. I have compared with the Latin.
  5161.  
  5162.  
  5163.  
  5164. The Extensive Continuum 75
  5165.  
  5166. phrase res vera in the same sense as that in which I have used the term
  5167. 'actual/ It means 'existence' in the fullest sense of that term, beyond
  5168. which there is no other. Descartes, indeed, would ascribe to God 'exis-
  5169. tence' in a generically different sense. In the philosophy of organism, as
  5170. here developed, God's existence is not generically different from that of
  5171. other actual entities, except that he is 'primordial' in a sense to be grad-
  5172. ually explained.
  5173.  
  5174. Descartes does not explicitly frame the definition of actuality in terms
  5175. of the ontological principle, as given in Section IVt of this chapter, that
  5176. actual occasions form the ground from which all other types of existence
  5177. are derivative and abstracted; but he practically formulates an equivalent in
  5178. subject-predicate phraseology, when he writes: "For this reason, when we
  5179. perceive any attribute, we therefore conclude that some existing thing or
  5180. substance to which it may be attributed, is necessarily present." 7 For
  5181. Descartes the word 'substance' is the equivalent of my phrase 'actual occa-
  5182. sion.' I refrain from the term 'substance,' for one reason because it sug-
  5183. gests the subject-predicate notion; and for another reason because Des-
  5184. cartes and Locke permit their substances to undergo adventures of chang-
  5185. ing qualifications, and thereby create difficulties.
  5186.  
  5187. In the quotation from the second Meditation: "I am, I exist, is nec-
  5188. essarily true each time that I pronounce it, or that I mentally conceive it,"f
  5189. Descartes adopts the position that an act of experience is the primary type
  5190. of actual occasion. But in his subsequent developments he assumes that
  5191. his mental substances endure change. Here he goes beyond his argument.
  5192. For each time he pronounces 'I am, I exist/ the actual occasion, which is
  5193. the ego, is different; and the 'he' which is common to the two egos is an
  5194. eternal object or, alternatively, the nexus of successive occasions. Also in
  5195. the quotation from the first [117] Meditation he begins by appealing to an
  5196. act of experience— "I am here, seated by the fire. ..." He then associates
  5197. this act of experience with his body— "these hands and body are mine.*'
  5198. He then finally appeals for some final notion of actual entities in the
  5199. remarkable sentence: "And for the same reason, although these general
  5200. things, to wit, [a body], eyes, a head, hands, and such like, may be imaginary,
  5201. we are bound at the same time to confess that there are at least some
  5202. other objects yet more simple and more universal, which are real and true;
  5203. and of these ... all these images of things which dwell in our thoughts,
  5204. whether true and real or false and fantastic, are formed."
  5205.  
  5206. Notice the peculiarly intimate association with immediate experience
  5207. which Descartes claims for his body, an association beyond the mere
  5208. sense-perception of the contemporary world— "these hands and feet are
  5209. mine." In the philosophy of organism this immediate association is the
  5210. recognition of them as distinguishable data whose formal constitutions are
  5211. immediately felt in the origination of experience. In this function the
  5212.  
  5213. 7 Principles of Philosophy, Part I, 52.
  5214.  
  5215.  
  5216.  
  5217. 76 Discussions and Applications
  5218.  
  5219. animal body does not differ in principle from the rest of the past actual
  5220. world; but it does differ in an intimacy of association by reason of which
  5221. its spatial and temporal connections obtain some definition in the ex-
  5222. perience of the subject. What is vague for the rest of the world has ob-
  5223. tained some additional measure of distinctness for the bodily organs. But,
  5224. in principle, it would be equally true to say, The actual world is mine.'
  5225. Descartes also asserts that "objects yet more simple and more uni-
  5226. versal, which are real and true" are what the "images of things which
  5227. dwellf in our thoughts"! are formed of. This does not seem to accord
  5228. with his theory of perception, of a later date, stated in his Principles, Part
  5229. IV, 196, 197, 198. In the later theory the emphasis is on the judicium, in
  5230. the sense of Inference/ and not in the sense of inspectio of realitas ob-
  5231. jectiva. But it does accord with the organic theory, that the objectifications
  5232. of other actual occasions form the given data from which an actual occa-
  5233. [118] sion originates. He has also brought the body into its immediate
  5234. association with the act of experience. Descartes, with Newton, assumes
  5235. that the extensive continuum is actual in the full sense of being an actual
  5236. entity. But he refrains from the additional material bodies which Newton
  5237. provides. Also in his efforts to guard his representative 'ideas' from the
  5238. fatal gap between mental symbol and actuality symbolized, he practically,
  5239. in some sentences, expresses the doctrine of objectification here put for-
  5240. ward. Thus:
  5241. Hence the idea of the sun will be the sun itself existing in the
  5242. mind, not indeed formally, as it exists in the sky, but objectively,
  5243. i.e. in the way in which objects are wont to exist in the mind; and this
  5244. mode of being is truly much less perfect than that in which things
  5245. exist outside the mind, but it is not on that account mere nothing,
  5246. as I have already said. 8
  5247.  
  5248. Both Descartes and Locke, in order to close the gap between idea repre-
  5249. senting and actual entity represented/ require this doctrine of 'the sun
  5250. itself existing in the mind/ But though, as in this passage, they at times
  5251. casually state it in order to push aside the epistemological difficulty, they
  5252. neither of them live up to these admissions. They relapse into the tacit
  5253. presupposition of the mind with its private ideas which are in fact qualities
  5254. without intelligible connection with the entities represented.
  5255.  
  5256. But if we take the doctrine of objectification seriously, the extensive
  5257. continuum at once becomes the primary factor in objectification. It pro-
  5258. vides the general scheme of extensive perspective which is exhibited in all
  5259. the mutual objectifications by which actual entities prehend each other.
  5260. Thus in itself, the extensive continuum is a scheme of real potentiality
  5261. which must find exemplification t in the mutual prehension of all actual
  5262. entities. It also finds exemplification in each actual entity considered
  5263.  
  5264. 8 Reply to Objections J: I have already quoted this passage in my Science and
  5265. the* Modem Wodd f note to Ch. IV.
  5266.  
  5267.  
  5268.  
  5269. The Extensive Continuum 77
  5270.  
  5271. 'formally/ In this sense, actual entities are extensive, [JJ9] since they arise
  5272. out of a potentiality for division, which in actual fact is not divided (cf.
  5273. Part IV). It is for this reason, as stated above, that the phrase 'actual
  5274. occasion' is used in the place of 'actual entity/
  5275.  
  5276. Descartes' doctrine of the physical world as exhibiting an extensive
  5277. plenum of actual entities is practically the same as the 'organic' doctrine.
  5278. But Descartes' bodies have to move, and this presupposition introduces
  5279. new obscurities. It is exactly at this point that Newton provides a clear
  5280. conception in comparison with that of Descartes. In the 'organic' doctrine,
  5281. motion is not attributable to an actual occasion.
  5282.  
  5283. In the 'organic' theory, (i) there is only one type of temporal actual
  5284. entity; (ii) each such actual entity is extensive; (iii) from the standpoint
  5285. of any one actual entity, the 'given/ actual world is a nexus of actual en-
  5286. tities, transforming the potentiality of the extensive scheme into a plenum
  5287. of actual occasions; (iv) in this plenum, motion cannot be significantly
  5288. attributed to any actual occasion; (v) the plenum is continuous in respect
  5289. to the potentiality from which it arises, but each actual entity is atomic;
  5290. (vi) the term 'actual occasion' is used synonymously t with 'actual entity';
  5291. but chiefly when its character of extensiveness has some direct relevance to
  5292. the discussion, either extensiveness in the form of temporal extensiveness,
  5293. that is to say 'duration/ or extensiveness in the form of spatial extension,
  5294. or in the more complete signification of spatio-temporal extensiveness.
  5295.  
  5296. SECTION V
  5297.  
  5298. The baseless metaphysical doctrine of 'undifferentiated endurance' is a
  5299. subordinate derivative from the misapprehension of the proper character
  5300. of the extensive scheme.
  5301.  
  5302. In our perception of the contemporary world via presentational im-
  5303. mediacy, nexus of actual entities are objectified for the percipient under
  5304. the perspective of their characters of extensive continuity. In the percep-
  5305. tion of a contemporary stone, for example, the separate indi- \120) viduality
  5306. of each actual entity in the nexus constituting the stone is merged into the
  5307. unity of the extensive plenum, which for Descartes and for common sense,
  5308. is the stone. The complete objectification is effected by the generic exten-
  5309. sive perspective of the stone, specialized into the specific perspective of
  5310. some sense-datum, such as some definite colour, for example. Thus the
  5311. immediate percept assumes the character of the quiet undifferentiated en-
  5312. durance of the material stone, perceived by means of its quality of colour.
  5313. This basic notion dominates language, and haunts both science and philos-
  5314. ophy. Further, by an unfortunate application of the excellent maxim, that
  5315. our conjectural explanation should always proceed by the utilization of a
  5316. vera causa, whenever science or philosophy has ventured to extrapolate
  5317. beyond the limits of the immediate deliverance of direct perception, a
  5318. satisfactory explanation has always complied with the condition that sub-
  5319. stances with undifferentiated endurance of essential attributes be pro-
  5320.  
  5321.  
  5322.  
  5323. 78 Discussions and Applications
  5324.  
  5325. duced, and that activity be explained as the occasional modification of
  5326. their accidental qualities and relations. Thus the imaginations of men are
  5327. dominated by the quiet extensive stone with its relationships of positions,
  5328. and its quality of colour—relationships and qualities which occasionally
  5329. change. The stone, thus interpreted, guarantees the vera causa, and con-
  5330. jectural explanations in science and philosophy follow its model.
  5331.  
  5332. Thus in framing cosmological theory, the notion of continuous stuff with
  5333. permanent attributes, enduring without differentiation, and retaining its
  5334. self-identity through any stretch of time however small or large, has been
  5335. fundamental. The stuff undergoes change in respect to accidental qualities
  5336. and relations; but it is numerically self-identical in its character of one
  5337. actual entity throughout its accidental adventures. The admission of this
  5338. fundamental metaphysical concept has wrecked the various systems of
  5339. pluralistic realism.
  5340.  
  5341. This metaphysical concept has formed the basis of scientific materialism.
  5342. For example, when the activities [121] associated with so-called empty
  5343. space required scientific formulation, the scientists of the nineteenth cen-
  5344. tury produced the materialistic ether as the ultimate substratum whose
  5345. accidental adventures constituted these activities.
  5346.  
  5347. But the interpretation of the stone, on which the whole concept is
  5348. based, has proved to be entirely mistaken. In the first place, from the
  5349. seventeenth century onwards the notion of the simple inherence of the
  5350. colour in the stone has had to be given up. This introduces the further
  5351. difficulty that it is the colour which is extended and only inferentially the
  5352. stone, since now we have had to separate the colour from the stone.
  5353. Secondly, the molecular theory has robbed the stone of its continuity, of
  5354. its unity, and of its passiveness. The stone is now conceived as a society of
  5355. separate molecules in violent agitation. But the metaphysical concepts,
  5356. which had their origin in a mistake about the stone, were now applied to
  5357. the individual molecules. Each atom was still a stuff which retained its self-
  5358. identity and its essential attributes in any portion of time— however short,
  5359. and however long— provided that it did not perish. The notion of the un-
  5360. differentiated endurance of substances with essential attributes and with
  5361. accidental adventures! was still applied. This is the root doctrine of ma-
  5362. terialism: the substance, thus conceived, is the ultimate actual entity.
  5363.  
  5364. But this materialistic concept has proved to be as mistaken for the atom
  5365. as it was for the stone. 'The atom is only explicable as a society with ac-
  5366. tivities involving rhythms with their definite periods. Again the concept
  5367. shifted its application: protons and electrons were conceived as ma-
  5368. terialistic electric charges whose activities could be construed as locomotive
  5369. adventures. We are now approaching the limits of any reasonable certainty
  5370. in our scientific knowledge; but again there is evidence that the concept
  5371. may be mistaken. The mysterious quanta of energy have made their ap-
  5372. pearance, derived, as it would seem, from the recesses of protons, or of
  5373. electrons. Still worse for the concept, these quanta seem to dissolve [122]
  5374.  
  5375.  
  5376.  
  5377. The Extensive Continuum 79
  5378.  
  5379. into the vibrations of light. Also the material of the stars seems to be
  5380. wasting itself in the production of the vibrations.
  5381.  
  5382. Further, the quanta of energy are associated by a simple law with the
  5383. periodic rhythms which we detect in the molecules. Thus the quanta are,
  5384. themselves, in their own nature, somehow vibratory; but they emanate
  5385. from the protons and electrons. Thus there is every reason to believe that
  5386. rhythmic periods cannot be dissociated from the protonic and electronic
  5387. entities.
  5388.  
  5389. The same concept has been applied in other connections where it even
  5390. more obviously fails. It is said that 'men are rational/ This is palpably
  5391. false: they are only intermittently rational—merely liable to rationality.
  5392. Again the phrase 'Socrates is mortal' is only another way of saying that
  5393. 'perhaps he will die/ The intellect of Socrates is intermittent: he occa-
  5394. sionally sleeps and he can be drugged or stunned.
  5395.  
  5396. The simple notion of an enduring substance sustaining persistent quali-
  5397. ties, either essentially or accidentally, expresses a useful abstract for many
  5398. purposes of life. But whenever we try to use it as a fundamental statement
  5399. of the nature of things, it proves itself mistaken. It arose from a mistake
  5400. and has never succeeded in any of its applications. But it has had one
  5401. success: it has entrenched itself in language, in Aristotelian logic, and in
  5402. metaphysics. For its employment in language and in logic, there is— as
  5403. stated above— a sound pragmatic defence. But in metaphysics the concept
  5404. is sheer error. This error does not consist in the employment of the word
  5405. 'substance'; but in the employment of the notion of an actual entity which
  5406. is characterized by essential qualities, and remains numerically one amidst
  5407. the changes of accidental relations and of accidental qualities. The con-
  5408. trary doctrine is that an actual entity never changes, and that it is the out-
  5409. come of whatever can be ascribed to it in the way of qualitv or relationship.
  5410. There then remain two alternatives for philosophy: (i) a monistic universe
  5411. [123] with the illusion of change; and (ii) a pluralistic universe in which
  5412. 'change' means the diversities among the actual entities which belong to
  5413. some one society of a definite type.
  5414.  
  5415. SECTION VI
  5416.  
  5417. We can now, in a preliminary way, summarize some of the agreements
  5418. and disagreements between the philosophy of organism and the seven-
  5419. teenth-century founders of the modern philosophic and scientific traditions.
  5420.  
  5421. It is the basis of any realistic philosophy, that in perception there is a
  5422. disclosure of objectified data, which are known as having a community
  5423. with the immediate experience for which they are data. This 'community'*
  5424. is a community of common activity involving mutual implication. This
  5425. premise is asserted as a primary fact, implicitly assumed in every detail of
  5426. our organization of life. It is implicitly asserted by Locke in his statement
  5427. (II, XXIII, 7, heading), "Power, a great part of our complex ideas of
  5428.  
  5429.  
  5430.  
  5431. 80 Discussions and Applications
  5432.  
  5433. substances ."t The philosophy of organism extends the Cartesian subjectiv-
  5434. ism by affirming the 'ontological principle' and by construing it as the defi-
  5435. nition of 'actuality/ This amounts to the assumption that each actual entity
  5436. is a locus for the universe. Accordingly Descartes' other statement, that
  5437. every attribute requires a substance,! is merely a special, limited example
  5438. of this more general principle.
  5439.  
  5440. Newton, in his treatment of space, transforms potentiality into actual fact,
  5441. that is to say, into a creature, instead of a datum for creatures. According
  5442. to the philosophy of organism, the extensive space-time continuum is the
  5443. fundamental aspect of the limitation laid upon abstract potentiality by the
  5444. actual world. A more complete rendering of this limited, 'real' potentiality
  5445. is the 'physical field/ A new creation has to arise from the actual world as
  5446. much as from pure potentiality: it arises from the total universe and not
  5447. solely from its mere abstract elements. It also adds to that universe. Thus
  5448. [124] every actual entity springs from that universe which there is for it.
  5449. Causation is nothing else than one outcome of the principle that every
  5450. actual entity has to house its actual world.
  5451.  
  5452. According to Newton, a portion of space cannot move. We have to ask
  5453. how this truth, obvious from Newton's point of view, takes shape in the
  5454. organic theory. Instead of a region of space, we should consider a bit of the
  5455. physical field. This bit, expressing one way in which the actual world in-
  5456. volves the potentiality for a new creation, acquires the unity of an actual
  5457. entity. The physical field is, in this way, atomized with definite divisions: it
  5458. becomes a 'nexus' f of actualities. Such a quantum (i.e., each actual divi-
  5459. sion) of the extensive continuum is the primary phase of a creature. This
  5460. quantum is constituted by its totality of relationships and cannot move.
  5461. Also the creature cannot have any external adventures, but only the in-
  5462. ternal adventure of becoming. Its birth is its end.
  5463.  
  5464. This is a theory of monads; but it differs from Leibniz's in that his
  5465. monads change. In the organic theory, they merely become. Each monadic
  5466. creature is a mode of the process of 'feeling' the world, of housing the
  5467. world in one unit of complex feeling, in every way determinate. Such a
  5468. unit is an 'actual occasion'; it is the ultimate creature derivative from the
  5469. creative process.
  5470.  
  5471. The term 'event' is used in a more genera] sense. An event is a nexus of
  5472. actual occasions inter-related in some determinate fashion in some exten-
  5473. sive quantum: it is either a nexus in its formal completeness, or it is an
  5474. objectified nexus. One actual occasion is a limiting type of event. The
  5475. most general sense of the meaning of change is 'the differences between
  5476. actual occasions in one event.' For example, a molecule is a historic route
  5477. of actual occasions; and such a route is an 'event.' Now the motion of the
  5478. molecule is nothing else than the differences between the successive occa-
  5479. sions of its life-history in respect to the extensive quanta from which they
  5480. arise; \12S] and the changes in the molecule are the consequential dif-
  5481. ferences in the actual occasions.
  5482.  
  5483.  
  5484.  
  5485. The Extensive Continuum 81
  5486.  
  5487. The organic doctrine is closer to Descartes than to Newton. Also it is
  5488. close to Spinoza; but Spinoza bases his philosophy upon the monistic sub-
  5489. stance, of which the actual occasions are inferior modes. The philosophy
  5490. of organism inverts this point of view.
  5491.  
  5492. As to the direct knowledge of the actual world as a datum for the
  5493. immediacy of feeling, we first refer to Descartes in Meditation J, 'These
  5494. hands and this body are mine' 7 ; also to Hume in his many assertions of the
  5495. type, we see with our eyes. Such statements witness to direct knowledge of
  5496. the antecedent functioning of the body in sense-perception. Both agree-
  5497. though Hume more explicitly— that sense-perception of the contemporary
  5498. world is accompanied by perception of the 'withness' of the body. It is
  5499. this withness that makes the body the starting point for our knowledge of
  5500. the circumambient world. We find here our direct knowledge of 'causal
  5501. efficacy/ Hume and Descartes in their theory of direct perceptive knowl-
  5502. edge dropped out this withness of the body; and thus confined perception
  5503. to presentational immediacy. Santayana, in his doctrine of 'animal faith/
  5504. practically agrees with Hume and Descartes as to this withness of the
  5505. actual world, including the body. Santayana also excludes our knowledge
  5506. of it from givenness. Descartes calls it a certain kind of 'understanding';
  5507. Santayana calls it 'animal faith' provoked by 'shock'; and Hume calls it
  5508. "practice. 7
  5509.  
  5510. But we must— to avoid 'solipsism of the present moment' — include in
  5511. direct perception something more than presentational immediacy. For the
  5512. organic theory, the most primitive perception is 'feeling the body as func-
  5513. tioning/ This is a feeling of the world in the past; it is the inheritance of
  5514. the world as a complex of feeling; namely, it is the feeling of derived feel-
  5515. ings. The later, sophisticated perception is 'feeling the contemporary
  5516. world/ Even this presentational immediacy begins with [126] sense-presen-
  5517. tation of the contemporary body. The body, however, is only a peculiarly
  5518. intimate bit of the world. Just as Descartes said, 'this body is mine'; so he
  5519. should have said, 'this actual world is mine/ My process of 'being myself
  5520. is my origination from my possession of the world.
  5521.  
  5522. It is obvious that there arise the questions of comparative relevance and
  5523. of comparative vagueness, which constitute the perspective of the world.
  5524. For example, the body is that portion of the world where, in causal per-
  5525. ception, there is some distinct separation of regions. There is not, in causal
  5526. perception, this distinctness for the past world external to the body. We
  5527. eke out our knowledge by 'symbolic transference 7 from causal perception
  5528. to sense-presentation, and vice versa.
  5529.  
  5530. Those realists, who base themselves upon the notion of substance, do
  5531. not get away from the notion of actual entities which move and change.
  5532. From the point of view of the philosophy of organism, there is great
  5533. merit in Newton's immovable receptacles. But for Newton they are eternal.
  5534. Locke's notion of time hits the mark better: time is 'perpetually perish-
  5535. ing.' In the organic philosophy an actual entity has 'perished* when it is
  5536.  
  5537.  
  5538.  
  5539. 82 Discussions and Applications
  5540.  
  5541. complete. The pragmatic use of the actual entity, constituting its static
  5542. life, lies in the future. The creature perishes and is immortal. The actual
  5543. entities beyond it can say, 'It is mine/ But the possession imposes
  5544. conformation.
  5545.  
  5546. This conception of an actual entity in the fluent world is little more
  5547. than an expansion of a sentence in the Timaeus: 9 "But that which is
  5548. conceived by opinion with the help of sensation and without reason, is
  5549. always in af process of becoming and perishing and never really is." Berg-
  5550. son, in his protest against "spatialization," is only echoing Plato's phrase
  5551. 'and never really is/
  5552.  
  5553.  
  5554.  
  5555. 9 28A;f Jowett's translation. Professor A. E. Taylor in his Commentary On
  5556. Plato's Timaeus renders the word 8o£ a by 'belief or 'judgment' in the place of
  5557. Jowett's word 'opinion/ Taylor's translation brings out the Platonic influence in
  5558. Descartes' Meditations, namely Plato's 8o£ a is the Cartesian judicium.
  5559.  
  5560.  
  5561.  
  5562. CHAPTER III
  5563. THE ORDER OF NATURE
  5564.  
  5565. SECTION I
  5566.  
  5567. [127] In this, and in the next chapter, among modern philosophers we
  5568. are chiefly concerned with Hume and with Kant, and among ancient phi-
  5569. losophers with the Timaeus of Plato. These chapters are concerned with
  5570. the allied problems of 'order in the universe/ of 'induction/ and of 'gen-
  5571. eral truths/ The present chapter is wholly concerned with the topic of
  5572. 'order/ For the organic doctrine the problem of order assumes primary
  5573. importance. No actual entity can rise beyond what the actual world as a
  5574. datum from its standpoint— its actual world— allows it to be. Each such
  5575. entity arises from a primary phase of the concrescence of objectifications
  5576. which are in some respects settled: the basis of its experience is 'given/
  5577. Now the correlative of 'order' is 'disorder/ There can be no peculiar mean-
  5578. ing in the notion of 'order' unless this contrast holds. Apart from it, 'order*
  5579. must be a synonym for 'givenness/ But 'order' means more than 'given-
  5580. ness/ though it presupposes 'givenness';t 'disorder' is also 'given/ Each
  5581. actual entity requires a totality of 'givenness/ and each totality of 'given-
  5582. ness' attains its measure of 'order/
  5583.  
  5584. Four grounds of 'order' at once emerge:
  5585.  
  5586. (i) That 'order' in the actual world is differentiated from mere
  5587. 'givenness' by introduction of adaptation for the attainment of an end.
  5588.  
  5589. (ii) That this end is concerned with the gradations of intensity in the
  5590. satisfactions of actual entities (members of the nexus) in whose formal
  5591. constitutions the nexus [128] (i.e., antecedent members of the nexus) in
  5592. question is objectified.
  5593.  
  5594. (iii) That the heightening of intensity arises from order such that the
  5595. multiplicity of components in the nexus can enter explicit feeling as con-
  5596. trasts, and are not dismissed into negative prehensions as incompatibilities.
  5597.  
  5598. (iv) That 'intensity' in the formal constitution of a subject-superject
  5599. involves 'appetition' in its objective functioning as superject.
  5600.  
  5601. 'Order' is a mere generic term: there can only be some definite specific
  5602. 'order/ not merely 'order' in the vague. Thus every definite total phase of
  5603. 'givenness' involves a reference to that specific 'order' which is its dominant
  5604. ideal, and involves the specific 'disorder' due to its inclusion of 'given'
  5605. components which exclude the attainment of the full ideal. The attain-
  5606. ment is partial, and thus there is 'disorder'; but there is some attainment,
  5607.  
  5608. 83
  5609.  
  5610.  
  5611.  
  5612. 84 Discussions and Applications
  5613.  
  5614. and thus there is some 'order/ There is not just one ideal 'order' which
  5615. all actual entities should attain and fail to attain . In each case there is an
  5616. ideal peculiar to each particular actual entity, and arising from the domi-
  5617. nant components in its phase of 'givenness.' This notion of 'dominance*
  5618. will have to be discussed later in connection with the notion of the sys-
  5619. tematic character of a 'cosmic epoch' and of the subordinate systematic
  5620. characters of 'societies' included in a cosmic epoch. The notion of one
  5621. ideal arises from the disastrous overmoralization of thought under the in-
  5622. fluence of fanaticism, or pedantry. The notion of a dominant ideal peculiar
  5623. to each actual entity is Platonic.
  5624.  
  5625. It is notable that no biological science has been able to express itself
  5626. apart from phraseology which is meaningless unless it refers to ideals proper
  5627. to the organism in question. This aspect of the universe impressed itself
  5628. on that great biologist and philosopher, Aristotle. His philosophy led to a
  5629. wild overstressing of the notion of 'final causes'! during the Christian mid-
  5630. dle ages; and thence, by a reaction, to the correlative overstressing of [129]
  5631. the notion of 'efficient causes' during the modern scientific period. One
  5632. task of a sound metaphysics is to exhibit final and efficient causes in their
  5633. proper relation to each other. The necessity and the difficulty of this task
  5634. are stressed by Hume in his Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion.
  5635.  
  5636. Thus the notion of 'order' is bound up with the notion of an actual
  5637. entity as involving an attainment which is a specific satisfaction. This satis-
  5638. faction is the attainment of something individual to the entity in question.
  5639. It cannot be construed as a component contributing to its own concres-
  5640. cence; it is the ultimate fact, individual to the entity. The notion of 'satis-
  5641. faction' is the notion of the 'entity as concrete' abstracted from the 'process
  5642. of concrescence'; it is the outcome separated from the process, thereby
  5643. losing the actuality of the atomic entity, which is both process and out-
  5644. come. 'Satisfaction' provides the individual element in the composition of
  5645. the actual entity— that element which has led to the definition of substance
  5646. as 'requiring nothing but itself in order to exist.' But the 'satisfaction' is
  5647. the 'superject' rather than the 'substance' or the 'subject.' It closes up the
  5648. entity; and yet is the superject adding its character to the creativity whereby
  5649. there is a becoming of entities superseding the one in question. The
  5650. 'formal' reality of the actuality in question belongs to its process of con-
  5651. crescence and not to its 'satisfaction/ This is the sense in which the
  5652. philosophy of organism interprets Plato's phrase 'and never really is'; for
  5653. the superject can only be interpreted in terms of its 'objective immortality/
  5654.  
  5655. 'Satisfaction' is a generic term: there are specific differences between
  5656. the 'satisfactions' of different entities, including gradations of intensity.
  5657. These specific differences can only be expressed by the analysis of the com-
  5658. ponents in the concrescence out of which the actual entity arises. The in-
  5659. tensity of satisfaction is promoted by the 'order' in the phases from which
  5660. concrescence arises and through which it passes; it is enfeebled by the [130]
  5661. 'disorder/ The components in the concrescence are thus 'values' con-
  5662.  
  5663.  
  5664.  
  5665. The Order of Nature 85
  5666.  
  5667. tributary to the 'satisfaction/ The concrescence is thus the building up
  5668. of a determinate 'satisfaction/ which constitutes the completion of the
  5669. actual togetherness of the discrete components. The process of concres-
  5670. cence terminates with the attainment of a fully determinate 'satisfaction';
  5671. and the creativity thereby passes over into the 'given' primary phase for the
  5672. concrescence of other actual entities. This transcendence is thereby estab-
  5673. lished when there is attainment of determinate 'satisfaction' completing
  5674. the antecedent entity. Completion is the perishing of immediacy: 'It never
  5675. really is/f
  5676.  
  5677. No actual entity can be conscious of its own satisfaction; for such knowl-
  5678. edge would be a component in the process, and would thereby alter the
  5679. satisfaction. In respect to the entity in question the satisfaction can only
  5680. be considered as a creative determination, by which the objectifications of
  5681. the entity beyond itself are settled. In other words, the 'satisfaction' of an
  5682. entity can only be discussed in terms of the usefulness of that entity. It is
  5683. a qualification of creativity. The tone of feeling embodied in this satisfac-
  5684. tion passes into the world beyond, by reason of these objectifications. The
  5685. world is self-creative; and the actual entity as self-creating creature passes
  5686. into its immortal function of part-creator of the transcendent world. In its
  5687. self-creation the actual entity is guided by its ideal of itself as individual
  5688. satisfaction and as transcendent creator. The enjoyment of this ideal is the
  5689. 'subjective aim/ by reason of which the actual entity is a determinate
  5690. process.
  5691.  
  5692. This subjective aim is not primarily intellectual; it is the lure for feeling.
  5693. This lure for feeling is the germ of mind. Here I am using the term 'mind'
  5694. to mean the complex of mental operations involved in the constitution of
  5695. an actual entity. Mental operations do not necessarily involve conscious-
  5696. ness. The concrescence, absorb- [131] ing the derived data into immediate
  5697. privacy, consists in mating the data with ways of feeling provocative of the
  5698. private synthesis. These subjective ways of feeling are not merely receptive
  5699. of the data as alien facts; they clothe the dry bones with the flesh of a real
  5700. being, emotional, purposive, appreciative. The miracle of creation is de-
  5701. scribed in the vision of the prophet Ezekiel: "So I prophesied as he com-
  5702. manded me, and the breath came into them, and they lived, and stood up
  5703. upon their feet, an exceeding great army." T
  5704.  
  5705. The breath of feeling which creates a new individual fact has an origina-
  5706. tion not wholly traceable to the mere data. It conforms to the data, in that
  5707. it feels the data. But the how of feeling, though it is germane to the data,
  5708. is not fully determined by the data. The relevant feeling is not settled, as
  5709. to its inclusions or exclusions of 'subjective form/ by the data about which
  5710. the feeling is concerned. The concrescent process is the elimination of
  5711. these indeterminations of subjective forms. The quality of feeling has to be
  5712. definite in respect to the eternal objects with which feeling clothes itself
  5713.  
  5714. 1 Ezekiel, xxxvii:10.t
  5715.  
  5716.  
  5717.  
  5718. 86 Discussions and Applications
  5719.  
  5720. in its self-definition. It is a mode of ingression of eternal objects into the
  5721. actual occasion. But this self-definition is analysable into two phases. First,
  5722. the conceptual ingression of the eternal objects in the double r&le of being
  5723. germane to the data and of being potentials for physical feeling. This is
  5724. the ingression of an eternal object in the r61e of a conceptual lure for feel-
  5725. ing. The second phase is the admission of the lure into the reality of feeling,
  5726. or its rejection from this reality. The relevance of an eternal object in its
  5727. role of lure is a fact inherent in the data. In this sense the eternal object
  5728. is a constituent of the 'objective lure/ But the admission into, or rejection
  5729. from, reality of conceptual feeling is the originative decision of the actual
  5730. occasion. In this sense an actual occasion is causa sui. The subjective forms
  5731. of the prehen- [132] sions in one phase of concrescence control the specific
  5732. integrations of prehensions in later phases of that concrescence.
  5733.  
  5734. An example of the lure for feeling is given by Hume himself. In the first
  5735. section of his Treatise* he lays down the proposition, "That all our simple
  5736. ideas in their first appearance, are derived from simple impressions ? which
  5737. are correspondent to them, and which they exactly represent!' It must be
  5738. remembered that in the organic philosophy the 'data of objectifications' are
  5739. the nearest analogue to Hume's 'simple impressions/ Thus, modifying
  5740. Hume's principle, the only lure to conceptual feeling is an exact con-
  5741. formation to the qualities realized in the objectified actualities. But Hume
  5742. (toe. eft.) notes an exception which carries with it the exact principle
  5743. which has just been laid down, namely, the principle of relevant potentials,
  5744. unrealized in the datum and yet constituent of an 'objective lure' by
  5745. proximity to the datum. The point is that 'order' in the actual world in-
  5746. troduces a derivative 'order' among eternal objects. Hume writes:
  5747. There is. however, one contradictory phenomenon, which may prove,
  5748. that it is not absolutely impossible for ideas to go before their corre-
  5749. spondent impressions. I believe it will readily be allowed, that the sev-
  5750. eral distinct ideas of colours, which enter by the eyes, orf those of
  5751. sounds, which are conveyed by the hearing, are really different from
  5752. each other, though, at the same time, resembling. Now, if this be true
  5753. of different colours, it must be no less so of the different shades of the
  5754. same colour, that each of them produces a distinct idea, independent of
  5755. the rest. . . . Suppose, therefore, a person to have enjoyed his sight for
  5756. thirty years, and to have become perfectly well acquainted with colours
  5757. of all kinds, excepting one particular shade of blue, for instance, which
  5758. it never hast been his fortune to meet with. Let all the different shades
  5759. of that colour, except that single one, be placed before him, descending
  5760. gradually from the deepest to the [133] lightest; it is plain, that he
  5761. will perceive a blank, where that shade is wanting, and will be sensible
  5762. that there is a greater distance in that place, betwixtt the contiguous
  5763. colours, than in any other. Now I ask, whether it is possible for him,
  5764. from his own imagination, to supply this deficiency, andt raise up to
  5765. himself the idea of that particular shade, though it had never been
  5766.  
  5767.  
  5768.  
  5769. The Order of Nature 87
  5770.  
  5771. conveyed to him by his senses? I believe there are few but will be of
  5772.  
  5773. opinion that he can; and this may serve as a proof, that the simple
  5774.  
  5775. ideas are not always derived from the correspondent impressions;
  5776.  
  5777. though the instance t is so particular and singular, that it is scarce
  5778.  
  5779. worth our observing, and does not merit that, for it alone, we should
  5780.  
  5781. alter our general maxim.
  5782.  
  5783. This passage requires no comment, except for its final clause. Hume puts
  5784. the 'instance' aside as being 'particular and singular'; it is exactly this esti-
  5785. mate which is challenged by the philosophy of organism. The analysis of
  5786. concrescence, here adopted, conceives that there is an origination of con-
  5787. ceptual feeling, admitting or rejecting whatever is apt for feeling by reason
  5788. of its germaneness to the basic data. The gradation of eternal objects in
  5789. respect to this germaneness is the 'objective lure' for feeling; the concres-
  5790. cent process admits a selection from this 'objective lure 7 into subjective
  5791. efficiency. This is the subjective 'ideal of itself which guides the process.
  5792. Also the basic data are constituted by the actual world which 'belongs to'
  5793. that instance of concrescent process. Feelings are 'vectors'; for they feel
  5794. what is there and transform it into what is here.
  5795.  
  5796. The term 'potential difference' is an old one in physical science; and re-
  5797. cently it has been introduced in physiology with a meaning diverse from,
  5798. though generically allied to, its older meaning in physics. The ultimate fact
  5799. in the constitution of an actual entity which suggests this term is the ob-
  5800. jective lure for feeling. In the comparison of two actual entities, the con-
  5801. trast be- \134] tween their objective lures is their 'potential difference'; and
  5802. all other uses of this phrase are abstractions derivative from this ultimate
  5803. meaning.
  5804.  
  5805. The 'objectifications' of the actual entities in the actual world, relative to
  5806. a definite actual entity, constitute the efficient causes out of which that
  5807. actual entity arises; the 'subjective aim' at 'satisfaction' constitutes the final
  5808. cause, or lure, whereby there is determinate concrescence; and that at-
  5809. tained 'satisfaction' remains as an element in the content of creative pur-
  5810. pose. There is, in this way, transcendence of the creativity; and this
  5811. transcendence effects determinate objectifications for the renewal of the
  5812. process in the concrescence of actualities beyond that satisfied superject.
  5813.  
  5814. Thus an actual entity has a threefold! character: (i) it has the char-
  5815. acter 'given' for it by the past; (ii) it has the subjective character aimed
  5816. at in its process of concrescence; (iii) it has the superjective character,
  5817. which is the pragmatic value of its specific satisfaction qualifying the
  5818. transcendent creativity.
  5819.  
  5820. In the case of the primordial actual entity, which is God, there is no
  5821. past. Thus the ideal realization of conceptual feeling takes the precedence.
  5822. God differs from other actual entities in rhe fact that Hume's principle, of
  5823. the derivate character of conceptual feelings, does not hold for him. There
  5824. is still, however, the same threefold character: (i) The 'primordial na-
  5825. ture' of God is the concrescence of at unity of conceptual feelings, in-
  5826.  
  5827.  
  5828.  
  5829. 88 Discussions and Applications
  5830.  
  5831. eluding among their data all eternal objects. The concrescence is directed
  5832. by the subjective aim. that the subjective forms of the feelings shall be
  5833. such as to constitute the eternal objects into relevant lures of feeling* sev-
  5834. erally appropriate for all realizable basic conditions, (ii) The 'consequent
  5835. nature' of God is the physical prehension by God of the actualities of the
  5836. evolving universe. His! primordial nature directs such perspectives of ob-
  5837. jectification that each novel actuality in the temporal world contributes
  5838. such elements as it can to a realization in God [J 35] free from inhibitions
  5839. of intensity by reason of discordance, (iii) The 'super jective nature' f of
  5840. God is the character of the pragmatic value of his specific satisfaction
  5841. qualifying the transcendent creativity in the various temporal instances.
  5842.  
  5843. This is the conception of God, according to which he is considered as the
  5844. outcome of creativity, as the foundation of order, and as the goad* to-
  5845. wards novelty. 'Order' and 'novelty' are but the instruments of his sub-
  5846. jective aim which is the intensification of 'formal immediacy.' It is to be
  5847. noted that every actual entity, including God, is something individual for
  5848. its own sake; and thereby transcends the rest of actuality. And also it is to
  5849. be noted that every actual entity, including God, is a creature transcended
  5850. by the creativity which it qualifies. A temporal occasion in respect to the
  5851. second element of its character, and God in respect to the first element of
  5852. his character satisfy Spinoza's definition of substance, that it is causa sui.
  5853. To be causa sui means that the process of concrescence is its own reason
  5854. for the decision in respect to the qualitative clothing of feelings. It is
  5855. finally responsible for the decision by which any lure for feeling is ad-
  5856. mitted to efficiency. The freedom inherent in the universe is constituted
  5857. by this element of self-causation.
  5858.  
  5859. In the subsequent discussion, 'actual entity' will be taken to mean a con-
  5860. ditioned actual entity of the temporal world, unless God is expressly in-
  5861. cluded in the discussion. The term 'actual occasion' will always exclude
  5862. God from its scope.
  5863.  
  5864. The philosophy of organism is the inversion of Kant's philosophy. The
  5865. Critique of Pure Reason describes the process by which subjective data
  5866. pass into the appearance of an objective world. Trie philosophy of organ-
  5867. ism seeks to describe how objective data pass into subjective satisfaction,
  5868. and how order in the objective data provides intensity in the subjective
  5869. satisfaction. For Kant, the world emerges from the subject; for the philoso-
  5870. phy of [J 36] organism, the subject emerges from the world— a 'super ject'
  5871. rather than a 'subject.' The word 'object' thus means an entity which is a
  5872. potentiality for being a component in feeling; and the word 'subject' means
  5873. the entity constituted by the process of feeling, and including this process.
  5874. The feeler is the unity emergent from its own feelings; and feelings are the
  5875. details of the process intermediary between this unity and its many data.
  5876. The data are the potentials for feeling; that is to say, they are objects. The
  5877. process is the elimination of indeterminateness of feeling from the unity
  5878. of one subjective experience. The degree of order in the datum is measured
  5879.  
  5880.  
  5881.  
  5882. The Order of Nature 89
  5883.  
  5884. by the degree of richness in the objective lure. The 'intensity 7 achieved be-
  5885. longs to the subjective form of the satisfaction,
  5886.  
  5887. SECTION II
  5888.  
  5889. It has been explained in the previous section that the notion of 'order' is
  5890. primarily applicable to the objectified data for individual actual entities.
  5891. It has been necessary to give a sketch of some categories applying to an
  5892. actual entity in order to show how this can be the case. But there is a
  5893. derivative sense of the term 'order/ which is more usually in our minds
  5894. when we use that word. We speak of the 'order of nature/ meaning
  5895. thereby the order reigning in that limited portion of the universe, 2 or even
  5896. of the surface of the earth, which has come under our observation. We also
  5897. speak of a man of orderly life, or of disorderly life. In any of these senses,
  5898. the term 'order' evidently applies to the relations among themselves en-
  5899. joyed by many actual entities which thereby form a society. The term
  5900. 'society' will always be restricted to mean a nexus of actual entities which
  5901. are 'ordered' among themselves in the sense to be explained in this sec-
  5902. tion. 3 [137] The point of a 'society,' as the term is here used, is that it is
  5903. self-sustaining; in other words, that it is its own reason. Thus a society is
  5904. more than a set of entities to which the same class-name applies: that is
  5905. to say, it involves more than a merely mathematical conception of 'order.'
  5906. To constitute a society, the class-name has got to apply to each member,
  5907. by reason of genetic derivation from other members of that same society.
  5908. The members of the society are alike because, by reason of their common
  5909. character, they impose on other members of the society the conditions
  5910. which lead to that likeness.
  5911.  
  5912. This likeness 4 consists in the fact that (i) a certain element of 'form'
  5913. is a contributory component to the individual satisfaction of each member
  5914. of the society; and that (ii) the contribution by the element to the objecti-
  5915. fication of any one member of the society for prehension by other mem-
  5916. bers promotes its analogous reproduction in the satisfactions of those other
  5917. members. Thus a set of entities is a society (i) in virtue of a 'defining
  5918. characteristic' shared by its members, and (ii) in virtue of the presence of
  5919. the defining characteristic being due to the environment provided by the
  5920. society itself.
  5921.  
  5922. For example, the life of** man is a historic route of actual occasions
  5923. which in a marked degree— to be discussed more fully later—inherit from
  5924. each other. That set of occasions, dating from his first acquirement of the
  5925.  
  5926. 2 Cf. The Fitness of the Environment, New York, Macmiilan, 1913, The
  5927. Order of Nature, Harvard Univ. Press, 1917, and Blood, Ha ward Univ. Press,
  5928. 1928, Ch. 1, allt by Professor L. }. Henderson. These works are fundamental
  5929. for anv discussion of this subject.
  5930.  
  5931. 3 Also cf.t Part I, Ch. Ill, Sect. II.
  5932. 4 Cf. Parti, Ch. Ill, Sect. II.
  5933.  
  5934.  
  5935.  
  5936. 90 Discussions and Applications
  5937.  
  5938. Greek language and including all those occasions up to his loss of any
  5939. adequate knowledge of that language, constitutes a society in reference to
  5940. knowledge of the Greek language. Such knowledge is a common character-
  5941. istic inherited from occasion to occasion along the historic route. This
  5942. example has purposely been chosen for its reference to a somewhat trivial
  5943. element of order, viz. knowledge of the Greek language; a more important
  5944. character of order would have been that complex character in virtue of
  5945. which a man is considered to be the same enduring person from birth to
  5946. death. Also in this in- [138] stance the members of the society are arranged
  5947. in a serial order by their genetic relations. Such a society is said 5 to possess
  5948. 'personal order/
  5949.  
  5950. Thus a society is, for each of its members, an environment with some
  5951. element of order in it, persisting by reason of the genetic relations between
  5952. its own members. Such an element of order is the order prevalent in the
  5953. society.
  5954.  
  5955. But there is no society in isolation. Every society must be considered
  5956. with its background of a wider environment of actual entities, which also
  5957. contribute their objectifications to which the members of the society must
  5958. conform. Thus the given contributions of the environment must at least
  5959. be permissive of the self-sustenance of the society. Also, in proportion to
  5960. its importance, this background must contribute those general characters
  5961. which the more special character of the society presupposes for its mem-
  5962. bers. But this means that the environment, together with the society in
  5963. question, must form a larger society in respect to some more general
  5964. characters than those defining the society from which we started. Thus we
  5965. arrive at the principle that every society requires a social background, of
  5966. which it is itself a part. In reference to any given society the world of actual
  5967. entities is to be conceived as forming a background in layers of social order,
  5968. the defining characteristics becoming wider and more general as we widen
  5969. the background. Of course, the remote actualities of the background have
  5970. their own specific characteristics of various types of social order. But such
  5971. specific characteristics have become irrelevant for the society in question
  5972. by reason of the inhibitions and attenuations introduced by discordance,
  5973. that is to say, by disorder.
  5974.  
  5975. The metaphysical characteristics of an actual entity— in the proper gen-
  5976. eral sense of 'metaphysics'— should be those which apply to all actual en-
  5977. tities. It may be doubted whether such metaphysical concepts have ever
  5978. [J 39] been formulated in their strict purity— even taking into account
  5979. the most general principles of logic and of mathematics. We have to con-
  5980. fine ourselves to societies sufficiently wide, and yet such that their defining
  5981. characteristics cannot safely be ascribed to all actual entities which have
  5982. been or may be.
  5983.  
  5984. The causal laws which dominate a social environment are the product
  5985.  
  5986. 5 Cf. Part I, Ch. Ill, Sect. II.
  5987.  
  5988.  
  5989.  
  5990. The Order of Nature 91
  5991.  
  5992. of the defining characteristic of that society. But the society is only efficient
  5993. through its individual members. Thus in a society, the members can only
  5994. exist by reason of the laws which dominate the society, and the laws only
  5995. come into being by reason of the analogous characters of the members
  5996. of the society.
  5997.  
  5998. But there is not any perfect attainment of an ideal order whereby the
  5999. indefinite endurance of a society is secured. A society arises from disorder,
  6000. where 'disorder 7 is defined by reference to the ideal for that society; the
  6001. favourable background of a larger environment either itself decays, or
  6002. ceases to favour the persistence of the society after some stage of growth:
  6003. the society then ceases to reproduce its members, and finally after a stage
  6004. of decay passes out of existence. Thus a system of 'laws' determining re-
  6005. production in some portion of the universe gradually rises into dominance;
  6006. it has its stage of endurance, and passes out of existence with the decay
  6007. of the society from which it emanates.
  6008.  
  6009. The arbitrary, as it were 'given/ elements in the laws of nature warn us
  6010. that we are in a special cosmic epoch. Here the phrase 'cosmic epoch' is
  6011. used to mean that widest society of actual entities whose immediate rele-
  6012. vance to ourselves is traceable. This epoch is characterized by electronic
  6013. and protonic actual entities, and by yet more ultimate actual entities which
  6014. can be dimly discerned in the quanta of energy. Maxwell's equations of
  6015. the electromagnetic field hold sway by reason of the throngs of electrons
  6016. and of protons. Also each electron is a society of electronic occasions, and
  6017. each proton is a soci- [MO] ety of protonic occasions. These occasions are
  6018. the reasons for the electromagnetic laws; but their capacity for reproduc-
  6019. tion, whereby each electron and each proton has a long life, and whereby
  6020. new electrons and new protons come into being, is itself due to these same
  6021. laws. But there is disorder in the sense that the laws are not perfectly
  6022. obeyed, and that the reproduction is mingled with instances of failure.
  6023. There is accordingly a gradual transition to new types of order, supervening
  6024. upon a gradual rise into dominance on the part of the present natural
  6025. laws.
  6026.  
  6027. But the arbitrary factors in the order of nature are not confined to the
  6028. electromagnetic laws. There are the four dimensions of the spatio-temporal
  6029. continuum, the geometrical axioms, even the mere dimensional character
  6030. of the continuum— apart from the particular number of dimensions— and
  6031. the fact of measurability. In later chapters (cf. Part IV) it will be evident
  6032. that all these properties are additional to the more basic fact of extensive-
  6033. ness; also, that even extensiveness allows of grades of specialization, arbi-
  6034. trarily one way or another, antecedently to the introduction of any of these
  6035. additional notions. By this discovery the logical and mathematical investi-
  6036. gations of the last two centuries are very relevant to philosophy. For the
  6037. cosmological theories of Descartes, Newton, Locke, Hume, and Kant were
  6038. framed in ignorance of that fact. Indeed, in the Timaeus Plato seems to be
  6039. more aware of it than any of his successors, in the sense that he frames
  6040.  
  6041.  
  6042.  
  6043. 92 Discussions and Applications
  6044.  
  6045. statements whose meaning is elucidated by its explicit recognition. These
  6046. 'given 7 factors in geometry point to the wider society of which the elec-
  6047. tronic cosmic epoch constitutes a fragment.
  6048.  
  6049. A society does not in any sense create the complex of eternal objects
  6050. which constitutes its defining characteristic. It only elicits that complex
  6051. into importance for its members, and secures the reproduction of its mem-
  6052. bership. In speaking of a society—unless the context ex- [141] pressly re-
  6053. quires another interpretation— 'membership' will always refer to the actual
  6054. occasions, and not to subordinate enduring objects composed of actual
  6055. occasions such as the life of an electron or of a man. These latter societies
  6056. are the strands of 'personal' order which enter into many societies; gen-
  6057. erally speaking, whenever we are concerned with occupied space, we are
  6058. dealing with this restricted type of corpuscular societies; and whenever
  6059. we are thinking of the physical field in empty space, we are dealing with
  6060. societies of the wider type. It seems as if the careers of waves of light illus-
  6061. trate the transition from the more restricted type to the wider type.
  6062.  
  6063. Thus our cosmic epoch is to be conceived primarily as a society of elec-
  6064. tromagnetic occasions, including electronic and protonic occasions, and
  6065. only occasionally— for the sake of brevity in statement—as a society of elec-
  6066. trons and protons. There is the same distinction between thinking of an
  6067. army either as a class of men, or as a class of regiments.
  6068.  
  6069. SECTION III
  6070.  
  6071. Thus the physical relations, the geometrical relations of measurement,
  6072. the dimensional relations, and the various grades of extensive relations,
  6073. involved in the physical and geometrical theory of nature, are derivative
  6074. from a series of societies of increasing width of prevalence, the more spe-
  6075. cial societies being included in the wider societies. This situation consti-
  6076. tutes the physical and geometrical order of nature. Beyond these societies
  6077. there is disorder, where 'disorder' is a relative term expressing the lack of
  6078. importance possessed by the defining characteristics of the societies in
  6079. question beyond their own bounds. When those societies decay, it will not
  6080. mean that their defining characteristics cease to exist; but that they lapse
  6081. into unimportance for the actual entities in question. The term 'disorder'
  6082. refers to a society only partially influential in impressing its characteristics
  6083. in the [142] form of prevalent laws. This doctrine, that order is a social
  6084. product, appears in modern science as the statistical theory of the laws of
  6085. nature, and in the emphasis on genetic relation.
  6086.  
  6087. But there may evidently be a state in which there are no prevalent so-
  6088. cieties securing any congruent unity of effect. This is a state of chaotic
  6089. disorder; it is disorder approaching an absolute sense of that term. In such
  6090. an ideal state, what is 'given' for any actual entity is the outcome of
  6091. thwarting, contrary decisions from the settled world. Chaotic disorder
  6092. means lack of dominant definition of compatible contrasts in the satisfac-
  6093.  
  6094.  
  6095.  
  6096. The Order of Nature 93
  6097.  
  6098. tions attained, and consequent enfeeblement of intensity. It means the
  6099. lapse towards slighter actuality. It is a natural figure of speech, but only
  6100. a figure of speech, to conceive a slighter actuality as being an approach
  6101. towards nonentity. But you cannot approach nothing; for there is nothing
  6102. to approach. It is an approach towards the futility of being a faint compro-
  6103. mise between contrary reasons. The dominance of societies, harmoniously
  6104. requiring each other, is the essential condition for depth of satisfaction.
  6105.  
  6106. The Timaeus of Plato, and the Scholium of Newton— the latter already
  6107. in large part quoted— are the two statements of cosmological theory which
  6108. have had the chief influence on Western thought. To the modern reader,
  6109. the Timaeus, considered as a statement of scientific details, is in compar-
  6110. ison with the Scholium simply foolish. But what it lacks in superficial de-
  6111. tail, it makes up for by its philosophic depth. If it be read as an allegory,
  6112. it conveys profound truth; whereas the Scholium is an immensely able
  6113. statement of details which, although abstract and inadequate as a philoso-
  6114. phy, can within certain limits be thoroughly trusted for the deduction of
  6115. truths at the same level of abstraction as itself. The penalty of its philo-
  6116. sophical deficiency is that the Scholium conveys no hint of the limits of
  6117. its own application. The practical effect is that the readers, and almost
  6118. certainly Newton himself, so construe its meaning as to fall into [143} what
  6119. I have elsewhere 6 termed the 'fallacy of misplaced concreteness/ It is the
  6120. office of metaphysics to determine the limits of the applicability of such
  6121. abstract notions.
  6122.  
  6123. The Scholium betrays its abstractness by affording no hint of that aspect
  6124. of self-production, of generation, of cf>6ai<;, of natura naturans, which is
  6125. so prominent in nature. For the Scholium, nature is merely, and com-
  6126. pletely, there, externally designed and obedient. The full sweep of the
  6127. modern doctrine of evolution would have confused the Newton of the
  6128. Scholium, but would have enlightened the Plato of the Timaeus. So far
  6129. as Newton is concerned, we have his own word for this statement. In a
  6130. letter to Bentley, he writes: "When I wrote my treatise about our system,
  6131. I had an eye upon such principles as might work with considering men for
  6132. the belief of a Deity; . . ." 7 The concept in Newton's mind is that of a
  6133. fully articulated system requiring a definite supernatural origin with that
  6134. articulation. This is the form of the cosmological argument, now generally
  6135. abandoned as invalid; because our notion of causation concerns the rela-
  6136. tions of states of things within the actual world, and can only be illegit-
  6137. imately extended to a transcendent derivation. The notion of God, which
  6138. will be discussed later (cf. Part V), is that of an actual entity immanent
  6139. in the actual world, but transcending any finite cosmic epoch — a being at
  6140. once actual, eternal, immanent, and transcendent. The transcendence of
  6141.  
  6142. 6 Cf. Science and the\ Modern World, Ch. III.
  6143.  
  6144. 7 This quotation is taken from Jebb's Life of Bentley, Ch. II. The Life is pub-
  6145. lished in the English Men of Letters series.
  6146.  
  6147.  
  6148.  
  6149. 94 Discussions and Applications
  6150.  
  6151. God is not peculiar to him. Every actual entity, in virtue ot its novelty,
  6152. transcends its universe, God included.
  6153.  
  6154. In the Scholium, space and time, with all their current mathematical
  6155. properties, are ready-made for the material masses; the material masses are
  6156. ready-made for the 'forces' which constitute their action and reaction; and
  6157. space, and time, and material masses, and forces, are [144] alike ready-
  6158. made for the initial motions which the Deity impresses throughout the
  6159. universe. It is not possible to extract from the Scholium— construed with
  6160. misplaced concreteness— either a theism, or an atheism, or an epistemology,
  6161. which can survive a comparison with the facts. This is the inescapable
  6162. conclusion to be inferred from Hume's Dialogues Concerning Natural Re-
  6163. ligion. Biology is also reduced to a mystery; and finally physics itself has
  6164. now reached a stage of experimental knowledge inexplicable in terms of
  6165. the categories of the Scholium.
  6166.  
  6167. In the Timaeus, there are many phrases and statements which find their
  6168. final lucid expression in the Scholium. While noting this concurrence of
  6169. the two great cosmological documents guiding Western thought, it can-
  6170. not be too clearly understood that, within its limits of abstraction, what
  6171. the Scholium says is true, and that it is expressed with the lucidity of
  6172. genius. Thus any cosmological document which cannot be read as an inter-
  6173. pretation of the Scholium is worthless. But there is another side to the
  6174. Timaeus which finds no analogy in the Scholium. In general terms, this
  6175. side of the Timaeus may be termed its metaphysical character, that is to
  6176. say, its endeavour to connect the behaviour of things with the formal na-
  6177. ture of things. The behaviour apart from the things is abstract, and so are
  6178. the things apart from their behaviour. Newton— wisely, for his purposes-
  6179. made this abstraction which the Timaeus endeavours to avoid.
  6180.  
  6181. In the first place, the Timaeus connects behaviour with the ultimate
  6182. molecular characters of the actual entities. Plato conceives the notion of
  6183. definite societies of actual molecular entities, each society with its de-
  6184. fining characteristics. He does not conceive this assemblage of societies as
  6185. causa sui. But he does conceive it as the work of subordinate deities, who
  6186. are the animating principles of those departments of nature. In Greek
  6187. thought, either poetic or philosophic, the separation between the cpOoiq
  6188. and such deities had not that absolute character which it has for us who
  6189. have inherited the Semitic Jehovah.
  6190.  
  6191. [J 45] Newton could have accepted a molecular theory as easily as Plato,
  6192. but there is this difference between them: Newton would have been sur-
  6193. prised at the modern quantum theory and at the dissolution of quanta into
  6194. vibrations; Plato would have expected it. While we note the many things
  6195. said by Plato in the Timaeus which are now foolishness, we must also give
  6196. him credit for that aspect of his teaching in which he was two thousand
  6197. years ahead of his time. Plato accounted for the sharp-cut differences be-
  6198. tween kinds of natural things, by assuming an approximation of the mole-
  6199.  
  6200.  
  6201.  
  6202. The Order of Nature 95
  6203.  
  6204. cules of the fundamental kinds respectively to the mathematical forms of
  6205. the regular solids. He also assumed that certain qualitative contrasts in oc-
  6206. currences, such as that between musical notes, depended on the participa-
  6207. tion of these occurrences in some of the simpler ratios between integral
  6208. numbers. He thus obtained a reason why there should be an approxima-
  6209. tion to sharp-cut differences between kinds of molecules, and why there
  6210. should be sharp-cut relations of harmony standing out amid dissonance.
  6211. Thus 'contrast'— as the opposite of incompatibility—depends on a certain
  6212. simplicity of circumstance; but the higher contrasts depend on the assem-
  6213. blage of a multiplicity of lower contrasts, this assemblage again exhibiting
  6214. higher types of simplicity.
  6215.  
  6216. It is well to remember that the modern quantum theory, + with its sur-
  6217. prises in dealing with the atom, is only the latest instance of a well-marked
  6218. character of nature, which in each particular instance is only explained by
  6219. some ad hoc dogmatic assumption. The theory of biological evolution
  6220. would not in itself lead us to expect the sharply distinguished genera and
  6221. species which we find in nature. There might be an occasional bunching of
  6222. individuals round certain typical forms; but there is no explanation of the
  6223. almost complete absence of intermediate forms. Again Newton's Scholium
  6224. gives no hint of the ninety-two possibilities for atoms, or of the limited
  6225. number of ways in which atoms can be combined so as to form molecules.
  6226. Physicists are now explaining these [J 46] chemical facts by means of con-
  6227. ceptions which Plato would have welcomed.
  6228.  
  6229. There is another point in which the organic philosophy only repeats
  6230. Plato. In the Timaeus the origin of the present cosmic epoch is traced back
  6231. to an aboriginal disorder, chaotic according to our ideals. This is the evolu-
  6232. tionary doctrine of the philosophy of organism. Plato's notion has puz-
  6233. zled critics who are obsessed with the Semitic 8 theory of a wholly tran-
  6234. scendent God creating out of nothing an accidental universe. Newton held
  6235. the Semitic theory. The Scholium made no provision for the evolution of
  6236. matter— very naturally, since the topic lay outside its scope. The result has
  6237. been that the non-evolution of matter has been a tacit presupposition
  6238. throughout modern thought. Until the last few years the sole alternatives
  6239. were: either the material universe, with its present type of order, is eternal;
  6240. or else it came into being, and will pass out of being, according to the fiat
  6241. of Jehovah. Thus, on all sides, Plato's allegory of the evolution of a new
  6242. type of order based on new types of dominant societies became a daydream,
  6243. puzzling to commentators.
  6244.  
  6245. Milton, curiously enough, in his Paradise Lost wavers between the
  6246. Timaeus and the Semitic doctrine. This is only another instance of the
  6247. intermixture of classical and Hebrew notions on which his charm of
  6248.  
  6249.  
  6250.  
  6251. 8 The book of Genesis is too primitive to bear upon this point.
  6252.  
  6253.  
  6254.  
  6255. 96 Discussions and Applications
  6256.  
  6257. thought depends. In the description of Satan's journey across Chaos, Satan
  6258. discovers
  6259.  
  6260. The secrets of the hoary deep, a dark
  6261.  
  6262. Illimitable ocean, without bound,
  6263.  
  6264. Without dimension, where length, breadth and highth,
  6265.  
  6266. And time and place are lost; where eldest Night f
  6267.  
  6268. And Chaos, ancestors of Nature, hold
  6269.  
  6270. Eternal anarchy amidst the noise
  6271.  
  6272. Of endless wars, and by confusion stand. 9
  6273.  
  6274. Milton is here performing for Plato the same poetic service that Lucre-
  6275. tius performed for Democritus—with [147] less justification, since Plato
  6276. was quite capable of being his own poet. Also the fact of Satan's journey
  6277. helped to evolve order; for he left a permanent track, useful for the devils
  6278. and the damned.
  6279.  
  6280. The appeal to Plato in this section has been an appeal to the facts
  6281. against the modes of expression prevalent in the last few centuries. These
  6282. recent modes of expression are partly the outcome of a mixture of theology
  6283. and philosophy, and are partly due to the Newtonian physics, no longer
  6284. accepted as a fundamental statement. But language and thought have been
  6285. framed according to that mould; and it is necessary to remind ourselves
  6286. that this is not the way in which the world has been described by some of
  6287. the greatest intellects. Both for Plato and for Aristotle the process of the
  6288. actual world has been conceived as a real incoming of forms into real po-
  6289. tentiality, issuing into that real togetherness which is an actual thing.
  6290. Also, for the Timaeus, the creation of the world is the incoming of a type
  6291. of order establishing a cosmic epoch. It is not the beginning of matter of
  6292. fact, but the incoming of a certain type of social order.
  6293.  
  6294. SECTION IV
  6295.  
  6296. The remainder of this chapter will be devoted to a discussion— largely
  6297. conjectural— of the hierarchy of societies composing our present epoch. In
  6298. this way, the preceding discussion of 'order' may be elucidated. It is to be
  6299. carefully noted that we are now deserting metaphysical generality. We shall
  6300. be considering the more special possibilities of explanation consistent with
  6301. our general cosmological doctrine, but not necessitated by it.
  6302.  
  6303. The physical world is bound together by a general type of relatedness
  6304. which constitutes it into an extensive continuum. When we analyse the
  6305. properties of this continuum we discover that they fall into two classes, of
  6306. which one— the more special— presupposes the other— the more general. 10
  6307. The more general type of properties [148] expresses the mere fact of 'ex-
  6308. tensive connection/ of 'whole and part/ of various types of 'geometrical
  6309.  
  6310. 9 Paradise Lost, Bk. II.
  6311.  
  6312. 10 Cf. Part IV for a detailed discussion.
  6313.  
  6314.  
  6315.  
  6316. The Order of Nature 97
  6317.  
  6318. elements' derivable by 'extensive abstraction ; but excluding the introduc-
  6319. tion of more special properties by which straight lines are definable xl and
  6320. measurability thereby introduced.
  6321.  
  6322. In these general properties of extensive connection, we discern the de-
  6323. fining characteristic of a vast nexus extending far beyond our immediate
  6324. cosmic epoch. It contains in itself other epochs, with more particular
  6325. characteristics incompatible with each other. Then from the standpoint of
  6326. our present epoch, the fundamental society in so far as it transcends our
  6327. own epoch seems a vast confusion mitigated by the few, faint elements of
  6328. order contained in its own defining characteristic of 'extensive connection. 7
  6329. We cannot discriminate its other epochs of vigorous order, and we merely
  6330. conceive it as harbouring the faint flush of the dawn of order in our own
  6331. epoch. This ultimate, vast society constitutes the whole environment within
  6332. which our epoch is set, so far as systematic characteristics are discernible
  6333. by us in our present stage of development. In the future the growth of
  6334. theory may endow our successors with keener powers of discernment.
  6335.  
  6336. Our logical analysis, in company with immediate intuition (inspectio),
  6337. enables us to discern a more special society within the society of pure ex-
  6338. tension. This is the 'geometrical 7 society. In this society 12 those specialized
  6339. relationships hold, in virtue of which straight lines are defined. Systematic
  6340. geometry is illustrated in such a geometrical society; and metrical rela-
  6341. tionships can be defined in terms of the analogies of function within the
  6342. scheme of any one systematic geometry. These 'analogies of function 7 are
  6343. what is meant by the notion of 'congruence. 7 This notion is nonsense apart
  6344. from a systematic geometry. The inclusion of extensive quantity [149]
  6345. among fundamental categoreal notions is a complete mistake. This notion
  6346. is definable in terms of each systematic geometry finding its application in a
  6347. geometrical society. It is to be noticed that a systematic geometry is deter-
  6348. mined by the definition of straight lines applicable to the society in ques-
  6349. tion. Contrary to the general opinio^ this definition is possible in inde-
  6350. pendence of the notion of 'measurement. 7 It cannot however be proved
  6351. that in the same geometrical society there may not be competing families
  6352. of loci with equal claims to the status of being a complete family of straight
  6353. lines.
  6354.  
  6355. Given a family of straight lines, expressing a system of relatedness in a
  6356. 'geometric 7 society, the notion of 'congruence 7 and thence of 'measurement 7
  6357. is now determinable in a systematic way throughout the society. But again
  6358. in this case there certainly are competing systems of measurement. Hence
  6359. in connection with each family of straight lines— allowing there be more
  6360. than one such family— there are alternative systems 13 of metrical geom-
  6361.  
  6362. ^ Cf. Part IV, Chs.t III, IV, V.
  6363.  
  6364. 12 Cf . Part IV, especially Chs. Ill, IV, V.
  6365.  
  6366. 13 The existence of alternative systems was demonstrated by Cayley in his
  6367. "Sixth Memoir on Quantics" in Transactions of the Royal Society, 1859.t
  6368.  
  6369.  
  6370.  
  6371. 98 Discussions and Applications
  6372.  
  6373. etry, no one system being more fundamental than the other. Our present
  6374. cosmic epoch is formed by an 'electromagnetic 7 society, which is a more
  6375. special society contained within the geometric society. In this society yet
  6376. more special defining characteristics obtain. These characteristics presup-
  6377. pose those of the two wider societies within which the 'electromagnetic'
  6378. society is contained. But in the ''electromagnetic' society the ambiguity as
  6379. to the relative importance of competing families of straight lines (if there
  6380. be such competing families), and the ambiguity as to the relative im-
  6381. portance of competing definitions of congruence, are determined in favour
  6382. of one family and one 14 congruence-definition. This determination is
  6383. effected by an additional set of physical relationships throughout the so-
  6384. ciety. But this set has lost [ISO] its merely systematic character because it
  6385. constitutes our neighbourhood. These relationships involve components ex-
  6386. pressive of certain individual diversities, and identities between the occa-
  6387. sions which are the members of the nexus. But these diversities and iden-
  6388. tities are correlated according to a systematic law expressible in terms of the
  6389. systematic measurements derived from the geometric nexus. We here
  6390. arrive at the notion of physical quantities which vary from individual to
  6391. individual; this is the notion of the systematization of individual differ-
  6392. ences, the notion of Taw/
  6393.  
  6394. It is the ideal of mathematical physicists to formulate this systematic
  6395. law in its complete generality for our epoch. It is sufficient for our purposes
  6396. to indicate the presumed character of this law by naming the members of
  6397. the society 'electromagnetic occasions/ Thus our present epoch is domi-
  6398. nated by a society of electromagnetic occasions. In so far as this dominance
  6399. approaches completeness, the systematic law which physics seeks is ab-
  6400. solutely dominant. In so far as the dominance is incomplete, the obedience
  6401. is a statistical fact with its corresponding lapses.
  6402.  
  6403. The electromagnetic society exhibits the physical electromagnetic field
  6404. which is the topic of physical science. The members of this nexus are the
  6405. electromagnetic occasions.
  6406.  
  6407. But in its turn, this electromagnetic society would provide no adequate
  6408. order for the production of individual occasions realizing peculiar 'inten-
  6409. sities 7 of experience unless it were pervaded by more special societies,
  6410. vehicles of such order. The physical world exhibits a bewildering com-
  6411. plexity of such societies, favouring each other, competing with each other.
  6412.  
  6413. The most general examples of such societies are the regular trains of
  6414. waves, individual electrons, protons, individual molecules, societies of
  6415. molecules such as inorganic bodies, living cells, and societies of cells such
  6416. as vegetable and animal bodies.
  6417.  
  6418. 14 The transformations into an indefinite variety of coordinates, to which the
  6419. 'tensor theory' refers, all presuppose one congruence-definition. t The invariance
  6420. of the Einsteinian *ds' expresses this fact.
  6421.  
  6422.  
  6423.  
  6424. The Order of Nature 99
  6425.  
  6426. SECTION V
  6427.  
  6428. [151] It is obvious that the simple classification (cf. Part I, Ch. Ill, Sect.
  6429. II) of societies into 'enduring objects/ 'corpuscular societies/ and 'non-
  6430. corpuscular societies' requires amplification. The notion of a society which
  6431. includes subordinate societies and nexus with a definite pattern of struc-
  6432. tural inter-relations f must be introduced. Such societies will be termed
  6433. 'structured/
  6434.  
  6435. A structured society as a whole provides a favourable environment for
  6436. the subordinate societies which it harbours within itself. Also the whole
  6437. society must be set in a wider environment permissive of its continuance.
  6438. Some of the component groups of occasions in a structured society can be
  6439. termed 'subordinate societies/ But other such groups must be given the
  6440. wider designation of 'subordinate nexus/ The distinction arises because in
  6441. some instances a group of occasions, such as ? for example, a particular en-
  6442. during entity, could have retained the dominant features of its defining
  6443. characteristic in the general environment, apart from the structured society.
  6444. It would have lost some features; in other words, the analogous sort of
  6445. enduring entity in the general environment is, in its mode of definiteness,
  6446. not quite identical with the enduring entity within the structured environ-
  6447. ment. But, abstracting such additional details from the generalized de-
  6448. fining characteristic, the enduring object with that generalized character-
  6449. istic may be conceived as independent of the structured society within
  6450. which it finds itself. t For example, we speak of a molecule within a living
  6451. cell, because its general molecular features are independent of the environ-
  6452. ment of the cell. Thus a molecule is a subordinate society in the structured
  6453. society which we call the 'living cell/
  6454.  
  6455. But there may be other nexus included in a structured society which,
  6456. excepting the general systematic characteristics of the external environ-
  6457. ment, present no features capable of genetically sustaining themselves apart
  6458. from [152] the special environment provided by that structured society.
  6459. It is misleading, therefore, to term such a nexus a 'society' when it is be-
  6460. ing considered in abstraction from the whole structured society. In such an
  6461. abstraction it can be assigned no 'social' features. Recurring to the example
  6462. of a living cell, it will be argued that the occasions composing the 'empty 7
  6463. space within the cell exhibit special features which analogous occasions out-
  6464. side the cell are devoid of. Thus the nexus, which is the empty space within
  6465. a living cell, is called a 'subordinate nexus/ but not a 'subordinate society/
  6466.  
  6467. Molecules are structured societies, and so in all probability are separate
  6468. electrons and protons. Crystals are structured societies. But gases are not
  6469. structured societies in any important sense of that term; although their
  6470. individual molecules are structured societies.
  6471.  
  6472. It must be remembered that each individual occasion within a special
  6473. form of society includes features which do not occur in analogous occasions
  6474.  
  6475.  
  6476.  
  6477. 100 Discussions and Applications
  6478.  
  6479. in the external environment. The first stage of systematic investigation
  6480. must always be the identification of analogies between occasions within the
  6481. society and occasions without it. The second stage is constituted by the
  6482. more subtle procedure of noting the differences between behaviour within
  6483. and without the society, differences t of behaviour exhibited by occasions
  6484. which also have close analogies to each other. The history of science is
  6485. marked by the vehement, dogmatic denial of such differences, until they
  6486. are found out.
  6487.  
  6488. An obvious instance of such distinction of behaviour is afforded by the
  6489. notion of the deformation of the shape of an electron according to varia-
  6490. tions in its physical situation.
  6491.  
  6492. A 'structured society 7 may be more or less 'complex' in respect to the
  6493. multiplicity of its associated sub-societies and sub-nexus and to the intricacy
  6494. of their structural pattern.
  6495.  
  6496. A structured society which is highly complex can be [153] correspond-
  6497. ingly favourable to intensity of satisfaction for certain sets of its com-
  6498. ponent members. This intensity arises by reason of the ordered complexity
  6499. of the contrasts which the society stages for these components.!
  6500.  
  6501. The structural relations gather intensity from this intensity in the in-
  6502. dividual experiences. Thus the growth of a complex structured society
  6503. exemplifies the general purpose pervading nature. The mere complexity of
  6504. givenness which procures incompatibilities has been superseded by the
  6505. complexity of order which procures contrasts.
  6506.  
  6507. SECTION VI
  6508.  
  6509. The doctrine that every society requires a wider social environment
  6510. leads to the distinction that a society may be more or less 'stabilized' in
  6511. reference to certain sorts of changes in that environment. A society is
  6512. 'stabilized' in reference to a species of change when it can persist through
  6513. an environment whose relevant parts exhibit that sort of change. If the
  6514. society would cease to persist through an environment with that sort of
  6515. heterogeneity, then the society is in that respect 'unstable/ A complex so-
  6516. ciety which is stable provided that the environment exhibits certain fea-
  6517. tures t is said to be 'specialized 7 in respect to those features. The notion of
  6518. 'specialization 7 seems to include both that of 'complexity 7 and that of
  6519. strictly conditioned 'stability/
  6520.  
  6521. An unspecialized society can survive through important changes in its
  6522. environment. This means that it can take on different functions in respect
  6523. to its relationship to a changing environment. In general the defining char-
  6524. acteristic of such a society will not include any particular determination
  6525. of structural pattern. By reason of this flexibility of structural pattern, the
  6526. society can adopt that special pattern adapted to the circumstances of the
  6527. moment. Thus an unspecialized society is apt to be deficient in structural
  6528. pattern, when viewed as a whole.
  6529.  
  6530.  
  6531.  
  6532. The Order of Nature 101
  6533.  
  6534. [154] Thus in general an unspecialized society does not secure conditions
  6535. favourable for intensity of satisfaction among its members, whereas t a
  6536. structured society with a high grade of complexity will in general be de-
  6537. ficient in survival value. In other words, such societies will in general be
  6538. 'specialized' in the sense of requiring a very special sort of environment.
  6539.  
  6540. Thus the problem t for Nature is the production of societies which are
  6541. 'structured' with a high 'complexity/ and which are at the same time 'un-
  6542. specialized. 7 In this way, intensity is mated with survival.
  6543.  
  6544. SECTION VII
  6545.  
  6546. There are two ways in which structured societies have solved this prob-
  6547. lem. Both ways depend on that enhancement of the mental pole, which
  6548. is a factor in intensity of experience. One way is by eliciting a massive
  6549. average objectification of a nexus, while eliminating the detailed diversities
  6550. of the various members of the nexus in question. This method, in fact,
  6551. employs the device of blocking out unwelcome detail. It depends on the
  6552. fundamental truth that objectification is abstraction. It utilizes this abstrac-
  6553. tion inherent in objectification so as to dismiss the thwarting elements of a
  6554. nexus into negative prehensions. At the same time the complex intensity
  6555. in the structured society is supported by the massive objectifications of the
  6556. many environmental nexus, each in its unity as one nexus, and not in its
  6557. multiplicity as many actual occasions.
  6558.  
  6559. This mode of solution requires the intervention of mentality operating in
  6560. accordance with the Category of Transmutation (i.e., Categoreal Obliga-
  6561. tion VI ) . It ignores diversity of detail by overwhelming the nexus by means
  6562. of some congenial uniformity which pervades it. The environment may
  6563. then change indefinitely so far as concerns the ignored details— so long as
  6564. they can be ignored.
  6565.  
  6566. The close association of all physical bodies, organic and [155] inorganic
  6567. alike, with 'presented loci' definable 15 by straight lines, suggests that this
  6568. development of mentality is characteristic of the actual occasions which
  6569. make up the structured societies which we know as 'material bodies; This
  6570. close association is evidenced by the importance of 'acceleration' in the
  6571. science of dynamics.! For 'acceleration 7 is nothing else than a mode of
  6572. estimating the shift from one family of 'presented loci' to another such
  6573. family (cf. Part IV).
  6574.  
  6575. Such mentality represents the first grade of ascent beyond the mere re-
  6576. productive stage which employs nothing more than the Category of Con-
  6577. ceptual Reproduction (i.e., Categoreal Obligation IV). There is some
  6578. initiative of conceptual integration, but no originality in conceptual pre-
  6579. hension. This initiative belongs to the Category of Transmutation, and the
  6580. excluded originality belongs to the Category of Reversion.
  6581.  
  6582. 15 Cf. Ch. IV of this Partt and also Part IV.
  6583.  
  6584.  
  6585.  
  6586. 102 Discussions and Applications
  6587.  
  6588. These material bodies belong to the lowest grade of structured societies
  6589. which are obvious to our gross apprehensions. They comprise societies of
  6590. various types of complexity— crystals, rocks, planets, and suns. Such bodies
  6591. are easily the most long-lived of the structured societies known to us,
  6592. capable of being traced through their individual life-histories.
  6593.  
  6594. The second way of solving the problem is by an initiative in conceptual
  6595. prehensions, i.e., in appetition. The purpose of this initiative is to receive
  6596. the novel elements of the environment into explicit feelings with such sub-
  6597. jective forms as conciliate them with the complex experiences proper to
  6598. members of the structured society. Thus in each concrescent occasion its
  6599. subjective aim originates novelty to match the novelty of the environment.
  6600.  
  6601. In the case of the higher organisms, this conceptual initiative amounts to
  6602. thinking about the diverse experiences; in the case of lower organisms,! this
  6603. conceptual initiative merely amounts to thoughtless adjustment of aesthetic
  6604. emphasis in obedience to an ideal of harmony. [156] In either case the
  6605. creative determination which transcends the occasion in question has been
  6606. deflected by an impulse original to that occasion. This deflection in general
  6607. originates a self-preservative reaction throughout the whole society. It may
  6608. be unfortunate or inadequate; and in the case of persistent failure we are
  6609. in the province of pathology.
  6610.  
  6611. This second mode of solution also presupposes the former mode. Thus
  6612. the Categories of Conceptual Reversion and of Transmutation are both
  6613. called into play.
  6614.  
  6615. Structured societies in which the second mode of solution has im-
  6616. portance are termed 'living/ It is obvious that a structured society may have
  6617. more or less 'life/ and that there is no absolute gap between living' and
  6618. 'non-living 7 societies. For certain purposes, whatever 'life' there is in a
  6619. society may be important; and for other purposes, unimportant.
  6620.  
  6621. A structured society in which the second mode is unimportant, and the
  6622. first mode is important will be termed 'inorganic'
  6623.  
  6624. In accordance with this doctrine of life, 7 the primary meaning of 'life'
  6625. is the origination of conceptual novelty— novelty of appetition. Such origi-
  6626. nation can only occur in accordance with the Category of Reversion. Thus
  6627. a society is only to be termed 'living' in a derivative sense. A 'living society'
  6628. is one which includes some 'living occasions.' Thus a society may be more
  6629. or less 'living,' according to the prevalence in it of living occasions. Also
  6630. an occasion may be more or less living according to the relative importance
  6631. of the novel factors in its final satisfaction.
  6632.  
  6633. Thus the two ways in which dominant members of structured societies
  6634. secure stability amid environmental novelties are (i) elimination of diver-
  6635. sities of detail, and (ii) origination of novelties of conceptual reaction. As
  6636. the result, there is withdrawal or addition of those details of emphasis
  6637. whereby the subjective aim directs the [157] integration of prehensions in
  6638. the concrescent phases of dominant members.
  6639.  
  6640.  
  6641.  
  6642. The Order of Nature 103
  6643.  
  6644. SECTION VIII
  6645.  
  6646. There is yet another factor in 'living 7 societies which requires more de-
  6647. tached analysis. A structured society consists in the patterned intertwining
  6648. of various nexus with markedly diverse defining characteristics. Some of
  6649. these nexus are of lower types than others, and some will be of markedly
  6650. higher types. There will be the 'subservient' nexus and the 'regnant 7 nexus
  6651. within the same structured society. This structured society will provide the
  6652. immediate environment which sustains each of its sub-societies, subservient
  6653. and regnant alike. In a living society only some of its nexus will be such
  6654. that the mental poles of all their members have any original reactions.
  6655. These will be its 'entirely living 7 nexus, and in practice a society is only
  6656. called 'living 7 when such nexus are regnant. Thus a living society involves
  6657. nexus which are 'inorganic/ and nexus which are inorganic do not need
  6658. the protection of the whole 'living 7 society for their survival in a changing
  6659. external I environment. Such nexus are societies. But 'entirely living 7 nexus
  6660. do require such protection, if they are to survive. According to this con-
  6661. jectural theory, an 'entirely living 7 nexus is not a 'society. 7 This is the theory
  6662. of the animal body, including a unicellular body as a particular instance.
  6663. A complex inorganic system of interaction is built up for the protection of
  6664. the 'entirely living 7 nexus, and the originative actions of the living elements
  6665. are protective of the whole system. On the other hand, the reactions! of
  6666. the whole system provide the intimate environment required by the 'en-
  6667. tirely living 7 nexus. We do not know of any living society devoid of its sub-
  6668. servient apparatus of inorganic societies.
  6669.  
  6670. 'Physical Physiology deals with the subservient inorganic apparatus; and
  6671. 'Psychological Physiology 7 seeks to deal with 'entirely living 7 nexus, partly
  6672. in abstraction [158] from the inorganic apparatus, and partly in respect to
  6673. their response to the inorganic apparatus, and partly in regard to their
  6674. response to each other. Physical Physiology has, in the last century, estab-
  6675. lished itself as a unified science; Psychological Physiology is still in the
  6676. process of incubation.
  6677.  
  6678. It must be remembered that an integral living society, as we know it, not
  6679. only includes the subservient inorganic apparatus, but also includes many
  6680. living nexus,t at least one for each 'cell/
  6681.  
  6682. SECTION IX
  6683.  
  6684. It will throw light upon the cosmology of the philosophy of organism to
  6685. conjecture some fundamental principles of Psychological Physiology as
  6686. suggested by that cosmology and by the preceding conjectures concerning
  6687. the 'societies 7 of our epoch. These principles are not necessitated by this
  6688. cosmology; but they seem to be the simplest principles which are both
  6689. consonant with that cosmology, and also fit the facts.
  6690.  
  6691.  
  6692.  
  6693. 104 Discussions and Applications
  6694.  
  6695. In the first instance, consider a single living cell. Such a cell includes
  6696. subservient inorganic societies, such as molecules and electrons. Thus, the
  6697. cell is an 'animal body'; and we must presuppose the physical physiology 7
  6698. proper to this instance. But what of the individual living occasions?
  6699.  
  6700. The first question to be asked is as to whether the living occasions, in
  6701. abstraction from the inorganic occasions of the animal body, form a cor-
  6702. puscular sub-society, so that each living occasion is a member of an en-
  6703. during entity with its personal order. In particular we may ask whether
  6704. this corpuscular society reduces to the extreme instance of such a society,
  6705. namely, to one enduring entity with its one personal order. f
  6706.  
  6707. The evidence before us is of course extremely slight; but so far as it
  6708. goes, it suggests a negative answer to both these questions. A cell gives no
  6709. evidence whatever of a single unified mentality, guided in each of its occa-
  6710. [J59] sions by inheritance from its own past. The problem to be solved is
  6711. that of a certain originality in the response of a cell to external stimulus.
  6712. The theory of an enduring entity with its inherited mentality gives us a
  6713. reason why this mentality should be swayed by its own past. We ask for
  6714. something original at the moment, and we are provided with a reason for
  6715. limiting originality. Life is a bid for freedom: an enduring entity binds
  6716. any one of its occasions to the line of its ancestry. The doctrine of the
  6717. enduring soul with its permanent characteristics is exactly the irrelevant
  6718. answer to the problem which life presents. That problem is, How can there
  6719. be originality? And the answer explains how the soul need be no more
  6720. original than a stone.
  6721.  
  6722. The theory of a corpuscular society, made up of many enduring entities,
  6723. fits the evidence no better. The same objections apply. The root fact is that
  6724. 'endurance 7 is a device whereby an occasion is peculiarly bound by a single
  6725. line of physical ancestry, while 'life 7 means novelty, introduced in accord-
  6726. ance with the Category of Conceptual Reversion. There are the same
  6727. objections to many traditions as there are to one tradition. What has to be
  6728. explained is originality of response to stimulus. This amounts to the doc-
  6729. trine that an organism is 'alive 7 when in some measure its reactions are
  6730. inexplicable by any tradition of pure physical inheritance.
  6731.  
  6732. Explanation by 'tradition 7 is merely another phraseology for explana-
  6733. tion by 'efficient cause. 7 We require explanation by 'final cause. 7 Thus a
  6734. single occasion is alive when the subjective aim which determines its pro-
  6735. cess of concrescence has introduced a novelty of definiteness not to be
  6736. found in the inherited data of its primary phase. The novelty is introduced
  6737. conceptually and disturbs the inherited 'responsive 7 adjustment of subjec-
  6738. tive forms. It alters the 'values/ in the artist's sense of that term.
  6739.  
  6740. It follows from these considerations that in abstraction from its animal
  6741. body an 'entirely living* nexus is not [J 60] properly a society at all, since
  6742. 'life' cannot be a defining characteristic. It is the name for originality, and
  6743. not for tradition. The mere response to stimulus is characteristic of all
  6744. societies whether inorganic or alive. Action and reaction are bound to-
  6745.  
  6746.  
  6747.  
  6748. The Order of Nature 105
  6749.  
  6750. gether. The characteristic of life is reaction adapted to the capture of in-
  6751. tensity, under a large variety of circumstances. But the reaction is dictated
  6752. by the present and not by the past. It is the clutch at vivid immediacy.
  6753.  
  6754. SECTION X
  6755.  
  6756. Another characteristic of a living society is that it requires food. In a
  6757. museum the crystals are kept under glass cases; in zoological gardens the
  6758. animals are fed. Having regard to the universality of reactions with envi-
  6759. ronment, the distinction is not quite absolute. It cannot, however, be
  6760. ignored. The crystals are not agencies requiring the destruction of elab-
  6761. orate societies derived from the environment; a living society is such an
  6762. agency. The societies which it destroys are its food. This food is destroyed
  6763. by dissolving it into somewhat simpler social elements. It has been robbed
  6764. of something. Thus, all societies require interplay with their environment;
  6765. and in the case of living societies this interplay takes the form of robbery.
  6766. The living society may, or may not, be a higher type of organism than the
  6767. food which it disintegrates. But whether or no it be for the general good,
  6768. life is robbery. It is at this point that with life morals become acute. The
  6769. robber requires justification.
  6770.  
  6771. The primordial appetitions which jointly constitute God's purpose are
  6772. seeking intensity, and not preservation. Because they are primordial, there
  6773. is nothing to preserve. He, in his primordial nature, is unmoved by love for
  6774. this particular, or that particular; for in this foundational process of crea-
  6775. tivity, there are no preconstituted particulars. In the foundations of his
  6776. being, God is indifferent alike to preservation and to novelty. [161] He
  6777. cares not whether an immediate occasion be old or new, so far as concerns
  6778. derivation from its ancestry. His aim 16 for it is depth of satisfaction as an
  6779. intermediate step towards the fulfilment of his own being. His tenderness
  6780. is directed towards each actual occasion, as it arises.
  6781.  
  6782. Thus God's purpose in the creative advance is the evocation of inten-
  6783. sities. The evocation of societies is purely subsidiary to this absolute end.
  6784. The characteristic of a living society is that a complex structure of in-
  6785. organic societies is woven together for the production of a non-social nexus
  6786. characterized by the intense physical experiences of its members. But such
  6787. an experience is derivate from the complex order of the material animal
  6788. body, and not from the simple 'personal order' of past occasions with
  6789. analogous experience. There is intense experience without the shackle of
  6790. reiteration from the past. This is the condition for spontaneity of concep-
  6791. tual reaction. The conclusion to be drawn from this argument is that life
  6792. is a characteristic of 'empty space' and not of space 'occupied' by any cor-
  6793. puscular society. In a nexus of living occasions, there is a certain social
  6794. deficiency. Life lurks in the interstices of each living cell, and in the in-
  6795.  
  6796. 16 Cf. Part V.
  6797.  
  6798.  
  6799.  
  6800. 106 Discussions and Applications
  6801.  
  6802. terstices of the brain. In the history of a living society, its more vivid
  6803. manifestations wander to whatever quarter is receiving from the animal
  6804. body an enormous variety of physical experience. This experience, if
  6805. treated inorganically, must be reduced to compatibility by the normal ad-
  6806. justments of mere responsive reception. This means the dismissal of in-
  6807. compatible elements into negative prehensions.
  6808.  
  6809. The complexity of the animal body is so ordered that in the critical por-
  6810. tions of its interstices the varied datum of physical experience is complex,
  6811. and on the edge of a compatibility beyond that to be achieved by mere in-
  6812. organic treatment. A novel conceptual prehension disturbs [162] the sub-
  6813. jective forms of the initial responsive phase. Some negative prehensions are
  6814. thus avoided, and higher contrasts are introduced into experience.
  6815.  
  6816. So far as the functioning of the animal body is concerned, the total
  6817. result is that the transmission of physical influence, through the empty
  6818. space within it, has not been entirely in conformity with the physical laws
  6819. holding for inorganic societies. The molecules within an animal body ex-
  6820. hibit certain peculiarities of behaviour not to be detected outside an animal
  6821. body. In fact, living societies illustrate the doctrine that the laws of nature
  6822. develop together with societies which constitute an epoch. There are sta-
  6823. tistical expressions of the prevalent types of interaction. In a living cell, the
  6824. statistical balance has been disturbed.
  6825.  
  6826. The connection of 'food' with 'life' is now evident. The highly complex
  6827. inorganic societies required for the structure of a cell, or other living body,
  6828. lose their stability amid the diversity of the environment. But, in the
  6829. physical field of empty space produced by the originality of living occasions,
  6830. chemical dissociations and associations take place which would not other-
  6831. wise occur. The structure is breaking down and being repaired. The food
  6832. is that supply of highly complex societies from the outside which, under the
  6833. influence of life, will enter into the necessary associations to repair the
  6834. waste. Thus life acts as though it were a catalytic agent.
  6835.  
  6836. The short summary of this account of a living cell is as follows: (i) an
  6837. extremely complex and delicately poised chemical structure; (ii) for the
  6838. occasions in the interstitial f 'empty' space a complex objective datum
  6839. derived from this complex structure; (iii) under normal 'responsive' treat-
  6840. ment, devoid of originality, the complex detail reduced to physical sim-
  6841. plicity by negative prehensions; (iv) this detail preserved for positive feel-
  6842. ing by the emotional and purposive readjustments produced by originality
  6843. of conceptual feeling (appetition); (v) the physical distortion of the field,
  6844. leading to instability of [163] the structure; (vi) the structure accepting
  6845. repair by food from the environment.
  6846.  
  6847. SECTION XI
  6848.  
  6849. The complexity of nature is inexhaustible. So far we have argued that the
  6850. nature of life is not to be sought by its identification with some society of
  6851.  
  6852.  
  6853.  
  6854. The Order of Nature 107
  6855.  
  6856. occasions, which are living in virtue of the defining characteristic of that
  6857. society. An 'entirely living' nexus is 7 in respect to its life, not social. Each
  6858. member of the nexus derives the necessities of its being from its prehen-
  6859. sions of its complex social environment; by itself the nexus lacks the genetic
  6860. power which belongs to 'societies/ But a living nexus, though non-social in
  6861. virtue of its life/ may support a thread of personal order along some his-
  6862. torical route of its members. Such an enduring entity is a living person/
  6863. It is not of the essence of life to be a living person. Indeed a living person
  6864. requires that its immediate environment be a living, non-social nexus.
  6865.  
  6866. The defining characteristic of a living person is some definite type of
  6867. hybrid prehensions transmitted from occasion to occasion of its existence.
  6868. The term 'hybrid' is defined more particularly in Part III. It is sufficient
  6869. to state here that a 'hybrid' prehension is the prehension by one subject of
  6870. a conceptual prehension, or of an 'impure' prehension, belonging to the
  6871. mentality of another subject. By this transmission the mental originality
  6872. of the living occasions receives a character and a depth. In this way origi-
  6873. nality is both 'canalized'— to use Bergson's word— and intensified. Its range
  6874. is widened within limits. Apart from canalization, depth of originality
  6875. would spell disaster for the animal body. With it, personal mentality can
  6876. be evolved, so as to combine its individual originality with the safety of the
  6877. material organism on which it depends. Thus life turns back into society: it
  6878. binds originality within bounds, and gains the massiveness due to reiterated
  6879. character.
  6880.  
  6881. In the case of single cells, of vegetation, and of the [164] lower forms of
  6882. animal life, we have no ground for conjecturing living personality. But in
  6883. the case of the higher animals there is central direction, which suggests
  6884. that in their case each animal body harbours a living person, or living per-
  6885. sons. Our own self-consciousness is direct awareness of ourselves as such
  6886. persons. 17 There are limits to such unified control, which indicate dis-
  6887. sociation of personality, multiple personalities in successive alternations,
  6888. and even multiple personalities in joint possession. This last case belongs
  6889. to the pathology of religion, and in primitive times has been interpreted as
  6890. demoniac possession. Thus, though life in its essence is the gain of inten-
  6891. sity through freedom, yet it can also submit to canalization and so gain the
  6892. massiveness of order. But it is not necessary merely to presuppose the
  6893. drastic case of personal order. We may conjecture, though without much
  6894. evidence, that even in the lowest form of life the entirely living nexus is
  6895. canalized into some faint form of mutual conformity. Such conformity
  6896. amounts to social order depending on hybrid prehensions of originalities in
  6897. the mental poles of the antecedent members of the nexus. The survival
  6898. power, arising from adaptation and regeneration, is thus explained. Thus
  6899. life is a passage from physical order to pure mental originality, and from
  6900.  
  6901. 17 This account of a living personality requires completion by reference to its
  6902. objectification in the consequent nature of God. Cf. Part V, Ch. II.
  6903.  
  6904.  
  6905.  
  6906. 108 Discussions and Applications
  6907.  
  6908. pure mental originality to canalized mental originality. It must also be
  6909. noted that the pure mental originality works by the canalization of rele-
  6910. vance arising from the primordial nature of God. Thus an originality in the
  6911. temporal world is conditioned, though not determined, by an initial sub-
  6912. jective aim supplied by the ground of all order and of all originality.
  6913.  
  6914. Finally, we have to consider the type of structured + society which gives
  6915. rise to the traditional body-mind problem. For example, human men-
  6916. tality is partly the outcome of the human body, partly the single directive
  6917. [165] agency of the body, partly a system of cogitations which have a cer-
  6918. tain irrelevance to the physical relationships of the body. The Cartesian
  6919. philosophy is based upon the seeming fact— the plain fact— of one body
  6920. and one mind, which are two substances in causaU association. For the
  6921. philosophy of organism the problem is transformed.
  6922.  
  6923. Each actuality is essentially bipolar, physical and mental, and the physi-
  6924. cal inheritance is essentially accompanied by a conceptual reaction partly
  6925. conformed to it, and partly introductory of a+ relevant novel contrast, but
  6926. always introducing emphasis, valuation, and purpose. The integration of
  6927. the physical and mental side into a unity of experience is a self-formation
  6928. which is a process of concrescence, and which by the principle of objective
  6929. immortality characterizes the creativity which transcends it. So though
  6930. mentality is non-spatial, mentality is always a reaction from, and integra-
  6931. tion with, physical experience which is spatial. It is obvious that we must
  6932. not demand another mentality presiding over these other actualities (a
  6933. kind of Uncle Sam, over and above all the U.S. citizens). All the life in
  6934. the body is the life of the individual cells. There are thus millions upon
  6935. millions of centres of life in each animal body. So what needs to be ex-
  6936. plained is not dissociation of personality but unifying control, by reason
  6937. of which we not only have unified behaviour, which can be observed by
  6938. others, but also consciousness of a unified experience.
  6939.  
  6940. A good many actions do not seem to be due to the unifying control, e.g.,
  6941. with proper stimulants a heart can be made to go on beating after it has
  6942. been taken out of the body. There are centres of reaction and control which
  6943. cannot be identified with the centre of experience. This is still more so with
  6944. insects. For example, worms and jellyfish seem to be merely harmonized
  6945. cells, very little centralized; when cut in two, their parts go on performing
  6946. their functions independently. Through a series of animals we can trace a
  6947. progressive rise into a [166] centrality of control. Insects have some cen-
  6948. tral control; even in man, many of the body's actions are done with some
  6949. independence, but with an organ of central control of very high-grade char-
  6950. acter in the brain.
  6951.  
  6952. The state of things, according to the philosophy of organism, is very dif-
  6953. ferent from the Scholastic view of St. Thomas Aquinas, of the mind as in-
  6954. forming the body. The living body is a coordination of high-grade actual
  6955. occasions; but in a living body of a low type the occasions are much nearer
  6956. to a democracy. In a living body of a high type there are grades of occa-
  6957.  
  6958.  
  6959.  
  6960. The Order of Nature 109
  6961.  
  6962. sions so coordinated by their paths of inheritance through the body, that
  6963. a peculiar richness of inheritance is enjoyed by various occasions in some
  6964. parts of the body. Finally, the brain is coordinated so that a peculiar rich-
  6965. ness of inheritance is enjoyed now by this and now by that part; and thus
  6966. there is produced the presiding personality at that moment in the body.
  6967. Owing to the delicate organization of the body, there is a returned influ-
  6968. ence, an inheritance of character derived from the presiding occasion and
  6969. modifying the subsequent occasions through the rest of the body.
  6970.  
  6971. We must remember the extreme generality of the notion of an enduring
  6972. object— a genetic character inherited through a historic route of actual
  6973. occasions. Some kinds of enduring objects form material bodies, others do
  6974. not. But just as the difference between living and non-living occasions is
  6975. not sharp, but more or less, so the distinction between an enduring object
  6976. which is an atomic material body and one which is nott is again more or
  6977. less. Thus the question as to whether to call an enduring object a transition
  6978. of matter or of character is very much a verbal question as to where you
  6979. draw the line between the various properties (cf. the way in which the
  6980. distinction between matter and radiant energy has now vanished).
  6981.  
  6982. Thus in an animal body the presiding occasion, if there be one, is the
  6983. final node, or intersection, of a complex [167} structure of many enduring
  6984. objects. Such a structure pervades the human body. The harmonized rela-
  6985. tions of the parts of the body constitute this wealth of inheritance into a
  6986. harmony of contrasts, issuing into intensity of experience. The inhibitions
  6987. of opposites have been adjusted into the contrasts of opposites. The human
  6988. mind is thus conscious of its bodilyt inheritance. There is also an enduring
  6989. object formed by the inheritance from presiding occasion to presiding oc-
  6990. casion. This endurance of the mind is only one more example of the gen-
  6991. eral principle on which the body is constructed. This route of presiding
  6992. occasions probably wanders from part to part of the brain, dissociated from
  6993. the physical material atoms. But central personal dominance is only partial,
  6994. and in pathological cases is apt to vanish.
  6995.  
  6996.  
  6997.  
  6998. CHAPTER IV
  6999. ORGANISMS AND ENVIRONMENT
  7000.  
  7001. SECTION I
  7002.  
  7003. [168] So far the discussion has chiefly concentrated upon the discrimina-
  7004. tion of the modes of functioning which in germ, or in mere capacity, are
  7005. represented in the constitution of each actual entity. The presumption
  7006. that there is only one genus of actual entities constitutes an ideal of cos-
  7007. mological theory to which the philosophy of organism endeavours to don-
  7008. form. The description of the generic character of an actual entity should
  7009. include God, as well as the lowliest actual occasion, though there is a spe-
  7010. cific difference between the nature of God and that of any occasion.
  7011.  
  7012. Also the differences between actual occasions, arising from the charac-
  7013. ters of their data, and from the narrowness and widths of their feelings,
  7014. and from the comparative importance of various stages, enable a classifica-
  7015. tion to be made whereby these occasions are gathered into various types.
  7016. From the metaphysical standpoint these types are not to be sharply dis-
  7017. criminated; as a matter of empirical observation, the occasions do seem to
  7018. fall into fairly distinct classes.
  7019.  
  7020. The character of an actual entity is finally governed by its datum; what-
  7021. ever be the freedom of feeling arising in the concrescence, there can be no
  7022. transgression of the limitations of capacity inherent in the datum. The
  7023. datum both limits and supplies. It follows from this doctrine that the
  7024. character of an organism depends on that of its environment. But the
  7025. character of an environment is the sum of the characters of the various
  7026. societies of actual entities which jointly constitute that envi- [J 69] ron-
  7027. ment; although it is pure assumption that every environment is com-
  7028. pletely overrun by societies of entities. Spread through the environment
  7029. there may be many entities which cannot be assigned to any society of
  7030. entities. The societies in an environment will constitute its orderly ele-
  7031. ment, and the non-social actual entities will constitute its element of
  7032. chaos. There is no reason, so far as our knowledge is concerned, to con-
  7033. ceive the actual world as purely orderly, or as purely chaotic.
  7034.  
  7035. Apart from the reiteration gained from its societies, an environment
  7036. does not provide the massiveness of emphasis capable of dismissing its
  7037. contrary elements into negative prehensions. Any ideal of depth of satis-
  7038. faction, arising from the combination of narrowness and width, can only
  7039. be achieved through adequate order. In proportion to the chaos there is
  7040. triviality. There are different types of order; and it is not true that in pro-
  7041.  
  7042.  
  7043.  
  7044. Organisms and Environment 111
  7045.  
  7046. portion to the orderliness there is depth. There are various types of order,
  7047. and some of them provide more trivial satisfaction than do others. Thus,
  7048. if there is to be progress beyond limited ideals, the course of history by
  7049. way of escape must venture along the borders of chaos in its substitution
  7050. of higher for lower types of order.
  7051.  
  7052. The immanence of God gives reason for the belief that pure chaos is
  7053. intrinsically impossible. At the other end of the scale, the immensity of
  7054. the world negatives the belief that any state of order can be so established
  7055. that beyond it there can be no progress. This belief in a final order, popu-
  7056. lar in religious and philosophic thought, seems to be due to the prevalent
  7057. fallacy that all types of seriality necessarily involve terminal instances.
  7058. It follows that Tennyson's phrase,
  7059.  
  7060. . . . onef far-off divine event
  7061.  
  7062. To which the whole creation moves,
  7063.  
  7064. presents a fallacious conception of the universe.
  7065.  
  7066. An actual entity must be classified in respect to its [170] 'satisfaction/
  7067. and this arises out of its datum by the operations constituting its 'process/
  7068. Satisfactions can be classified by reference to 'triviality/ Vagueness/ 'nar-
  7069. rowness/ 'width.' Triviality and vagueness are characteristics in the satis-
  7070. faction which have their origins respectively in opposed characteristics in
  7071. the datum. Triviality arises from lack of coordination in the factors of the
  7072. datum, so that no feeling arising from one factor is reinforced by any
  7073. feeling arising from another factor. In other words, the specific constitu-
  7074. tion of the actual entity in question is not such as to elicit depth of feel-
  7075. ing from contrasts thus presented. Incompatibility has predominated over
  7076. contrast. Then the process can involve no coordinating intensification
  7077. either from a reinforced narrowness, or from enhancement of relevance
  7078. due to the higher contrasts derived from harmonized width. Triviality is
  7079. due to the wrong sort of width; that is to say, it is due to width without
  7080. any reinforced narrowness in its higher categories. Harmony is this com-
  7081. bination of width and narrowness. Some narrow concentration on a
  7082. limited set of effects is essential for depth; but the difference arises in the
  7083. levels of the categories of contrast involved. A high category involves un-
  7084. plumbed potentiality for the realization of depth in its lower components.
  7085. Thus 'triviality' arises from excess of incompatible differentiation.
  7086.  
  7087. On the other hand, 'vagueness' is due to excess of identification. In the
  7088. datum the objectifications of various actual entities are replicas with faint
  7089. coordinations of perspective contrast. Under these conditions the con-
  7090. trasts between the various objectifications are faint, and there is deficiency
  7091. in supplementary feeling discriminating the objects from each other.
  7092. There can thus be intensive narrowness in the prehension of the whole
  7093. nexus, by reason of the common character,! combined with vagueness,
  7094. which is the irrelevance of the differences between the definite actual en-
  7095. tities of the nexus. The objectified entities reinforce each other by their
  7096.  
  7097.  
  7098.  
  7099. 112 Discussions and Applications
  7100.  
  7101. likeness. But there [171] is lack of differentiation among the component
  7102. objectifications owing to the deficiency in relevant contrasts.
  7103.  
  7104. In this way a group of actual entities contributes to the satisfaction as
  7105. one extensive whole. It is divisible, but the actual divisions, and their
  7106. sporadic differences of character, have sunk into comparative irrelevance
  7107. beside the one character belonging to the whole and any of its parts.
  7108.  
  7109. By reason of vagueness, many count as one, and are subject to indefi-
  7110. nite possibilities of division into such multifold unities. When there is
  7111. such vague prehension, the differences between the actual entities so pre-
  7112. hended are faint chaotic factors in the environment, and have thereby
  7113. been relegated to irrelevance. Thus vagueness is an essential condition for
  7114. the narrowness which is one condition for depth of relevance. It enables a
  7115. background to contribute its relevant quota, and it enables a social group
  7116. in the foreground to gain concentrated relevance for its community of
  7117. character. The right chaos, and the right vagueness, are jointly required
  7118. for any effective harmony. They produce the massive simplicity which has
  7119. been expressed by the term 'narrowness/ Thus chaos is not to be identified
  7120. with evil; for harmony requires the due coordination of chaos, vagueness,
  7121. narrowness, and width.
  7122.  
  7123. According to this account, the background in which the environment is
  7124. set must be discriminated into two layers. There is first the relevant back-
  7125. ground, providing a massive systematic uniformity. This background is
  7126. the presupposed world to which all ordinary propositions refer. Secondly,
  7127. there is the more remote chaotic background which has merely an irrelevant
  7128. triviality, so far as concerns direct objectification in the actual entity in
  7129. question. This background represents those entities in the actual world
  7130. with such perspective remoteness that there is even a chaos of diverse
  7131. cosmic epochs. In the background there is triviality, vagueness, and mas-
  7132. sive uniformity; in the foreground discrimination and [172] contrasts, but
  7133. always negative prehensions of irrelevant diversities.
  7134.  
  7135. SECTION II
  7136.  
  7137. Intensity is the reward of narrowness. The domination of the environ-
  7138. ment by a few social groups is the factor producing both the vagueness of
  7139. discrimination between actual entities and the intensification of relevance
  7140. of common characteristics. These are the two requisites for narrowness.
  7141. The lower organisms have low-grade types of narrowness; the higher or-
  7142. ganisms have intensified contrasts in the higher categories. In describing
  7143. the capacities, realized or unrealized, of an actual occasion, we have, with
  7144. Locke, tacitly taken human experience as an example upon which to
  7145. found the generalized description required for metaphysics. But when we
  7146. turn to the lower organisms we have first to determine which among such
  7147. capacities fade from realization into irrelevance, that is to say, by com-
  7148. parison with human experience which is our standard.
  7149.  
  7150.  
  7151.  
  7152. Organisms and Environment 113
  7153.  
  7154. In any metaphysical scheme founded upon the Kantian or Hegelian
  7155. traditions, experience is the product of operations which lie among the
  7156. higher of the human modes of functioning. For such schemes, ordered ex-
  7157. perience is the result of schematization of modes of thought, concerning
  7158. causation, substance, quality, quantity.
  7159.  
  7160. The process by which experiential unity is attained f is thereby con-
  7161. ceived in the guise of modes of thought. The exception is to be found in
  7162. Kant's preliminary sections on 'Transcendental Aesthetic/ by which he
  7163. provides space and time. But Kant, following Hume, assumes the radical
  7164. disconnection of impressions qua data; and therefore conceives his tran-
  7165. scendental aesthetic* to be the mere description of a subjective process
  7166. appropriating the data by orderliness of feeling.
  7167.  
  7168. The philosophy of organism aspires to construct a critique of pure
  7169. feeling, in the philosophical position in [173] which Kant put his Critique
  7170. of Pure Reason. This should also supersede the remaining Critiques re-
  7171. quired in the Kantian philosophy. Thus in the organic philosophy Kant's
  7172. 'Transcendental Aesthetic' becomes a distorted fragment of what should
  7173. have been his main topic. The datum includes its own interconnections,
  7174. and the first stage of the process of feeling is the reception into the
  7175. ^responsive conformity of feeling whereby the datum, which is mere po-
  7176. tentiality, becomes the individualized basis for a complex unity of
  7177. realization.
  7178.  
  7179. This conception, as found in the philosophy of organism, is practically
  7180. identical with Locke's ways of thought in the latter half of his Essay. He
  7181. speaks of the ideas in the perceived objects, and tacitly presupposes their
  7182. identification with corresponding ideas in the perceiving mind. The ideas in
  7183. the objects have been appropriated by the subjective functioning of the
  7184. perceiving mind. This mode of phraseology can be construed as a casual
  7185. carelessness of speech on the part of Locke, or a philosophic inconsistency.
  7186. But apart from this inconsistency Locke's philosophy falls to pieces; as in
  7187. fact was its fate in the hands of Hume.
  7188.  
  7189. There is, however, a fundamental misconception to be found in Locke,
  7190. and in prevalent doctrines of perception. It concerns the answer to the
  7191. question t as to the description of the primitive types of experience. Locke
  7192. assumes that the utmost primitiveness is to be found in sense-perception.
  7193. The seventeenth-century physics, with the complexities of primary and
  7194. secondary qualities, should have warned philosophers that sense-percep-
  7195. tion was involved in complex modes of functioning. Primitive feeling is to
  7196. be found at a lower level. The mistake was natural for mediaeval and Greek
  7197. philosophers: for they had not modern physics before them as a plain
  7198. warning. In sense-perception we have passed the Rubicon, dividing direct
  7199. perception from the higher forms of mentality, which play with error and
  7200. thus found intellectual empires.
  7201.  
  7202. [174] The more primitive types of experience are concerned with sense-
  7203. reception, and not with sense-perception. This statement will require some
  7204.  
  7205.  
  7206.  
  7207. 114 Discussions and Applications
  7208.  
  7209. prolonged explanation. But the course of thought can be indicated by
  7210. adopting Bergson's admirable phraseology, sense-reception is 'unspatial-
  7211. ized/ and sense-perception is 'spatialized/ In sense-reception the sensa are
  7212. the definiteness of emotion: they are emotional forms transmitted from
  7213. occasion to occasion. Finally in some occasion of adequate complexity, the
  7214. Category of Transmutation endows them with the new function of charac-
  7215. terizing nexus.
  7216.  
  7217.  
  7218.  
  7219. SECTION HI
  7220.  
  7221. In the first place, those eternal objects which will be classified under the
  7222. name 'sensa' constitute the lowest category of eternal objects. Such eternal
  7223. objects do not express a manner of relatedness between other eternal ob-
  7224. jects. They are not contrasts, or patterns. Sensa are necessary as com-
  7225. ponents in any actual entity, relevant in the realization of the higher
  7226. grades. But a sensum does not, for its own realization, require any eternal
  7227. object of a lower grade, though it does involve the potentiality of pattern
  7228. and does gain access of intensity from some realization of status in some
  7229. realized pattern. Thus a sensum requires, as a rescue from its shallowness
  7230. of zero width, some selective relevance of wider complex eternal objects
  7231. which include it as a component; but it does not involve the relevance of
  7232. any eternal objects which it presupposes. Thus, in one sense, a sensum is
  7233. simple; for its realization does not involve the concurrent realization of
  7234. certain definite eternal objects, which are its definite simple components.
  7235. But, in another sense, each sensum is complex; for it cannot be dissociated
  7236. from its potentiality for ingression into any actual entity, and fromf its
  7237. potentiality of contrasts and of patterned relationships with other eternal
  7238. objects. Thus each sensum shares the characteristic common to all eternal
  7239. objects, that it introduces the notion of the logi- [175] cal variable, in both
  7240. forms, the unselective 'any' and the selective 'some/
  7241.  
  7242. It is possible that this definition of 'sensa' excludes some cases of con-
  7243. trast which are ordinarily termed 'sensa' and that it includes some emo-
  7244. tional qualities which are ordinarily excluded. Its convenience consists in
  7245. the fact that it is founded on a metaphysical principle, and not on an
  7246. empirical investigation of the physiology of the human body.
  7247.  
  7248. Narrowness in the lowest category achieves such intensity as belongs to
  7249. such experience, but fails by reason of deficiency of width. Contrast elicits
  7250. depth, and only shallow experience is possible when there is a lack of pat-
  7251. terned contrast. Hume notices the comparative failure of the higher fa-
  7252. culty of imagination in respect to mere sensa. He exaggerates this com-
  7253. parative failure into a dogma of absolute inhibition to imagine a novel
  7254. sensum; whereas the evidence which he himself adduces, of the imagina-
  7255. tion of a new shade of colour to fill a gap in a graduated scale of shades,
  7256. shows t that a contrast between given shades can be imaginatively extended
  7257. so as to generate the imagination of the missing shade. But Hume's ex-
  7258.  
  7259.  
  7260.  
  7261. Organisms and Environment 115
  7262.  
  7263. ample also shows that imagination finds its easiest freedom among the
  7264. higher categories of eternal objects,
  7265.  
  7266. A pattern is in a sense simple: a pattern is the 'manner' of a complex
  7267. contrast abstracted from the specific eternal objects which constitute the
  7268. 'matter' of the contrast. But the pattern refers unselectively to any eternal
  7269. objects with the potentiality of being elements in the 'matter' of some
  7270. contrast in that 'manner/
  7271.  
  7272. A pattern and a sensum are thus both simple in the sense that neither
  7273. involves other specified eternal objects in its own realization. The manner
  7274. of a pattern is the individual essence of the pattern. But no individual
  7275. essence is realizable apart from some of its potentialities of relationship,
  7276. that is, apart from its relational essence. But a pattern lacks simplicity in
  7277. another sense, in which \176] a sensum retains simplicity. The realization
  7278. of a pattern necessarily involves the concurrent realization of a group of
  7279. eternal objects capable of contrast in that pattern. The realization of the
  7280. pattern is through the realization of this contrast. The realization might
  7281. have occurred by means of another contrast in the same pattern; but
  7282. some complex contrast in that pattern is required. But the realization of a
  7283. sensum in its ideal shallowness of intensity, with zero width, does not
  7284. require any other eternal object, other than its intrinsic apparatus of indi-
  7285. vidual and relational essence; it can remain just itself, with its unrealized
  7286. potentialities for patterned contrasts. An actual entity with this absolute
  7287. narrowness has an ideal faintness of satisfaction, differing from the ideal
  7288. zero of chaos, but equally impossible. For realization means ingression in
  7289. an actual entity, and this involves the synthesis of all ingredients with data
  7290. derived from a complex universe. Realization is ideally distinguishable
  7291. from the ingression of contrasts, but not in fact.
  7292.  
  7293. The simplest grade of actual occasions must be conceived as experienc-
  7294. ing a few sensa, with the minimum of patterned contrast. The sensa are
  7295. then experienced emotionally, and constitute the specific feelings whose
  7296. intensities sum up into the unity of satisfaction. In such occasions the proc-
  7297. ess is deficient in its highest phases; the process is the slave to the datum.
  7298. There is the individualizing phase of conformal feeling, but the originative
  7299. phases of supplementary and conceptual feelings f are negligible.
  7300.  
  7301. SECTION IV
  7302.  
  7303. According to this account, the experience of the simplest grade of ac-
  7304. tual entity is to be conceived as the unoriginative response to the datum
  7305. with its simple content of sensa. The datum is simple, because it presents
  7306. the objectified experiences of the past under the guise of simplicity. Occa-
  7307. sions A, B, and C enter into the experience of occasion M as themselves
  7308. experiencing [177] sensa Si and s 2 unified by some faint contrast between
  7309. s x and s 2 . Occasion JVf responsively feels sensa $1 and s 2 as its own sensa-
  7310. tions. There is thus a transmission of sensation emotion from A, B, and C
  7311. to M. If M had the wit of self-analysis, M would know that it felt its own
  7312.  
  7313.  
  7314.  
  7315. 116 Discussions and Applications
  7316.  
  7317. sensa, by reason of a transfer from A, B, and C to itself. Thus the (un-
  7318. conscious) direct perception of A, B, and C is merely the causal efficacy
  7319. of A, B, and C as elements in the constitution of M. Such direct percep-
  7320. tion will suffer from vagueness; for if A, B, and C tell the same tale with
  7321. minor variation of intensity, the discrimination of A, and B, and C from
  7322. each other will be irrelevant. There may thus remain a sense of the causal
  7323. efficacy of actual presences, whose exact relationships in the external world
  7324. are shrouded. Thus the experience of M is to be conceived as a quantitative
  7325. emotion arising from the contribution of sensa from A, B, C and propor-
  7326. tionately conformed to by M.
  7327.  
  7328. Generalizing from the language of physics, the experience of M is an
  7329. intensity arising out of specific sensa, directed from A, B, C. There is in
  7330. fact a directed influx from A, B, C of quantitative feeling, arising from
  7331. specific forms of feeling. The experience has a vector character, a common
  7332. measure of intensity, and specific forms of feelings conveying that inten-
  7333. sity. If we substitute the term 'energy' for the concept of a quantitative
  7334. emotional intensity, and the term 'form of energy 7 for the concept of
  7335. 'specific form of feeling/ and remember that in physics Vector' means defi-
  7336. nite transmission from elsewhere, we see that this metaphysical description
  7337. of the simplest elements in the constitution of actual entities agrees ab-
  7338. solutely with the general principles according to which the notions of
  7339. modern physics are framed. The 'datum/ in metaphysics is the basis of the
  7340. vector-theory in physics; the quantitative satisfaction in metaphysics is
  7341. the basis of the scalar localization of energy in physics; the 'sensa' in
  7342. metaphysics are the basis of the diversity of specific forms under which
  7343. energy clothes itself. Sci- [178] entific descriptions are, of course, entwined
  7344. with the specific details of geometry and physical laws, which arise from
  7345. the special order of the cosmic epoch in which we find ourselves. But the
  7346. general principles of physics are exactly what we should expect as a spe-
  7347. cific exemplification of the metaphysics required by the philosophy of
  7348. organism. It has been a defect in the modern philosophies that they throw
  7349. no light whatever on any scientific principles. Science should investigate
  7350. particular species, and metaphysics should investigate the generic notions
  7351. under which those specific principles should fall. Yet, modern realisms
  7352. have had nothing to say about scientific principles; and modern idealisms
  7353. have merely contributed the unhelpful suggestion that the phenomenal
  7354. world is one of the inferior avocations of the Absolute.
  7355.  
  7356. The direct perception whereby the datum in the immediate subject is
  7357. inherited from the past can thus, under an abstraction, be conceived as the
  7358. transference of throbs of emotional energy, clothed in the specific forms
  7359. provided by sensa. Since the vagueness in the experientf subject will veil
  7360. the separate objeetifi cations wherein there are individual contributions
  7361. to the total satisfaction, the emotional energy in the final satisfaction wears
  7362. the aspect of a total intensity capable of all gradations of ideal variation.
  7363. But in its origin it represents the totality arising from the contributions of
  7364.  
  7365.  
  7366.  
  7367. Organisms and Environment 117
  7368.  
  7369. separate objects to that form of energy. Thus, having regard to its origin,
  7370. a real atomic structure of each form of energy is discernible, so much from
  7371. each objectified actual occasion; and only a finite number of actual occa-
  7372. sions will be relevant.
  7373.  
  7374. This direct perception, characterized by mere subjective responsiveness
  7375. and by lack of origination in the higher phases, exhibits the constitution
  7376. of an actual entity under the guise of receptivity. In the language of causa-
  7377. tion, it describes the efficient causation operative in the actual world. In
  7378. the language of epistemology, as framed by Locke, it describes how the
  7379. ideas of particular [179] existents are absorbed into the subjectivity of the
  7380. percipient and are the datum for its experience of the external world. In
  7381. the language of science, it describes how the quantitative intensity of lo-
  7382. calized energy bears in itself the vector marks of its origin, and the spe-
  7383. cialities of its specific forms; it also gives a reason for the atomic quanta
  7384. to be discerned in the building up of a quantity of energy. In this way,
  7385. the philosophy of organism— as it should— appeals to the facts.
  7386.  
  7387. SECTION V
  7388.  
  7389. The current accounts of perception are the stronghold of modern meta-
  7390. physical difficulties. They have their origin in the same misunderstanding
  7391. which led to the incubus of the substance-quality categories. The Greeks
  7392. looked at a stone, and perceived that it was grey. The Greeks were ig-
  7393. norant of modern physics; but modern philosophers discuss perception in
  7394. terms of categories derived from the Greeks.
  7395.  
  7396. The Greeks started from perception in its most elaborate and sophisti-
  7397. cated form, namely, visual perception. In visual perception, crude per-
  7398. ception is most completely made over by the originative phases in ex-
  7399. perience, phases which are especially prominent in human experience. If
  7400. we wish to disentangle the two earlier prehensive phases— the receptive
  7401. phases, namely, the datum and the subjective response— from the more
  7402. advanced originative phases, we must consider what is common to all
  7403. modes of perception, amid the bewildering variety of originative
  7404. amplification.
  7405.  
  7406. On this topic I am content to appeal to Hume. He writes: "But my
  7407. senses convey to me only the impressions of coloured points, disposed in a
  7408. certain manner. If the eye is sensible of any thingt further, I desire it may
  7409. be pointed out to me/' 1 And again: "It is universally allowed by the
  7410. writers on optics, that the eye at all times sees an equal number of physical
  7411. points, and that a man [180] on the top of a mountain has no larger an
  7412. image presented to his senses, than when he is cooped up in the narrow-
  7413. est court or chamber." 2
  7414.  
  7415. In each of these quotations Hume explicitly asserts that the eye sees.
  7416.  
  7417. 1 Treatise, Bk. U Part II, Sect. III. Italics not his.
  7418.  
  7419. 2 Treatise, Bk. I, Part III, Sect. IX.*
  7420.  
  7421.  
  7422.  
  7423. 118 Discussions and Applications
  7424.  
  7425. The conventional comment on such a passage is that Hume, for the sake
  7426. of intelligibility, is using common forms of expression; that he is only
  7427. really speaking of impressions on the mind; and that in the dim future,
  7428. some learned scholar will gain reputation by emending 'eye' into 'ego/
  7429. The reason for citing the passages is to enforce the thesis that the form
  7430. of speech is literary and intelligible because it expresses the ultimate truth
  7431. of animal perception. The ultimate momentary 'ego' has as its datum the
  7432. 'eye as experiencing such-and-such f sights/ In the second quotation, the
  7433. reference to the number of physical points is a reference to the excited
  7434. area on the retina. Thus the 'eye as experiencing such-and-such sights' is
  7435. passed on as a datum 7 from the cells of the retina, throughf the train of
  7436. actual entities forming the relevant nerves, up to the brain. Any direct
  7437. relation of eye to brain is entirely overshadowed by this intensity of in-
  7438. direct transmission. Of course this statement is merely a pale abstraction
  7439. from the physiological theory of vision. But the physiological account
  7440. does not pretend to be anything more than indirect inductive knowledge.
  7441. The point here to be noticed is the immediate literary obviousness of 'the
  7442. eye as experiencing such-and-such sights/ This is the very reason why
  7443. Hume uses the expression in spite of his own philosophy. The conclusion,
  7444. which the philosophy of organism draws, is that in human experience the
  7445. fundamental fact of perception is the inclusion, in the datum, of the ob-
  7446. jectification of an antecedent part of the human body with such-and-such
  7447. experiences. Hume agrees with this conclusion f sufficiently well so as to
  7448. argue from it, when it suits his purpose. He writes:
  7449.  
  7450. I would fain ask those philosophers, who found so much of their
  7451. reasonings on the distinction [J 81] of substance and accident, and
  7452. imagine we have clear ideas of each, whether the idea of substance be
  7453. derived from the impressions of sensation or reflection? If it be con-
  7454. veyed to usf by our senses, I ask, which of them, and after what man-
  7455. ner? If it be perceived by the eyes, it must be a colour; if by the ears, a
  7456. sound; if by the palate, a taste; and so of the other senses. 3
  7457. We can prolong Hume's list: the feeling of the stone is in the hand; the
  7458. feeling of the food is the ache in the stomach; the compassionate yearning
  7459. is in the bowels, according to biblical writers; the feeling of well-being is in
  7460. the viscera passim; ill temper is the emotional tone derivative from the
  7461. disordered liver.
  7462.  
  7463. In this list, Hume's and its prolongation, for some cases—as in sight,
  7464. for example— the supplementary phase in the ultimate subject overbal-
  7465. ances in importance the datum inherited from the eye. In other cases, as
  7466. in touch, the datum of 'the feeling in the hand' maintains its importance,
  7467. however much the intensity, or even the character, of the feeling may be
  7468. due to supplementation in the ultimate subject: this instance should be
  7469. contrasted with that of sight. In the instance of the ache the stomach, as
  7470.  
  7471. 3 Treatise, Bk. I, Part I, Sect. VI.
  7472.  
  7473.  
  7474.  
  7475. Organisms and Environment 119
  7476.  
  7477. datum, is of chief importance, and the food though obscurely felt is
  7478. secondary— at least, until the intellectual analysis of the situation due to
  7479. the doctor, professional or amateur. In the instances of compassion, well-
  7480. being, and ill temper, the supplementary feelings in the ultimate subject
  7481. predominate, though there are obscure references to the bodily organs as
  7482. inherited data.
  7483.  
  7484. This survey supports the view that the predominant basis of perception
  7485. is perception of the various bodily organs, as passing on their experiences
  7486. by channels of transmission and of enhancement. It is the accepted doc-
  7487. trine in physical science that a living body is to be interpreted according
  7488. to what is known of other sections of the physical universe. This is a sound
  7489. axiom; but it [182] is double-edged. For it carries with it the converse de-
  7490. duction that other sections of the universe are to be interpreted in ac-
  7491. cordance with what we know of the human body.
  7492.  
  7493. It is also a sound rule that all interpretation should be based upon a
  7494. vera causa. Now the original reliance upon 'the grey stone 7 has been
  7495. shown by modern physics to be due to a misapprehension of a complex
  7496. situation; but we have direct knowledge of the relationship of our central
  7497. intelligence to our bodily feelings. According to this interpretation, the
  7498. human body is to be conceived as a complex 'amplifier'— to use the lan-
  7499. guage of the technology of electromagnetism. The various actual entities,
  7500. which compose the body, are so coordinated that the experiences of any
  7501. part of the body are transmitted to one or more central occasions to be
  7502. inherited with enhancements accruing upon the way, or finally added by
  7503. reason of the final integration. The enduring personality is the historic
  7504. route of living occasions which are severally dominant in the body at suc-
  7505. cessive instants. The human body is thus achieving on a scale of concen-
  7506. trated efficiency a type of social organization, which with every gradation
  7507. of efficiency constitutes the orderliness whereby a cosmic epoch shelters in
  7508. itself intensity of satisfaction.
  7509.  
  7510. The crude aboriginal character of direct perception is inheritance. What
  7511. is inherited is feeling-tone with evidence of its origin: in other words, vector
  7512. feeling-tone. In the higher grades of perception vague feeling-tone dif-
  7513. ferentiates itself into various types of sensa— those of touch, sight, smell,
  7514. etc.— each transmuted into a definite prehension of tonal contemporary
  7515. nexus f by the final percipient.
  7516.  
  7517. SECTION VI
  7518.  
  7519. In principle, the animal body is only the more highly organized and
  7520. immediate part of the general environment for its dominant actual occa-
  7521. sion, which is the ultimate [183] percipient. But the transition from with-
  7522. out to within the body marks the passage from lower to higher grades of
  7523. actual occasions. The higher the grade, the more vigorous and the more
  7524. original is the enhancement from the supplementary phase. Pure recep-
  7525.  
  7526.  
  7527.  
  7528. 120 Discussions and Applications
  7529.  
  7530. tivity and transmission givef place to the trigger-action of life whereby
  7531. there is release of energy in novel forms. Thus the transmitted datum ac-
  7532. quires sensa enhanced in relevance or even changed in character by the
  7533. passage from the low-grade external world into the intimacy of the human
  7534. body. The datum transmitted from the stone becomes the touch-feeling
  7535. in the hand, but it preserves the vector characterf of its origin from the
  7536. stone. The touch-feeling in the hand with this vector origin from the stone
  7537. is transmitted to the percipient in the brain. Thus the final perception is
  7538. the perception of the stone through the touch in the hand. In this per-
  7539. ception the stone is vague and faintly relevant in comparison with the
  7540. hand. But, however dim, it is there.
  7541.  
  7542. In the transmission of inheritance from A to B, to C, to D, A is ob-
  7543. jectified by the eternal object S as a datum for B; where S is a sensum or a
  7544. complex pattern of sensa. Then B is objectified for C. But the datum for
  7545. B is thereby capable of some relevance for C, namely, A as objectified for
  7546. B becomes reobjectified for C; and so on to D 7 and throughout the line of
  7547. objectifications. Then for the ultimate subject M the datum includes A as
  7548. thus transmitted, B as thus transmitted, and so on. The final objectifica-
  7549. tions for M are effected by a set S 3 f of eternal objects which is a modifica-
  7550. tion of the original group S. The modification consists partly in relegation
  7551. of elements into comparative irrelevance, partly in enhancement of rele-
  7552. vance for other elements, partly in supplementation by eliciting into
  7553. important relevance some eternal objects not in the original S. Generally
  7554. there will be vagueness in the distinction between A, and B, and C, and
  7555. D, etc., in their function as components in the datum for M. Some of the
  7556. line, A and C for instance, may stand out \184] with distinctness by rea-
  7557. son of some peculiar feat of original supplementation which retains its
  7558. undimmed importance in subsequent transmission. Other members of the
  7559. chain may sink into oblivion. For example, in touch there is a reference to
  7560. the stone in contact with the hand, and a reference to the hand; but in
  7561. normal, healthy, bodily operations the chain of occasions along the arm
  7562. sinks into the background, almost into complete oblivion. Thus M, which
  7563. has some analytic consciousness of its datum, is conscious of the feeling in
  7564. its hand as the hand touches the stone. According to this account, per-
  7565. ception in its primary form is consciousness of the causal efficacy of the
  7566. external world by reason of which the percipient is a concrescence from a
  7567. definitely constituted datum. The vector character of the datum is this
  7568. causal efficacy.
  7569.  
  7570. Thus perception, in this primary sense, is perception of the settled
  7571. world in the past as constituted by its feeling-tones, and as efficacious by
  7572. reason of those feeling-tones. Perception, in this sense of the term, will be
  7573. called 'perception in the mode of causal efficacy/ Memory is an example
  7574. of perception in this mode. For memory is perception relating to the data
  7575. from some historic route of ultimate percipient subjects Mi, M 2 , M 3 ,
  7576. etc., leading up to M which is the memorizing percipient.
  7577.  
  7578.  
  7579.  
  7580. Organisms and Environment 121
  7581.  
  7582.  
  7583.  
  7584. SECTION VII
  7585.  
  7586. It is evident that 'perception in the mode of causal efficacy' is not that
  7587. sort of perception which has received chief attention in the philosophical
  7588. tradition. Philosophers have disdained the information about the universe
  7589. obtained through their visceral feelings, and have concentrated on visual
  7590. feelings.
  7591.  
  7592. What we ordinarily term our visual perceptions are the result of the
  7593. later stages in the concrescence of the percipient occasion. When we
  7594. register in consciousness our visual perception of a grey stone, something
  7595. more than bare sight is meant. The 'stone' has a reference [185] to its
  7596. past, when it could have been used as a+ missile if small enough, or as a seat
  7597. if large enough. A 'stone' has certainly a history, and probably a future. It is
  7598. one of the elements in the actual world which has got to be referred to
  7599. as an actual reason and not as an abstract potentiality. But we all know
  7600. that the mere sight involved, in the perception of the grey stone, is the
  7601. sight of a grey shape contemporaneous with the percipient, and with
  7602. certain spatial relations to the percipient, more or less vaguely defined.
  7603. Thus the mere sight is confined to the illustration of the geometrical
  7604. perspective relatedness, of a certain contemporary spatial region, to the
  7605. percipient, the illustration being effected by the mediation of 'grey/ The
  7606. sensum 'grey' rescues that region from its vague confusion with other
  7607. regions.
  7608.  
  7609. Perception which merely, by means of a sensum, rescues from vagueness
  7610. a contemporary spatial region, in respect to its spatial shape and its spatial
  7611. perspective from the percipient, will be called 'perception in the mode of
  7612. presentational immediacy.'
  7613.  
  7614. Perception in this mode has already been considered in Part II, Chapter
  7615. II. A more elaborate discussion of it can now be undertaken. 4 The defini-
  7616. tion, which has just been given, extends beyond the particular case of
  7617. sight. The unravelling of the complex interplay between the two modes of
  7618. perception— causal efficacy and presentational immediacy— t is one main
  7619. problem of the theory of perception. 5 The ordinary philosophical discus-
  7620. sion of perception is almost wholly concerned with this interplay, and
  7621. ignores the two pure modes which are essential for its proper explanation.
  7622. The interplay between the two modes will be termed 'symbolic reference.'
  7623.  
  7624. [186] Such symbolic reference is so habitual in human experience that
  7625. great care is required to distinguish the two modes. In order to find ob-
  7626.  
  7627. 4 Also cf.f subsequent discussions in Parts III and IV.
  7628.  
  7629. 5 Cf. my Barbour-Page lectures, Symbolism, Its Meaning and Effect, delivered
  7630. at the University of Virginia, April, 1927 (New York: Macrnillan, 1927; Cam-
  7631. bridge University Press, 1928).+ Another discussion of this question is there
  7632. undertaken, with other illustrations, Cf. also Professor Norman Kemp Smith's
  7633. Prolegomena to an Idealist Theory of Knowledge, Macrnillan, 1924.
  7634.  
  7635.  
  7636.  
  7637. 122 Discussions and Applications
  7638.  
  7639. vious examples of the pure mode of causal efficacy we must have recourse
  7640. to the viscera and to memory; and to find examples of the pure mode of
  7641. presentational immediacy we must have recourse to so-called 'delusive'
  7642. perceptions. For example, the image of a grey stone as seen in a mirror
  7643. illustrates the space behind the mirror; the visual delusions arising from
  7644. some delirium, or some imaginative excitement, illustrate surrounding
  7645. spatial regions; analogously for the double-vision due to maladjustment of
  7646. the eyes; the sight at night, of the stars and nebulae and Milky Way,
  7647. illustrates vague regions of the contemporary sky; the feelings in ampu-
  7648. tated limbs illustrate spaces beyond the actual body; a bodily pain, re-
  7649. ferred to some part not the cause of the disorder, illustrates the painful
  7650. region though not the pain -giving region. All these are perfectly good ex-
  7651. amples of the pure mode of presentational immediacy.
  7652.  
  7653. The epithet 'delusive/ which fits many, if not all, of these examples of
  7654. presentational immediacy, is evidence that the mediating eternal object is
  7655. not to be ascribed to the donation of the perceived region. It must have
  7656. acquired its ingression in this mode from one of the originative phases of
  7657. the percipient occasion. To this extent, the philosophy of organism is in
  7658. agreement with the seventeenth-century doctrine of primary and second-
  7659. ary qualities, the mediating eternal object being, in this mode of ingres-
  7660. sion, a secondary quality. But in the philosophy of organism the doctrine
  7661. does not have the consequences which follow in the earlier philosophies.
  7662.  
  7663. The account of perception in the pure mode of presentational imme-
  7664. diacy, which has just been given, agrees absolutely with Descartes' doctrine
  7665. of perception in general, so far as can be judged from his arguments which
  7666. presuppose perception, and putting aside a few detached [J 87] passages
  7667. wherein he comes near to the doctrine of 'objectification' and near to
  7668. Locke's second doctrine of 'ideas determined to particular existents.' Any-
  7669. how, his conclusion immediately follows that, in perception, thus de-
  7670. scribed, all that is perceived is that the object has extension and is
  7671. implicated in a complex of extensive relatedness with the animal body
  7672. of the percipient. Part of the difficulties of Cartesian philosophy, and
  7673. of any philosophy which accepts this account as a complete account
  7674. of perception, is to explain how we know more than this meagre fact
  7675. about the world although our only avenue of direct knowledge limits
  7676. us to this barren residium. Also, if this be all that we perceive about
  7677. the physical world, we have no basis for ascribing the origination of
  7678. the mediating sensa to any functioning of the human body. We are thus
  7679. driven to the Cartesian duality of substances, bodies and minds. Percep-
  7680. tion is to be ascribed to mental functioning in respect to the barren ex-
  7681. tensive universe. We have already done violence to our immediate con-
  7682. viction by thus thrusting the human body out of the story; for, as Hume
  7683. himself declares, we know that we see by our eyes, and taste by our palates.
  7684. But when we have gone so far, it is inevitable to take a further step, and
  7685. to discard our other conviction that we are perceiving a world of actual
  7686.  
  7687.  
  7688.  
  7689. Organisms and Environment 123
  7690.  
  7691. things within which we find ourselves. For a barren, extensive world is not
  7692. really what we mean. We thus reduce perceptions to consciousness of
  7693. impressions on the mind, consisting of sensa with 'manners' of related-
  7694. ness. We then come to Hume, and to Kant. Kant's philosophy is an en-
  7695. deavour to retrieve some meaning for the two convictions which we have
  7696. successively discarded. We have noted that Locke wavers in his account of
  7697. perception, so that in the earlier portion of his Essay he agrees with Hume,
  7698. and in the later portion with the philosophy of organism. We have also
  7699. noted that Hume is inconsistent to the extent of arguing from a convic-
  7700. tion which is discarded in his philosophy.
  7701.  
  7702. SECTION VIII
  7703.  
  7704. [188] Presentational immediacy illustrates the contemporary world in re-
  7705. spect to its potentiality for extensive subdivision into atomic actualities
  7706. and in respect to the scheme of perspective relationships which thereby
  7707. eventuates. But it gives no information as to the actual atomization of
  7708. this contemporary 'real potentiality/ By its limitations it exemplifies the
  7709. doctrine, already stated above, that the contemporary world happens in-
  7710. dependently of the actual occasion with which it is contemporary. This is
  7711. in fact the definition of contemporaneousness (cf. Part II, Ch. II, Sect. I);
  7712. namely, that actual occasions, A and B, are mutually contemporary, when
  7713. A does not contribute to the datum for B, and B does not contribute to
  7714. the datum for A, except that both A and B are atomic regions in the po-
  7715. tential scheme of spatio-temporal extensiveness which is a datum for both
  7716. A and B.
  7717.  
  7718. Hume's polemic respecting causation is, in fact, one prolonged, con-
  7719. vincing argument that pure presentational immediacy does not disclose
  7720. any causal influence, either whereby one actual entity is constitutive of
  7721. the percipient actual entity, or whereby one perceived actual entity is con-
  7722. stitutive of another perceived actual entity. The conclusion is that, in so
  7723. far as concerns their disclosure by presentational immediacy, actual en-
  7724. tities in the contemporary universe are causally independent of each other.
  7725.  
  7726. The two pure modes of perception in this way disclose a variety of loci
  7727. defined by reference to the percipient occasion M. For example, there are
  7728. the actual occasions of the settled world which provide the datum for M;
  7729. these lie in M's causal past. Again, there are the potential occasions for
  7730. which M decides its own potentialities of contribution to their data; these
  7731. lie in M's causal future. There are also those actual occasions which lie
  7732. neither in M's causal past, nor in M's causal future. Such actual occasions
  7733. are called M's 'contemporaries/ These \189] three loci are defined solely
  7734. by reference to the pure mode of causal efficacy.
  7735.  
  7736. We now turn to the pure mode of presentational immediacy. One great
  7737. difference from the previous way+ of obtaining loci at once comes into
  7738. view. In considering the causal mode, the past and the future were de-
  7739.  
  7740.  
  7741.  
  7742. 124 Discussions and Applications
  7743.  
  7744. fined positively, and the contemporaries of M were defined negatively as
  7745. lying neither in M's past nor in JVf s future. In dealing with presentational
  7746. immediacy the opposite way must be taken. For presentational immediacy
  7747. gives positive information only about the immediate present as defined by
  7748. itself. Presentational immediacy illustrates, by means of sensa, potential
  7749. subdivisions within a cross-section of the world, which is in this way ob-
  7750. jectified for M. This cross-section is JVPs immediate present. What is in
  7751. this way illustrated is the potentiality for subdivision into actual atomic
  7752. occasions; we can also recognize potentialities for subdivision of regions
  7753. whose subdivisions remain unillustrated by any contrast of sensa. There
  7754. are well-known limitations to such direct perceptions of unillustrated po-
  7755. tentiality, a perception outrunning the real illustration of division by con-
  7756. trasted sensa. Such limitations constitute the minima sensibilia.
  7757.  
  7758. Hume's polemic respecting causation constitutes a proof that M's 'im-
  7759. mediate present' lies within the locus of M's contemporaries. The presen-
  7760. tation to M of this locus, forming its immediate present, contributes to
  7761. M's datum two facts about the universe: one fact is that there is a 'unison
  7762. of becoming/ constituting a positive relation of all the occasions in this
  7763. community to any one of them. The members of this community share in
  7764. a common immediacy; they are in 'unison' as to their becoming: that is
  7765. to say, any pair of occasions in the locus are contemporaries. The other
  7766. fact is the subjective illustration of the potential extensive subdivision
  7767. with complete vagueness respecting the actual atomization. For example,
  7768. the stone, which in the immediate [190] present is a group of many actual
  7769. occasions, is illustrated as one grey spatial region. But, to go back to the
  7770. former fact, the many actual entities of the present stone and the per-
  7771. cipient are connected together in the 'unison of immediate becoming.'
  7772. This community of concrescent occasions, forming M's immediate present,
  7773. thus establishes a principle of common relatedness, a principle realized as
  7774. an element in M's datum. This is the principle of mutual relatedness in
  7775. the 'unison of becoming/ But this mutual relatedness is independent of
  7776. the illustration by those sensa t through which presentational immediacy
  7777. for M is effected. Also the illustration by these sensa has unequal relevance
  7778. for M, throughout the locus. In its spatially remote parts it becomes vaguer
  7779. and vaguer, fainter and fainter; and yet the principle of 'unison of be-
  7780. coming' still holds, in despite of the fading importance of the sensa. We
  7781. thus find that the locus— namely, M's immediate present— is determined
  7782. by the condition of 'mutual unison' independently of variations of rele-
  7783. vant importance in M's illustrative sensa, and extends to their utmost
  7784. bounds of faintness, and is equally determinate beyond such bounds. We
  7785. thus gain the conception of a locus in which any two atomic actualities
  7786. are in 'concrescent unison,' and which is particularized by the fact that M
  7787. belongs to it, and so do all actual occasions belonging to extensive regions
  7788. which lie in M's immediate present as illustrated by importantly relevant
  7789. sensa. This complete region is the prolongation of M's immediate present
  7790.  
  7791.  
  7792.  
  7793. Organisms and Environment 125
  7794.  
  7795. beyond M's direct perception, the prolongation being effected by the
  7796. principle of 'concrescent unison/
  7797.  
  7798. A complete region, satisfying the principle of 'concrescent unison/ will
  7799. be called a 'duration/ A duration is a cross-section of the universe; it is
  7800. the immediate present condition of the world at some epoch, according to
  7801. the old 'classical' theory of time— a theory never doubted until within the
  7802. last few years. It will have been seen that the philosophy of organism
  7803. accepts and defines this [191] notion. Some measure of acceptance is
  7804. imposed upon metaphysics. If the notion be wholly rejected no appeal to
  7805. universal obviousness of conviction can have any weight; since there can
  7806. be no stronger instance of this force of obviousness.
  7807.  
  7808. The 'classical' theory of time tacitly assumed that a duration included
  7809. the directly perceived immediate present of each one of its members. The
  7810. converse proposition certainly follows from the account given above, that
  7811. the immediate present of each actual occasion lies in a duration. An actual
  7812. occasion will be said 6 to be 'cogredientf with' or 'stationary in' the dura-
  7813. tion including its directly perceived immediate present. The actual occa-
  7814. sion is included in its own immediate present; so that each actual occa-
  7815. sion through its percipience in the pure mode of presentational imme-
  7816. diacy—if such percipience has important relevance— defines one duration
  7817. in which it is included. The percipient occasion is 'stationary' in this
  7818. duration.
  7819.  
  7820. But the classical theory also assumed the converse of this statement. It
  7821. assumed that any actual occasion only lies in one duration; so that if N
  7822. lies in the duration including M's immediate present, then M lies in the
  7823. duration including N's immediate present. The philosophy of organism, in
  7824. agreement with recent physics, rejects this conversion; though it holds that
  7825. such rejection is based on scientific examination of our cosmic epoch, and
  7826. not on any more general metaphysical principle. According to the philoso-
  7827. phy of organism, in the present cosmic epoch only one duration includes
  7828. all M's immediate present; this one duration will be called M's 'presented
  7829. duration.' But M itself lies in many durations; each duration including M
  7830. also includes some portions of M's presented duration. In the case of
  7831. human perception practically all the important portions are thus included;
  7832. also in human experience the relationship to such dura- \192] tions is what
  7833. we express by the notion of 'movement/
  7834.  
  7835. To sum up this discussion. In respect to any one actual occasion M
  7836. there are three distinct nexus of occasions to be considered:
  7837.  
  7838. (i) The nexus of M's contemporaries, defined by the characteristic that
  7839. M and any one of its contemporaries happen in causal independence of
  7840. each other.
  7841.  
  7842. (ii) Durations including M;f any such duration is defined by the char-
  7843. acteristic that any two of its members are contemporaries. (It follows that
  7844.  
  7845. 6 Cf. my Principles of Natural Knowledge, Ch. XI, and my Concept of Nature,
  7846. Ch. V.
  7847.  
  7848.  
  7849.  
  7850. 126 Discussions and Applications
  7851.  
  7852. any member of such a duration is contemporary with M, and thence that
  7853. such durations are all included in the locus (i). The characteristic prop-
  7854. erty of a duration is termed 'unison of becoming/)
  7855.  
  7856. (iii) M's presented locus, which is the contemporary nexus perceived in
  7857. the mode of presentational immediacy, with its regions defined by sensa.
  7858. It is assumed, on the basis of direct intuition, that JVf s presented locus is
  7859. closely related to some one duration including M. It is also assumed, as
  7860. the outcome of modern physical theory, that there is more than one dura-
  7861. tion including M. The single duration which is so related to M's presented
  7862. locus is termed 'JVf s presented duration/ But this connection is criticized
  7863. in the following sections of this chapter. In Part IV, the connection of
  7864. these 'presented' loci to regions defined by straight lines is considered in
  7865. more detail; the notion of 'strain-loci'* is there introduced.
  7866.  
  7867. SECTION IX
  7868.  
  7869. Physical science has recently arrived at the stage in which the practical
  7870. identification, made in the preceding section, between the 'presented
  7871. locus' of an actual entity, and a locus in 'unison of becoming with the
  7872. actual entity must be qualified.
  7873.  
  7874. The two notions, 'presented locus' and 'unison of becoming/ are dis-
  7875. tinct. The identification merely rests on the obvious experience of daily
  7876. life. In any recasting of [193] thought it is obligatory to include the iden-
  7877. tification as a practical approximation to the truth, sufficient for daily life.
  7878. Subject to this limitation, there is no reason for rejecting any distinction
  7879. between them which the evidence suggests.
  7880.  
  7881. In the first place, the presented locus is defined by some systematic
  7882. relation to the human body— so far as we rely, as we must, upon human
  7883. experience. A certain state of geometrical strain in the body, and a certain
  7884. qualitative physiological excitement in the cells of the body, govern the
  7885. whole process of presentational immediacy. In sense-perception the whole
  7886. function of antecedent occurrences outside the body is merely to excite
  7887. these strains and physiological excitements within the body. But any
  7888. other means of production would do just as well, so long as the relevant
  7889. states of the body are in fact produced. The perceptions are functions of
  7890. the bodily states. The geometrical details of the projected sense-perception
  7891. depend on the geometrical strains in the body, the qualitative sensa de-
  7892. pend on the physiological excitements of the requisite cells in the body.
  7893.  
  7894. Thus the presented locus must be a locus with a systematic geometrical
  7895. relation to the body. According to all the evidence, it is completely inde-
  7896. pendent of the contemporary actualities which in fact make up the nexus
  7897. of actualities in the locus. For example, we see a picture on the wall with
  7898. direct vision. But if we turn our back to the wall, and gaze into a good
  7899. mirror, we see the same sight as an image behind the mirror. Thus, given
  7900. the proper physiological state of the body, the locus presented in sense-
  7901.  
  7902.  
  7903.  
  7904. Organisms and Environment 127
  7905.  
  7906. perception is independent of the details of the actual happenings which
  7907. it includes. This is not to sayt that sense-perception is irrelevant to the
  7908. real world. It demonstrates to us the real extensive continuum in terms of **
  7909. which these contemporary happenings have their own experiences quali-
  7910. fied. Its additional information in terms of the qualitative sensa has rele-
  7911. vance in proportion to the relevance of the immediate bodily state to the
  7912. imme- [194] diate happenings throughout the locus. Both are derived
  7913. from a past which is practically common to them all. Thus there is always
  7914. some relevance; the correct interpretation of this relevance is the art of
  7915. utilizing the perceptive mode of presentational immediacy as a means for
  7916. understanding the world as a medium.
  7917.  
  7918. But the question which is of interest for this discussion is how this
  7919. systematic relevance, of body to presented locus, is definable. This is not a
  7920. mere logical question. The problem is to point out that element in the
  7921. nature of things constituting such a geometrical relevance of the bodv to
  7922. the presented locus. If there be such an element, we can understand that a
  7923. certain state of the body may lift it into an important factor of our
  7924. experience.
  7925.  
  7926. The only possible elements capable of this extended systematic relevance
  7927. beyond the body are straight lines and planes. Planes are definable in
  7928. terms of straight lines, so that we can concentrate attention upon straight
  7929. lines.
  7930.  
  7931. It is a dogma of science that straight lines are not definable in terms of
  7932. mere notions of extension. Thus, in the expositions of recent physical
  7933. theory, straight lines are defined in terms of the actual physical happenings.
  7934. The disadvantage of this doctrine is that there is no method of charac-
  7935. terizing the possibilities of physical events antecedently to their actual
  7936. occurrence. It is easy to verify that in fact there is a tacit relevance to an
  7937. underlying system, by reference to which the physical loci— including those
  7938. called 'straight lines'— are defined. The question is how to define this un-
  7939. derlying system in terms of 'pure' straight lines, determinable without ref-
  7940. erence to the casual** details of the happenings.
  7941.  
  7942. It will be shown later (cf. Part IV, Chs. Ill and IV) that this dogma of
  7943. the indefinability of straight lines is mistaken. Thus the systematic relation
  7944. of the body to the presented locus occasions no theoretical difficulty.
  7945.  
  7946. All measurement is effected by observations of sensa [195] with geo-
  7947. metrical relations within this presented locus. Also all scientific observa-
  7948. tion of the unchanged character of things ultimately depends! upon the
  7949. maintenance of directly observed geometrical analogies within such loci.
  7950.  
  7951. However far the testing of instruments is carried, finally all scientific
  7952. interpretation is based upon the assumption of directly observed unchange-
  7953. ably of some instrument for seconds, for hours, for months, for years.
  7954. When we test this assumption we can only use another instrument; and
  7955. there! cannot be an infinite regress of instruments.
  7956.  
  7957. Thus ultimately all science depends upon direct observation of homol-
  7958.  
  7959.  
  7960.  
  7961. 128 Discussions and Applications
  7962.  
  7963. ogy of status within a system. Also the observed system is the complex of
  7964. geometrical relations within some presented locus.
  7965.  
  7966. In the second place, a locus of entities in 'unison of becoming' ob-
  7967. viously depends on the particular actual entities. The question, as to how
  7968. the extensive continuum is in fact atomized by the atomic actualities, is
  7969. relevant to the determination of the locus. The factor of temporal en-
  7970. durance selected for any one actuality will depend upon its initial 'sub-
  7971. jective aim/ The categoreal conditions which govern the 'subjective aim'
  7972. are discussed later in Part III. They consist generally in satisfying some
  7973. condition of a maximum, to be obtained by the transmission of inherited
  7974. types of order. This is the foundation of the 'stationary' conditions in
  7975. terms of which the ultimate formulations of physical science can be
  7976. mathematically expressed.
  7977.  
  7978. Thus the loci of 'unison of becoming' are only determinable in terms of
  7979. the actual happenings of the world. But the conditions which they satisfy
  7980. are expressed in terms of measurements derived from the qualification of
  7981. actualities by the systematic character of the extensive continuum.
  7982.  
  7983. The term 'duration' will be used for a locus of 'unison of becoming/
  7984. and the terms 'presented locus' and 'strain- [196] locus' for the systematic
  7985. locus involved in presentational immediacy. 7
  7986.  
  7987. The strain-loci provide the systematic geometry with its homology of
  7988. relations throughout all its regions; the durations share in the deficiency of
  7989. homology characteristic of the physical field which arises from the pe-
  7990. culiarities of the actual events.
  7991.  
  7992. SECTION X
  7993.  
  7994. We can now sum up this discussion of organisms, order, societies,! nexus.
  7995.  
  7996. The aim of the philosophy of organism is to express a coherent cos-
  7997. mology based upon the notions of 'system,' 'process/ 'creative advance into
  7998. novelty,' 'res vera! (in Descartes' sense), 'stubborn fact/ 'individual unity of
  7999. experience,' 'feeling/ 'time as perpetual perishing/ 'endurance as re-crea-
  8000. tion/ 'purpose,' 'universals as forms of defmiteness/ 'particulars— i.e., res
  8001. verae—as ultimate agents of stubborn fact.'
  8002.  
  8003. Every one of these notions is explicitly formulated either by Descartes
  8004. or by Locke. Also no one can be dropped without doing violence to com-
  8005. mon sense. But neither Descartes nor Locke weaves these notions into one
  8006. coherent system of cosmology. In so far as either philosopher is systematic,
  8007. he relies on alternative notions which in the end lead to Hume's extreme
  8008. of sensationalism.
  8009.  
  8010. In the philosophy of organism it is held that the notion of 'organism'
  8011. has two meanings, interconnected but intellectually separable, namely,
  8012. the microscopic meaning and the macroscopic meaning.** The microscopic
  8013.  
  8014. 7 In The Concept of Nature these two loci were not discriminated, namely,
  8015. durations and strain-loci.
  8016.  
  8017.  
  8018.  
  8019. Organisms and Environment 129
  8020.  
  8021. meaning is concerned with the formal constitution of an actual occasion,
  8022. considered as a process of realizing an individual unity of experience. The
  8023. macroscopic meaning is concerned with the givenness of the actual world,
  8024. considered as the stubborn fact which at once limits and provides [197]
  8025. opportunity for the actual occasion. The canalization of the creative urge,
  8026. exemplified in its massive reproduction of social nexus, is for common
  8027. sense the final illustration of the power of stubborn fact. Also in our ex-
  8028. perience, we essentially arise out of our bodies which are the stubborn
  8029. facts of the immediate relevant past. We are also carried on by our im-
  8030. mediate past of personal experience; we finish a sentence because we have
  8031. begun it. The sentence may embody a new thought, never phrased before,
  8032. or an old one rephrased with verbal novelty. There need be no well-worn
  8033. association between the sounds of the earlier and the later words. But it
  8034. remains remorselessly true, that we finish a sentence because we have be-
  8035. gun it. We are governed by stubborn fact.
  8036.  
  8037. It is in respect to this 'stubborn fact' that the theories of modern philos-
  8038. ophy are weakest. Philosophers have worried themselves about remote
  8039. consequences, and the inductive formulations of science. They should con-
  8040. fine attention to the rush of immediate transition. Their explanations
  8041. would then be seen in their native absurdity.
  8042.  
  8043.  
  8044.  
  8045. CHAPTER V
  8046. LOCKE AND HUME
  8047.  
  8048. SECTION I
  8049.  
  8050. [198] A more detailed discussion of Descartes, Locke, and Hume— in
  8051. this and in the succeeding chapter— may make plain how deeply the philos-
  8052. ophy of organism is founded on seventeenth-century thought and how at
  8053. certain critical points it diverges from that thought
  8054.  
  8055. We shall understand better the discussion, if we start with some analysis
  8056. of the presuppositions upon which Hume's philosophy rests. These pre-
  8057. suppositions were not original to Hume, nor have they ceased with him.
  8058. They were largely accepted by Kant and are widely prevalent in modern
  8059. philosophy. The philosophy of organism can be best understood by con-
  8060. ceiving it as accepting large portions of the expositions of Hume and Kant,
  8061. with the exception of these presuppositions, and of inferences directly
  8062. derived from them. Hume is a writer of unrivalled clearness; and, as far as
  8063. possible ? it will be well to allow him to express his ideas in his own words.
  8064. He writes:
  8065.  
  8066. We may observe, that it is universally allowed by philosophers,
  8067. and is besides pretty obvious of itself, that nothing is ever really pres-
  8068. ent with the mind but its perceptions or impressions and ideas, and
  8069. that external objects become known to us only by those perceptions
  8070. they occasion. To hate, to love, to think, to feel, to see; all this is
  8071. nothing but to perceive. 1
  8072. Again:
  8073.  
  8074. All the perceptions of the human mind resolve themselves into
  8075. two distinct kinds, which I shall call impressions and ideas. The
  8076. difference betwixt these consists in [199] the degrees of force and live-
  8077. liness, with which they strike upon the mind, and make their way into
  8078. our thought or consciousness. Those perceptions which enter with
  8079. most force and violence, we may name impressions; and, under this
  8080. name, I comprehend all our sensations, passions, and emotions, as
  8081. they make their first appearance in the soul. By ideas, I mean the
  8082. faint images of these in thinking and reasoning; such as, for instance,
  8083. are all the perceptions excited by the present discourse, excepting only
  8084. those which arise from the sight and touch, and excepting the imme-
  8085. diate pleasure or uneasiness it may occasion, 2
  8086.  
  8087. 1 Treatise, Bk. I, Part II, Sect. VI.
  8088.  
  8089. 2 Treatise, Bk. I, Part I, Sect. I.
  8090.  
  8091.  
  8092.  
  8093. Locke and Hume 131
  8094.  
  8095. The exceptions made in the above quotation are, of course, due to the
  8096. fact that the 'perceptions' arising in these excepted ways are 'impressions'
  8097. and not 'ideas/ Hume immediately draws attention to the fact that he
  8098. deserts Locke's wide use of the term 'idea/ and restores it to its more usual
  8099. and narrow meaning. He divides both ideas and impressions into 'simple'
  8100. and 'complex/ He then adds:
  8101.  
  8102. ... we shall here content ourselves with establishing one general
  8103. proposition, That all our simple ideas in their first appearance, are
  8104. derived from simple impressions, which are correspondent to them,
  8105. and which they exactly represent?
  8106.  
  8107. When Hume passes on to complex impressions and ideas, his admirable
  8108. clearness partially deserts him. He fails to distinguish sufficiently between
  8109. (i) the ' ( manner' (or 'order') in which many simples constitute some one
  8110. complex perception, i.e., impression or idea; and (ii) the efficacious fact by
  8111. reason of which this complex perception arises; and (iii) the mere multi-
  8112. plicity of simples which constitute the complex perception in this definite
  8113. manner. In this respect Hume's followers only differ from Hume by dis-
  8114. carding some of that clarity which never wholly deserts him. Each one of
  8115. these three notions is an essential element in his argument. He writes:
  8116. [200] ... we may conclude with certainty, that the idea of extension is
  8117. nothing but a copy of these coloured f points, and of the manner of
  8118. their appearance. 4
  8119. Also he writes:
  8120.  
  8121. Were ideas entirely loose and unconnected, chancef alone would
  8122. join them; and it is impossible the same simple ideas should! fall
  8123. regularly into complex ones (as they commonly do), without some
  8124. bond of union among them, some associating quality, by which one
  8125. idea naturally introduces another. This uniting principle among ideas
  8126. is not to be considered as an inseparable connection; for that has been
  8127. already 5 excluded from the imagination: nor yet are we to conclude,
  8128. that without it the mind cannot join two ideas; for nothing is more
  8129. free than that faculty: but we are only to regard it as a gentle force,
  8130. which commonly prevails, and is the cause why, among other things,
  8131. languages so nearly correspond to each other; Nature, in a manner,
  8132. pointing out to every one those simple ideas, which are most proper
  8133. to be united into a complex one. 6
  8134. As a final quotation, to illustrate Hume's employment of the third no-
  8135. tion, we have:
  8136. The idea of a substance as well as that of a mode, is nothing but a col-
  8137. lection of simple ideas, that are united by the imagination, and have a
  8138. particular name assigned them, . . . But the difference betwixt these
  8139.  
  8140. 3 Treatise, Bk. I, Part I, Sect. I.
  8141.  
  8142. 4 Treatise, Bk. I, Part II, Sect. III.
  8143.  
  8144. 5 Cf. Hume's previous section.
  8145.  
  8146. 6 Treatise, Bk. I, Part I, Sect. IV.
  8147.  
  8148.  
  8149.  
  8150. 132 Discussions and Applications
  8151.  
  8152. ideas consists in this, that the particular qualities, which form at sub-
  8153. stance, are commonly referred to an unknown something [italics
  8154. Hume's], in which they are supposed to inhere; or granting this fiction
  8155. should not take place, are at least supposed to be closely and in-
  8156. separably connected by the relations of contiguity and causation.
  8157. The effect of this is, that whatever new simple quality we discover to
  8158. have the same connection with the rest, we immediately comprehend
  8159. it among them, even though it did not enter into the first conception
  8160. of the substance. . . . The principle of union being regarded as the
  8161. chief part of the complex [201] idea, gives entrance to whatever qual-
  8162. ity afterwards occurs, and is equally comprehended by it, as are the
  8163. others, which first presented themselves. . . . 7
  8164.  
  8165. In this last quotation, the phrase 'principle of union' is ambiguous as
  8166. between 'manner' and 'efficacious' reason. In either sense, it is inconsistent
  8167. with the phrase 'nothing but a collection,' which at the beginning of \fhe
  8168. quotation settles so simply the notion of 'substance.'
  8169.  
  8170. Returning to the first of this sequence of three quotations, we note that
  8171. any particular 'manner' of composition must itself be a simple idea, or im-
  8172. pression. For otherwise we require yet another 'manner' of composition
  8173. for the original manner, and so on indefinitely. Thus there is either a
  8174. vicious infinity or a final simple idea. But Hume admits that there are
  8175. novel compound ideas which are not copies of compound impressions.
  8176. Thus he should also admit that there is a novel simple idea conveying the
  8177. novel 'manner,' which is not a copy of an impression. He has also himself
  8178. drawn attention to another exception in respect to missing shades of
  8179. colour in a graduated colour scheme. This exception cannot be restricted
  8180. to colour, and must be extended to sound, and smell, and to all gradua-
  8181. tions of sensations. Thus Hume's proposition, that simple ideas are all
  8182. copies of simple impressions, is subject to such considerable qualifications
  8183. that it cannot be taken for an ultimate philosophical principle, at least
  8184. not when enunciated in Hume's unguarded fashion. Hume himself, in
  8185. the passage (Part I, Sect. IV) quoted above for its relevance to his doc-
  8186. trine of the association of ideas, says, ". . . for nothing is more free than
  8187. that faculty [i.e., the imagination]." But he limits its freedom to the
  8188. production of novel complex ideas, disregarding the exceptional case of
  8189. missing shades. This question of imaginative freedom is obviously treated
  8190. very superficially by Hume. Imagination is never very free: it does not
  8191. seem to be limited to complex ideas, as asserted by [202] him; but such
  8192. freedom as it has in fact seems to establish the principle of the possibility
  8193. of diverse actual entities with diverse grades of imaginative freedom,
  8194. some more, some less, than the instances in question.
  8195.  
  8196. In this discussion of Hume's doctrine of imaginative freedom, two
  8197. other points have been left aside. One such point is the difference be-
  8198.  
  8199. 7 Treatise, Bk. I, Part I, Sect. VI. Italics not in edition quoted, except where
  8200. noted.*
  8201.  
  8202.  
  8203.  
  8204. Locke and Hume 133
  8205.  
  8206. tween various grades of generic abstraction, for example, scarlet, red ?
  8207. colour, sense-datum, manner of connectedness of diverse sense-data. The
  8208. other point is the contrast between 'simplicity' and 'complexity/ We may
  8209. doubt whether 'simplicity' is ever more than a relative term, having regard
  8210. to some definite procedure of analysis. I hold this to be the case; and by
  8211. reason of this opinion find yet another reason for discarding Hume's
  8212. doctrine which would debar imagination from the free conceptual pro-
  8213. duction of any type of eternal objects, such as Hume calls 'simple/ But
  8214. there is no such fact as absolute freedom; every actual entity possesses
  8215. only such freedom t as is inherent in the primary phase 'given' by its stand-
  8216. point of relativity to its actual universe. Freedom, givenness, potentiality,
  8217. are notions which presuppose each other and limit each other.
  8218.  
  8219. SECTION II
  8220.  
  8221. Hume, at the end of this passage on the connectedness of ideas, places
  8222. the sentence "... Nature, in a manner, pointing out to every one those
  8223. simple ideas, which are most proper to be united into a complex one." *
  8224. Hume's philosophy is occupied with the double search, first, for manners
  8225. of unity, whereby many simples become one complex impression; and
  8226. secondly, for a standard of propriety by which to criticize the production
  8227. of ideas.
  8228.  
  8229. Hume can find only one standard of propriety, and that is, repetition.
  8230. Repetition is capable of more or less: the more often impressions are
  8231. repeated, the more proper it is that ideas should copy them. Fortunately,
  8232. and without any reason so far as Hume can discover, complex [203] im-
  8233. pressions, often repeated, are also often copied by their corresponding
  8234. complex ideas.
  8235.  
  8236. Also the frequency of ideas following upon the frequency of their cor-
  8237. relate impressions is also attended by an expectation of the repetition of
  8238. the impression. Hume also believes, without any reason he can assign, that
  8239. this expectation is pragmatically justified. It is this pragmatic justification,
  8240. without metaphysical reason, which constitutes the propriety attaching to
  8241. 'repetition/ This is the analysis of the course of thought involved in Hume's
  8242. doctrine of the association of ideas in its relation to causation, and in
  8243. Hume's final appeal to practice.
  8244.  
  8245. It is a great mistake to attribute to Hume any disbelief in the importance
  8246. of the notion of 'cause and effect/ Throughout the Treatise he steadily
  8247. affirms its fundamental importance; and finally, when he cannot fit it into
  8248. his metaphysics, he appeals beyond his metaphysics to an ultimate justifi-
  8249. cation outside any rational systematization. This ultimate justification is
  8250. 'practice/
  8251.  
  8252. Hume writes:
  8253.  
  8254. As our senses show us in one instance two bodies, or motions, or
  8255.  
  8256. qualities, in certain relations of succession and contiguity, so our
  8257.  
  8258. memory presents us only with a multitude of instances wherein we
  8259.  
  8260.  
  8261.  
  8262. 134 Discussions and Applications
  8263.  
  8264. always find like bodies, motions, or qualities, in like relations. From
  8265. the mere repetition of any past impression, even to infinity, there
  8266. never will arise any new original idea, such as that of a necessary
  8267. connection; and the number of impressions has in this case no more
  8268. effect than if we confined ourselves to one only. But though this rea-
  8269. soning seems just and obvious, yet, as it would be folly to despair too
  8270. soon, we shall continue the thread of our discourse; and having found,
  8271. that after the discovery of the constant conjunction of any objects, we
  8272. always draw an inference from one object to another, we shall now
  8273. examine the nature of that inference, and of the transition from the
  8274. impression to the idea. Perhaps it will appear in the end, that the
  8275. necessary connection depends on the inference, instead of the in-
  8276. ference's depending on [204} the necessary connection. . . . The only
  8277. connection or relation of objects, which can lead us beyond the im-
  8278. mediate impressions of our memory and senses, is that of cause and
  8279. effect; and that because it is the only one, on which we can found a
  8280. just inference from one object to another. The idea of cause and
  8281. effect is derived from experience [italics Hume's], which informs us,
  8282. that such particular objects, in all past instances, have been con-
  8283. stantly conjoined with each other: and as an object similar to one of
  8284. these is supposed to be immediately present in its impression, we
  8285. thence presume on the existence of one similar to its usual attendant.
  8286. According to this account of things, which is, I think, in every point
  8287. unquestionable, probability is founded on the presumption of a re-
  8288. semblance betwixt those objects of which we have had experience,
  8289. and those of which we have had none; and, therefore, it is impossible
  8290. t this presumption can arise from probability*
  8291.  
  8292. Hume's difficulty with 'cause and effect' is that it lies "beyond the im-
  8293. mediate impressions of our memory and senses."! In other words, this man-
  8294. ner of connection is not given in any impression. Thus the whole basis of
  8295. the idea, its propriety, is to be traced to the repetition of impressions. At
  8296. this point of his argument, Hume seems to have overlooked the difficulty
  8297. that 'repetition' stands with regard to 'impressions' in exactly the same
  8298. position as does 'cause and effect.' Hume has confused a 'repetition of
  8299. impressions' with an 'impression of repetitions of impressions/ In Hume's
  8300. own words on another topic (Part II, Sect. V) :
  8301. For whence should it be derived? Does it arise from an impression of
  8302. sensation or of reflection? Point it out distinctly to us, that we may
  8303. know its nature and qualities. But if you cannot point out any such
  8304. impression [Hume's italics], you may be certain you are mistaken,
  8305. when you imagine you have any such idea*
  8306.  
  8307. Hume's answer to this criticism would, of course, be [205} that he ad-
  8308. mits 'memory.' But the question is what is consistent with Hume's own
  8309.  
  8310. 8 Treatise, Bk. I, Part III, Sect. VI. Italics not in Treatise.
  8311.  
  8312.  
  8313.  
  8314. Locke and Hume 135
  8315.  
  8316. doctrine. This is Hume's doctrine of memory (Part III, Sect. V): "Since
  8317. therefore the memory is known, neither by the order of its complex ideas,
  8318. nor f the nature of its simple ones; it follows, that the difference be-
  8319. twixt it and the imagination lies in its superior force and vivacity." But (in
  8320. Part I, Sect. I) he writes: "By ideas I mean the faint images of these [i.e.,
  8321. impressions] in thinking and reasoning/' and later on he expands 'faint'
  8322. into "degree of force and vivacity." 9 Thus, purely differing in 'force and
  8323. vivacity/ we have the order: impressions, memories, ideas.
  8324.  
  8325. This doctrine is very implausible; and, to speak bluntly, is in contradic-
  8326. tion to plain fact. But, even worse, it omits the vital character of memory,
  8327. namely, that it is memory. In fact the whole notion of repetition is lost in
  8328. the 'force and vivacity doctrine. What Hume does explain is that with a
  8329. number of different perceptions immediately concurrent, he sorts them
  8330. out into three different classes according to force and vivacity. But the
  8331. repetition character, which he ascribes to simple ideas, and which is the
  8332. whole point of memory, finds no place in his explanation. Nor can it do
  8333. so, without an entire recasting of his fundamental philosophic notions.
  8334.  
  8335. SECTION III
  8336.  
  8337. Hume's argument has become circular. In the beginning of his Treatise,
  8338. he lays down the 'general proposition': "That all our simple ideas in their
  8339. first appearance, are derived from simple impressions, . . ." He proves this
  8340. by an empirical survey. But the proposition itself employs— covertly, so far
  8341. as language is concerned— the notion of 'repetition/ which itself is not an
  8342. 'impression/ Again, later he finds 'necessary connection': he discards \206]
  8343. this because he can find no corresponding impression. But the original
  8344. proposition was only founded on an empirical survey; so the argument for
  8345. dismissal is purely circular. Further, if Hume had only attended to his
  8346. own excellent Part II, Section VI, "Of the Idea of Existence, and of external
  8347. Existence,"! he would have remembered that whatever we do think of,
  8348. thereby in some sense 'exists.' Thus, having the idea of 'necessary con-
  8349. nection/ the only question is as to its exemplification in the connectedness
  8350. of our 'impressions.' He muddies the importance of an idea with the fact
  8351. of our entertainment of the idea. We cannot even be wrong in thinking
  8352. that we think of 'necessary connection/ unless we are thinking of 'neces-
  8353. sary connection.' Of course, we may be very wrong in believing that the
  8354. notion is important.
  8355.  
  8356. The reasons for this examination of Hume, including the prolonged
  8357. quotations, are (i) that Hume states with great clearness important as-
  8358. pects of our experience; (ii) that the defects in his statements are emi-
  8359.  
  8360. 9 This doctrine of 'force and vivacity' is withdrawn in the last sentence* of
  8361. Hume's Appendix to the Treatise. But the argument in the Treatise is substan-
  8362. tially built upon it. In the light of the retraction the whole 'sensationalist' doc-
  8363. trine requires reconsideration. The withdrawal cannot be treated as a minor
  8364. adjustment.
  8365.  
  8366.  
  8367.  
  8368. 1 36 Discussions and Applications
  8369.  
  8370. nently natural defects which emerge with great clearness, owing to the
  8371. excellence of his presentation; and (iii) that Hume differs from the great
  8372. majority of his followers chiefly by the way in which he faces up to the
  8373. problems raised by his own philosophy.
  8374.  
  8375. The first point to notice is that Hume's philosophy is pervaded by the
  8376. notion of 'repetition/ and that memory is a particular example of this
  8377. character of experience, that in some sense there is entwined in its funda-
  8378. mental nature the fact that it is repeating something. Tear 'repetition' out
  8379. of 'experience/ and there is nothing left. On the other hand, 'immediacy/
  8380. or 'first-handedness/ is another element in experience. Feeling overwhelms
  8381. repetition; and there remains the immediate, first-handed fact, which is the
  8382. actual world in an immediate complex unity of feeling.
  8383.  
  8384. There is another contrasted pair of elements in experience, clustering
  8385. round the notion of time, namely, 'endurance' and 'change/ Descartes,
  8386. who emphasizes the notion [207] of 'substance/ also emphasizes 'change/
  8387. Hume, who minimizes the notion of 'substance/ similarly emphasizes
  8388. 'change/ He writes:
  8389. Now as time is composed of parts that are not coexistent, an un-
  8390. changeable object, since it produces none but coexistent impressions,
  8391. produces none that can give us the idea of time: and, consequently,
  8392. that idea must be derived from a succession of changeable objects,
  8393. and time in its first appearance can never be severed from such a
  8394. succession. 10
  8395. Whereas Descartes writes:
  8396.  
  8397. ... for this [i.e., 'the nature of time or of the duration of things'] is
  8398. of such a kind that its parts do not depend one upon the other, and
  8399. never co-exist; and from the fact that we now are, it does not follow
  8400. that we shall be a moment afterwards, if some cause— the same that
  8401. first produced us— does not continue so to produce us; that is to say,
  8402. to conserve us.
  8403. And again:
  8404.  
  8405. We shall likewise have a very different understanding of duration,
  8406. order and number, if, in place of mingling with the idea that we
  8407. have of them what properly speaking pertains to the conception of sub-
  8408. stance, we merely consider that the duration of each thing is a mode
  8409. under which we shall consider this thing in so far as it continues to
  8410. exist; . . , 11
  8411.  
  8412. We have certainly to make room in our philosophy for the two con-
  8413. trasted notions, one that every actual entity endures, and the other that
  8414. every morning is a new fact with its measure of change.
  8415.  
  8416. These various aspects can be summed up in the statement that ex-
  8417. perience involves a becoming, that becoming means that something be-
  8418.  
  8419. 10 Treatise, Bk. I, Part II, Sect. III.
  8420.  
  8421. 11 Principles, Part I, 21, and 55.
  8422.  
  8423.  
  8424.  
  8425. Locke and Hume 1 37
  8426.  
  8427. comes, and that what becomes involves repetition transformed into novel
  8428. immediacy.
  8429.  
  8430. This statement directly traverses one main presupposition which Des-
  8431. cartes and Hume agree in stating explicitly. This presupposition is that of
  8432. the individual independence of successive temporal occasions. For [208]
  8433. example, Descartes, in the passage cited above, writes: "[The nature of
  8434. time is such]t that its parts do not depend one upon the other, . . ." Also
  8435. Hume's impressions are self-contained, and he can find no temporal re-
  8436. lationship other than mere serial order. This statement about Hume re-
  8437. quires qualifying so far as concerns the connection between 'impressions'
  8438. and 'ideas/ There is a relation of 'derivation' of 'ideas' from 'impressions'
  8439. which he is always citing and never discussing. So far as it is to be taken
  8440. seriously — for he never refers it to a correlate 'impression'— it constitutes
  8441. an exception to the individual independence of successive 'perceptions.'
  8442. This presupposition of individual independence is what I have elsewhere 12
  8443. called, the 'fallacy of simple location.' The notion of 'simple location' is
  8444. inconsistent with any admission of 'repetition'; Hume's difficulties arise
  8445. from the fact that he starts with simple locations and ends with repetition.
  8446. In the organic philosophy the notion of repetition is fundamental. The
  8447. doctrine of objectification is an endeavourf to express how what is settled
  8448. in actuality is repeated under limitations, so as to be 'given' for immediacy.
  8449. Later, in discussing 'time,' this doctrine will be termed the doctrine of
  8450. 'objective immortality.'
  8451.  
  8452. SECTION IV
  8453.  
  8454. The doctrine of the individual independence of real facts is derived
  8455. from the notion that the subject-predicate form of statement conveys a
  8456. truth which is metaphysically ultimate. According to this view, an indi-
  8457. vidual substance with its predicates constitutes the ultimate type of ac-
  8458. tuality. If there be one individual, the philosophy is monistic; if there be
  8459. many individuals, the philosophy is pluralistic. With this metaphysical
  8460. presupposition, the relations between individual substances constitute
  8461. metaphysical nuisances: there is no place for them. Accordingly— in de-
  8462. fiance of the most obvious deliverance of our intuitive 'prejudices'— every
  8463. [209] respectable philosophy of the subject-predicate type is monistic.
  8464.  
  8465. The exclusive dominance of the substance-quality metaphysics was enor-
  8466. mouslv promoted by the logical bias of the mediaeval period. It was re-
  8467. tarded by the study of Plato and of Aristotle. These authors included the
  8468. strains of thought which issued in this doctrine, but included them in-
  8469. consistently mingled with other notions. The substance-quality meta-
  8470. physics triumphed with exclusive dominance in Descartes' doctrines. Un-
  8471. fortunately he did not realize that his notion of the 'res vera' did not en-
  8472. tail the same disjunction of ultimate facts as that entailed by the Aris-
  8473.  
  8474. 12 Cf. Science and the Modem World, Ch. III.
  8475.  
  8476.  
  8477.  
  8478. 1 38 Discussions and Applications
  8479.  
  8480. totelian notion of 'primary substance/ Locke led a revolt from this dom-
  8481. inance, but inconsistently. For him and also for Hume, in the background
  8482. and tacitly presupposed in all explanations, there remained the mind with
  8483. its perceptions. The perceptions, for Hume, are what the mind knows
  8484. about itself; and tacitly the knowable facts are always treated as qualities
  8485. of a subject— the subject being the mind. His final criticism of the notion
  8486. of the 'mind' does not alter the plain fact that the whole of the previous
  8487. discussion has included this presupposition. Hume's final criticism only
  8488. exposes the metaphysical superficiality of his preceding exposition.
  8489.  
  8490. In the philosophy of organism a subject-predicate proposition is con-
  8491. sidered as expressing a high abstraction.
  8492.  
  8493. The metaphysical superiority of Locke over Hume is exhibited in his
  8494. wide use of the term 'idea/ which Locke himself introduced and Hume
  8495. abandoned. Its use marks the fact that his tacit subject-predicate bias is
  8496. slight in its warping effect. He first (I, I, 8*) explains: "... I have used
  8497. it [i.e., idea] to express whatever is meant by phantasm, notion, species, or
  8498. whatever it is which the mind can be employed about in thinking; . . ."
  8499. But later (III, III, 6t), without any explicit notice of the widening of
  8500. use, he writes: ". . . and ideas become 13 \210] general by separating from
  8501. them the circumstances of time, and place, and any other ideas that may
  8502. determine them to this or that particular existence" Here, for Locke, the
  8503. operations of the mind originate from ideas 'determined' to particular
  8504. existents. This is a fundamental principle with Locke; it is a casual con-
  8505. cession to the habits of language with Hume; and it is a fundamental
  8506. principle with the philosophy of organism. In an earlier section (II, XXIII,
  8507. 1) Locke expresses more vaguely the same doctrine, though in this con-
  8508. text he immediately waters it down into an unexplained notion of 'going
  8509. constantly together': "The mind, being, . . . furnished with a great number
  8510. of the simple ideas conveyed in by the senses, as they are found in ex-
  8511. terior things, . . . takes notice, also, that a certain number of these simple
  8512. ideas go constantly together"
  8513.  
  8514. But Locke wavers in his use of this principle of some sort of perception
  8515. of 'particular existents'; and Hume seeks consistency by abandoning it;
  8516. while the philosophy of organism seeks to reconstruct Locke by abandon-
  8517. ing those parts of his philosophy which are inconsistent with this prin-
  8518. ciple. But the principle itself is to be found plainly stated by Locke.
  8519.  
  8520. Hume has only impressions of 'sensation' and of 'reflection/ He writes:
  8521. "The first kind arises in the soul originally, from unknown causes." 14
  8522. Note the tacit presupposition of 'the soul' as subject, and 'impression of
  8523. sensation' as predicate. Also note the dismissal of any intrinsic relevance to
  8524. a particular existent, which is an existent in the same sense as the 'soul' is
  8525. an existent; whereas Locke illustrates his meaning by referring (cf. Ill,
  8526.  
  8527. 13 Italics mine.*
  8528.  
  8529. 14 Treatise, Bk. I, Part I, Sect. II.
  8530.  
  8531.  
  8532.  
  8533. Locke and Hume 139
  8534.  
  8535. HI, 7) to a 'child —corresponding to 'the soul 7 in Hume's phrase— and to
  8536. its 'nurse' of whom the child has its 'idea/
  8537.  
  8538. Hume is certainly inconsistent, because he cannot entirely disregard
  8539. common sense. But his inconsistencies are violent, and his main argument
  8540. negates Locke's use. [21 J] As an example of his glaring inconsistency of
  8541. phraseology, note:
  8542. As to those impressions, which arise from the senses, their ultimate
  8543. cause is, in my opinion, perfectly inexplicable by human reason, and
  8544. it will always be impossible to decide with certainty, whether they
  8545. arrive immediately from the object, or are produced by the creative
  8546. power of the mind, or are derived from the Author of our being. 15
  8547. Here he inconsistently speaks of the object, whereas he has nothing on
  8548. hand in his philosophy which justifies the demonstrative word 'the! In
  8549. the second reference 'the object' has emerged into daylight. He writes:
  8550. "There is no object which implies the existence of any other, if we con-
  8551. sider these objects in themselves, and never look beyond the ideas which
  8552. we form of them." This quotation exhibits an ingenious confusion whereby
  8553. Hume makes the best of two metaphysical worlds, the world with Locke's
  8554. principle, and his own world which is without Locke's principle.
  8555.  
  8556. But Locke's principle amounts to this: That there are many actual
  8557. existents, and that in some sense one actual existent repeats itself in
  8558. another actual existent, so that in the analysis of the latter existent a
  8559. component 'determined to' the former existent is discoverable. The phi-
  8560. losophy of organism expresses this principle by its doctrines of 'prehen-
  8561. sion' and of 'objectification.' Locke always supposes that consciousness is
  8562. consciousness of the ideas in the conscious mind. But he never separates
  8563. the 'ideas' from the 'consciousness.' The philosophy of organism makes
  8564. this separation, and thereby relegates consciousness to a subordinate meta-
  8565. physical position; and gives to Locke's Essay a metaphysical interpretation
  8566. which was not in Locke's mind. This separation asserts Kant's principle:
  8567. "Gedanken ohne Inhalt sind leer, Anschauungen ohne Begriffe sind
  8568. blind." 16 But Kant's principle is here applied in exactly the converse way
  8569. to Kant's own use of it. Kant is obsessed with the mentality [212] of 'in-
  8570. tuition,' and hence f with its necessary involution in consciousness. His*
  8571. suppressed premise is 'Intuitions are never blind.'
  8572.  
  8573. SECTION V
  8574.  
  8575. In one important respect Hume's philosophical conceptions show a
  8576. marked superiority over those of Locke. In the Essay Concerning Human
  8577. Understanding, the emphasis is laid upon the morphological structure of
  8578. 'human understanding.' The logical relationships of various sorts of 'ideas'
  8579. are examined. Now, whether in physics, biology, or elsewhere, morphology,
  8580.  
  8581. is Treatise, Bk. I, Part III, Sect. V; cf. also Sect. VI. f
  8582.  
  8583. 16 Critique of Pure Reason, Transcendental Logic,' Introduction, Sect. I.t
  8584.  
  8585.  
  8586.  
  8587. 140 Discussions and Applications
  8588.  
  8589. in the sense of the analysis of logical relationships, constitutes the first
  8590. stage of knowledge. It is the basis of the new 'mathematical' method
  8591. which Descartes introduced. Morphology deals in analytical propositions,
  8592. as they are termed by Kant. For example, Locke writes: "The common
  8593. names of substances, as well as other general terms, stand for sorts:
  8594. which 1? is nothing else but the being made signs of such complex ideas,
  8595. wherein several particular substances do or might agree, by virtue of which
  8596. they are capable of being comprehended in one common conception, and
  8597. be signified by one name." And again: "Our abstract ideas are to us the
  8598. measures of species." And again: "Nor let any one say, that the power of
  8599. propagation in animals by the mixture of male and female, and in plants
  8600. by seeds, keeps the supposed real species distinct and entire/ 7 18 In tech-
  8601. nical language, Locke had no use for genetic evolution.
  8602.  
  8603. On the other hand, Hume's train of thought unwittingly emphasizes
  8604. 'process/ His very scepticism is nothing but the discovery that there is
  8605. something in the world which cannot be expressed in analytic proposi-
  8606. tions. Hume discovered that "We murder to dissect/' He did not say
  8607. this, because he belonged to the mid-eighteenth century; and so left the
  8608. remark to Wordsworth. But, in [213] effect, Hume discovered that an ac-
  8609. tual entity is at once a process, and is atomic; so that in no sense is it the
  8610. sum of its parts. Hume proclaimed the bankruptcy of morphology.
  8611.  
  8612. Hume's account of the process discoverable in 'the soul' is as follows:
  8613. first, impressions of sensation, of unknown origin; then, ideas of such im-
  8614. pressions, 'derived from' the impressions; then, impressions of reflection
  8615. 'derived from' the antecedent ideas; and then, ideas of impressions of re-
  8616. flection. Somewhere in this process, there is to be found repetition of im-
  8617. pressions, and thence by 'habit'— by which we may suppose that a par-
  8618. ticular mode of 'derivation' is meant— by habit, a repetition of the cor-
  8619. relate ideas; and thence expectancy of the repetition of the correlate im-
  8620. pressions. This expectancy would be an 'impression or reflection.' It is
  8621. difficult to understand why Hume exempts 'habit' from the same criticism
  8622. as that applied to the notion of 'cause/ We have no 'impression' of 'habit/
  8623. just as we have no 'impression' of 'cause.' Cause, repetition, habit are all
  8624. in the same boat.
  8625.  
  8626. Somewhat inconsistently, Hume never allows impressions of sensation
  8627. to be derived from the correlate ideas; though, as the difference between
  8628. them only consists in 'force and vivacity,' the reason for this refusal can-
  8629. not be found inl his philosophy. The truth is that Hume retained an
  8630. obstinate belief in an external world which his principles forbade him to
  8631. confess in his philosophical constructions. He reserved that belief for his
  8632. daily life, and for his historical and sociological writings, and for his
  8633. Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion,
  8634.  
  8635. The merit of Hume's account is that the process described is within
  8636.  
  8637. 17 Italics mine.
  8638.  
  8639. 18 III, VI, 1,22,23.
  8640.  
  8641.  
  8642.  
  8643. Locke and Hume 141
  8644.  
  8645. 'the soul/ In the philosophy of organism 'the soul' as it appears in Hume,
  8646. and 'the mind' as it appears in Locke and Hume, are replaced by the
  8647. phrases 'the actual entity/ and 'the actual occasion/ these phrases being
  8648. synonymous.
  8649.  
  8650. Two defects, found equally in Locke and in Hume, are, first, the con-
  8651. fusion between a Lockian 'idea' and [214] consciousness of such an idea;
  8652. and, secondly, the assigned relations between 'ideas' of sensation and
  8653. 'ideas' of reflection.! In Hume's language, this latter point is concerned
  8654. with the relations between 'impressions of sensation' and 'impressions of
  8655. reflection.' Hume and Locke, with the overintellectualist bias prevalent
  8656. among philosophers, assume that emotional feelings are necessarily deriva-
  8657. tive from sensations. This is conspicuously not the case; the correlation
  8658. between such feelings and sensations is on the whole a secondary effect.
  8659. Emotions conspicuously brush aside sensations and fasten upon the 'par-
  8660. ticular' objects to which— in Locke's phrase— certain 'ideas' are 'deter-
  8661. mined. 7 The confinement of our prehension of other actual entities to the
  8662. mediation of private sensations is pure myth. The converse doctrine is
  8663. nearer the truth: the more primitive mode of objectification is via emo-
  8664. tional tone, and only in exceptional organisms does objectification, via
  8665. sensation, supervene with any effectiveness. In their doctrine on this
  8666. point, Locke and Hume were probably only repeating the mediaeval tradi-
  8667. tion, and they have passed on the tradition to their successors. None the
  8668. less, the doctrine is founded upon no necessity of thought, and lacks
  8669. empirical confirmation. If we consider the matter physiologically, the emo-
  8670. tional tone depends mainly on the condition of the viscera which are
  8671. peculiarly ineffective in generating sensations. Thus the whole notion of
  8672. prehension should be inverted. We prehend other actual entities more
  8673. primitively by direct mediation of emotional tone, and only secondarily
  8674. and waveringly by direct mediation of sense. The two modes fuse with
  8675. important effects upon our perceptive knowledge. This topic must be
  8676. reserved (cf. Parts III and IV) for further discussion; but it is fundamental
  8677. in the philosophy of organism. One difficulty in appealing to modern
  8678. psychology, for the purpose of a preliminary survey of the nature of ex-
  8679. perience, is that so much of that science is based upon the presupposition
  8680. of the sensationalist mythology. Thus the sim- [215] pier, more naive sur-
  8681. veys of Locke and Hume are philosophically the more useful.
  8682.  
  8683. Later, in Part III, a 'prehension' will be analysed into 'prehending sub-
  8684. ject/ 'object prehended/ and 'subjective form.' The philosophy of or-
  8685. ganism follows Locke in admitting particular 'exterior things' into the
  8686. category of 'object prehended.' It also follows Hume in his admission at
  8687. the end of his Appendix to the Treatise: "Had I said, that two ideas of the
  8688. same object can only be different by their different jeeling y I should have
  8689. been nearer the truth." What Hume here calls 'feeling' is expanded in the
  8690. philosophy of organism into the doctrine of 'subjective form.' But there is
  8691. another ineradicable difference between some prehensions, namely, their
  8692.  
  8693.  
  8694.  
  8695. 142 Discussions and Applications
  8696.  
  8697. diversity of prehending subjects, when the two prehensions are in that
  8698. respect diverse. The subsequent uses of the term 'feeling' are in the sense
  8699. of the positive' type of prehensions, and not in the sense in which Hume
  8700. uses it in the above quotation.
  8701.  
  8702. The approximation of the philosophy of organism to Santayana's doc-
  8703. trine of 'animal faith' is effected by this doctrine of objectification by the
  8704. mediation of 'feeling/
  8705.  
  8706. Santayana would deny that 'animal faith' has in it any element of given-
  8707. ness. This denial is presumably made in deference to the sensationalist
  8708. doctrine, that all knowledge of the external world arises by the mediation
  8709. of private sensations. If we allow the term 'animal faith' to describe a
  8710. kind of perception which has been neglected by the philosophic tradition,
  8711. then practically the whole of Santayana's discussion 19 is in accord with
  8712. the organic philosophy.
  8713.  
  8714. The divergence from, and the analogy to, Santayana's doctrine can be
  8715. understood by quoting two sentences:
  8716. I propose therefore to use the word existence ... to designate not
  8717. data of intuition but facts or events believed to occur in nature. These
  8718. facts or events will include, first, intuitions themselves, or instances of
  8719. con- [216] sciousness, like pains and pleasures and all remembered ex-
  8720. periences and mental discourse; and second, physical things and
  8721. events, having a transcendent relation to the data of intuition which,
  8722. in belief, may be used as signs for them; . . .*
  8723.  
  8724. It may be remarked in passing that this quotation illustrates Santayana's
  8725. admirable clarity of thought, a characteristic which he shares with the men
  8726. of genius of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. Now the exact point
  8727. where Santayana differs from the organic philosophy ist his implicit as-
  8728. sumption that 'intuitions themselves* cannot be among the 'data of in-
  8729. tuition/ that is to say, the data of other intuitions. This possibility is what
  8730. Santayana denies and the organic philosophy asserts. In this respect
  8731. Santayana is voicing the position which, implicitly or explicitly, pervades
  8732. modern philosophy. He is only distinguished by his clarity of thought. If
  8733. Santayana's position be granted, there is a phenomenal veil, a primitive
  8734. credulity associated with action and valuation, and a mysterious symbolism
  8735. from the veil to the realities behind the veil. The only difference between
  8736. such philosophers lies in their reading of the symbolism, some read more
  8737. and some less. There can be no decision between them, since there are no
  8738. rational principles which penetrate from the veil to the dark background of
  8739. reality.
  8740.  
  8741. The organic philosophy denies this doctrine because, first, it is contrary
  8742. to naive experience; secondly, 'memory' is a very special instance of an
  8743. antecedent act of experience becoming a datum of intuition for another
  8744. act of experience; thirdly, the rejected doctrine is derived from the mis-
  8745.  
  8746. 19 Cf . his Scepticism and Animal Faith.
  8747.  
  8748.  
  8749.  
  8750. Locke and Hume 143
  8751.  
  8752. conception of Locke, already noted previously (cf. Part II, Ch. I, Sect.
  8753. VI), that logical simplicity can be identified with priority in the con-
  8754. crescent process. Locke, in his first two books,t attempts to build up
  8755. experience from the basic elements of simple 'ideas' of, sensation. These
  8756. simple ideas are practically Santayana's 'intuitions of essences. 7 Santayana
  8757. explicitly [217] repudiates the misconception, but in so doing he knocks
  8758. away one of the supports of his doctrine. A fourth reason for the rejection
  8759. of the doctrine is that the way is thereby opened for a rational scheme of
  8760. cosmology in which a final reality is identified with acts of experience.
  8761.  
  8762.  
  8763.  
  8764. CHAPTER VI
  8765. FROM DESCARTES TO KANT
  8766.  
  8767. SECTION I
  8768.  
  8769. [218] A comparison of thet different ways in which Descartes and Locke
  8770. respectively conceived the scope of their investigations at once discloses the
  8771. very important shift which Locke introduced into the tradition of philo-
  8772. sophic thought. Descartes asked the fundamental metaphysical question,
  8773. What is it to be an actual entity? He found three kinds of actual entities,
  8774. namely, cogitating minds, extended bodies, and God. His word for an
  8775. actual entity was 'substance/ The fundamental proposition, whereby the
  8776. analysis of actuality could be achieved, took the form of predicating a
  8777. quality of the substance in question. A quality was either an accident or an
  8778. essential attribute. In the Cartesian philosophy there was room for three
  8779. distinct kinds of change: one was the change of accidents of an enduring
  8780. substance; another was the origination of an individual substance; and the
  8781. third was the cessation of the existence of an enduring substance. Any
  8782. individual belonging to either of the first two kinds of substances did not
  8783. require any other individual of either of these kinds in order to exist. But
  8784. it did require the concurrence of God. Thus the essential attributes of a
  8785. mind were its dependence on God and its cogitations; and the essential
  8786. attributes of a body were its dependence on God and its extension. Des-
  8787. cartes does not apply the term 'attribute' to the 'dependence on God ? ; but
  8788. it is an essential element in his philosophy. It is quite obvious that the
  8789. accidental relationships between diverse individual substances form a great
  8790. difficulty for Descartes. If they are to be included in his scheme of the
  8791. actual [219] world, they must be qualities of a substance. Thus a relation-
  8792. ship is the correlation of a pair of qualities,! one belonging exclusively to
  8793. one individual, and the other exclusively to the other individual. The cor-
  8794. relaton itself must be referred to God as one of his accidental qualities.
  8795. This is exactly Descartes' procedure in his theory of representative ideas.
  8796. In this theory, the perceived individual has one quality; the perceiving in-
  8797. dividual has anothert quality which is the 'idea' representing this quality;
  8798. God is aware of the correlation; and the perceiver's knowledge of God
  8799. guarantees for him the veracity of his idea. It is unnecessary to criticize
  8800. this very artificial account of what common sense believes to be our direct
  8801. knowledge of other actual entities. But it is the only account consistent
  8802. with the metaphysical materials provided by Descartes, combined with his
  8803. assumption of a multiplicity of actual entities. In this assumption of a
  8804.  
  8805. 144
  8806.  
  8807.  
  8808.  
  8809. From Descartes To Kant 145
  8810.  
  8811. multiplicity of actual entities the philosophy of organism follows Des-
  8812. cartes. It is, however! obvious that there are only two ways out of Descartes*
  8813. difficulties; one way is to have recourse to some form of monism; the other
  8814. way is to reconstruct Descartes' metaphysical machinery.
  8815.  
  8816. But Descartes asserts one principle which is the basis of all philosophy:
  8817. he holds that the whole pyramid of knowledge is based upon the im-
  8818. mediate operation of knowing which is either an essential (for Descartes),
  8819. or a contributory, element in the composition of an immediate actual en-
  8820. tity. This is also a first principle for the philosophy of organism. But
  8821. Descartes allowed the subject-predicate form of proposition, and the
  8822. philosophical tradition derived from it, to dictate his subsequent meta-
  8823. physical development. For his philosophy, 'actuality' meant 'to be a sub-
  8824. stance with inhering qualities/ For the philosophy of organism, the per-
  8825. cipient occasion is its own standard of actuality. If in its knowledge other
  8826. actual entities appear, it can only be because they conform to its standard
  8827. of actuality. There can only be [220] evidence of a world of actual entities,
  8828. if the immediate actual entity discloses them as essential to its own com-
  8829. position. Descartes' notion of an unessential experience of the external
  8830. world is entirely alien to the organic philosophy. This is the root point of
  8831. divergence; and is the reason why the organic philosophy has to abandon
  8832. any approach to the substance-quality notion of actuality. The organic
  8833. philosophy interprets experience as meaning the 'self-enjoyment of being
  8834. one among many, and of being one arising out of the composition of
  8835. many/ Descartes interprets experience as meaning the 'self-enjoyment, by
  8836. an individual substance, of its qualification by ideas/ t
  8837.  
  8838. SECTION II
  8839.  
  8840. Locke explicitly discards metaphysics. His enquiry has a limited scope:
  8841. This therefore being my purpose, to inquire into the original, cer-
  8842. tainty, and extent of human knowledge, together with the grounds and
  8843. degrees of belief, opinion, and assent, I shall not at present meddle
  8844. with the physical consideration of the mind, or trouble myself to
  8845. examine wherein its essence consists, ... It shall suffice to my present
  8846. purpose, to consider the discerning faculties of a man as they are em-
  8847. ployed about the objects which they have to do with; . . }
  8848.  
  8849. The enduring importance of Locke's work comes from the candour,
  8850. clarity, and adequacy with which he stated the evidence, uninfluenced by
  8851. the bias of metaphysical theory. He explained, in the sense of stating
  8852. plainly, and not in the more usual sense of 'explaining away/ By an ironic
  8853. development in the history of thought, Locke's successors, who arrogated
  8854. to themselves the title of 'empiricists,' have been chiefly employed in ex-
  8855. plaining away the obvious facts of experience in obedience to the a priori
  8856. doctrine of sensationalism, inherited from the mediaeval philosophy which
  8857.  
  8858. 1 Essay, I, I, 2.
  8859.  
  8860.  
  8861.  
  8862. 146 Discussions and Applications
  8863.  
  8864. they despised. Locke's Essay is the invaluable storehouse for those who
  8865. wish to [221] confront their metaphysical constructions by a recourse to
  8866. the facts.
  8867.  
  8868. Hume clipped his explanation by this a priori theory, which he states
  8869. explicitly in the first quotation made from his Treatise in the previous
  8870. chapter. It cannot be too often repeated:
  8871. We may observe, that it is universally allowed by philosophers, and is
  8872. besides pretty obvious of itself, that nothing is ever really present with
  8873. the mind but its perceptions f or impressions and ideas, and that ex-
  8874. ternal objects become known to us only by those perceptions they
  8875. occasion. To hate, to love, to think, to feel, to see; all this is nothing
  8876. but to perceive.
  8877.  
  8878. Hume, in agreement with what 'is universally allowed by philosophers/
  8879. interprets this statement in a sensationalist sense. In accordance with
  8880. this sense, an impression is nothing else than a particular instance of the
  8881. mind's awareness of a universal, which may either be simple, or may be a
  8882. manner of union of many simple universals. For Hume, hating, loving,
  8883. thinking, feeling, are nothing but perceptions derivate from these funda-
  8884. mental impressions. This is the a priori sensationalist dogma, which bounds
  8885. all Hume's discoveries in the realm of experience. It is probable that this
  8886. dogma was in Locke's mind throughout the earlier portion of his Essay.
  8887. But Locke was not seeking consistency with any a priori dogma. He also
  8888. finds in experience 'ideas' with characteristics which 'determine them to
  8889. this or that particular existent.' Such inconsistency with their dogma
  8890. shocks empiricists, who refuse to admit experience, naked and unashamed,
  8891. devoid of their a priori figleaf. Locke is merely stating what, in practice,
  8892. nobody doubts. But Locke would have agreed with Hume in refusing to
  8893. admit that 'ideas of reflection' may be directly 'determined to some par-
  8894. ticular existent,' without the intervention of 'ideas of sensation.' In this
  8895. respect, Locke was a sensationalist, and the philosophy of organism is not
  8896. sensationalist. But Locke's avoidance of metaphysics only led him up to a
  8897. stage of thought for which meta- [222] physics is essential to clarity. The
  8898. questions as to the status of a 'particular existent,' and of an 'idea deter-
  8899. mined to a particular existent,' demand metaphysical discussion. Locke is
  8900. never tired of disparaging the notion of 'substance'; but he gives no hint of
  8901. alternative categories which he would employ to analysef the notions of
  8902. an 'actual entity' and of 'reality.' But his Essay, however, does contain a
  8903. line of thought which can be developed into a metaphysic. In the first
  8904. place, he distinctly holds that ideas of particular existents— for example,
  8905. the child's idea of its mother —constitute the fundamental data which the
  8906. mental functioning welds into a unity by a determinate process of ab-
  8907. sorption, including comparison, emphasis, and abstraction. He also holds
  8908. that 'powers' are to be ascribed to particular existents whereby the con-
  8909. stitutions of other particulars are conditioned. Correlatively, he holds that
  8910. the constitutions of particular existents must be described so as to exhibit
  8911.  
  8912.  
  8913.  
  8914. From Descartes To Kant 147
  8915.  
  8916. their 'capacities' for being conditioned by such 'powers' in other particulars.
  8917. He also holds that all qualities have in some sense a relational element in
  8918. them. Perhaps, though Locke does not say so, this notion of the relational
  8919. element in qualities is illustrated in the following passage: "Besides, there
  8920. is scarce any particular thing existing, which, in some of its simple ideas,
  8921. does not communicate with a greater, and in others with a less, number of
  8922. particular beings: . . ." 2 Locke here expresses the notion of an identity be-
  8923. tween two simple ideas in the form of a 'communication' between the par-
  8924. ticular existents which possess that common quality. This passage also
  8925. illustrates Locke's habit of employing the term 'idea't in a sense other than
  8926. particular content of an act of awareness. Finally, Locke's notion of the
  8927. passage of time is that something is 'perpetually perishing/ If he had
  8928. grasped the notion that the actual entity 'perishes' in the passage of time,
  8929. so that no actual entity changes, he would have arrived [223] at the point
  8930. of view of the philosophy of organism. What he does say, is "perpetually
  8931. perishing parts of succession." 3 Here, as elsewhere, Locke's neglect of
  8932. ultimate questions revenges itself upon him. Nothing can make the var-
  8933. ious parts of his Essay mutually consistent. He never revises the sub-
  8934. stance-quality categories which remain presupposed throughout his Essay.
  8935. In the first two books of the Essay , he professes to lay the foundations of
  8936. his doctrine of ideas. These books are implicitly dominated by the notion
  8937. of the ideas as mere qualifications of the substrate mind. In the third book
  8938. of the Essay he is apparently passing on to the application of his estab-
  8939. lished doctrine of ideas to the subordinate question of the function of
  8940. language. But he tacitly introduces a new doctrine of ideas, which is dif-
  8941. ficult to conciliate with the sensationalist doctrine of the preceding books.
  8942. Hume concentrates upon the doctrine of Locke's earlier books; the phi-
  8943. losophy of organism concentrates upon that of the later books in the Essay.
  8944. If Locke's Essay is to be interpreted as a consistent scheme of thought, un-
  8945. doubtedly Hume is right; but such an interpretation offers violence to
  8946. Locke's contribution to philosophy.
  8947.  
  8948. SECTION III
  8949.  
  8950. In the philosophy of organism it is assumed that an actual entity is
  8951. composite. 'Actuality* is the fundamental exemplification of composition;
  8952. all other meanings of 'composition' are referent to this root-meaning. But
  8953. 'actuality' is a general term, which merely indicates this ultimate type of
  8954. composite unity: there are many composite unities to which this general
  8955. term applies. There is no general fact of composition, not expressible in
  8956. terms of the composite constitutions of the individual occasions. Every
  8957. proposition is entertained in the constitution of some one actual entity, or
  8958. severally in the constitutions of many actual entities. This is only [224]
  8959.  
  8960. * Essay, III, IX, 14.
  8961. 3 II, XIV, 1.
  8962.  
  8963.  
  8964.  
  8965. 148 Discussions and Applications
  8966.  
  8967. another rendering of the 'ontological principle/ It follows from the on-
  8968. tological principle, thus interpreted, that the notion of a 'common world'
  8969. must find its exemplification in the constitution of each actual entity, taken
  8970. by itself for analysis. For an actual entity cannot be a member of a 'com-
  8971. mon world/ except in the sense that the 'common world' is a constituent
  8972. of its own constitution. It follows that every item of the universe, includ-
  8973. ing all the other actual entities, is a constituentt in the constitution of any
  8974. one actual entity. This conclusion has already been employed under the
  8975. title of the principle of relativity/ This principle of relativity is the axiom
  8976. by which the ontological principle is rescued from issuing in an extreme
  8977. monism. Hume adumbrates this principle in his notion of 'repetition/
  8978.  
  8979. Some principle is now required to rescue actual entities from being
  8980. undifferentiated repetitions, each of the other, with mere numerical di-
  8981. versity. This requisite is supplied by the 'principle of intensive relevance/
  8982. The notion of intensive relevance is fundamental for the meaning of such
  8983. concepts as 'alternative possibilities/ 'more or less/ 'important or negli-
  8984. gible. 7 The principle asserts that any item of the universe, however pre-
  8985. posterous as an abstract thought, or however remote as an actual entity,
  8986. has its own gradation of relevance, as prehended, in the constitution of any
  8987. one actual entity: it might have had more relevance: and it might have had
  8988. less relevance, including the zero of relevance involved in the negative
  8989. prehension; but in fact it has just that relevance whereby it finds its
  8990. status in the constitution of that actual entity. It will be remembered that
  8991. Hume finds it necessary to introduce the notion of variations in 'force and
  8992. vivacity/ He is here making a particular application— and, as I believe, an
  8993. unsuccessful application— of the general principle of intensive relevance.
  8994.  
  8995. There is interconnection between the degrees of relevance of different
  8996. items in the same actual entity. This fact of interconnection is asserted in
  8997. the 'principle of \225] compatibility and contrariety/ There are items
  8998. which, in certain respective gradations of relevance, are contraries to each
  8999. other; so that those items, with their respective intensities of relevance,
  9000. cannot coexist in the constitution of one actual entity. If some group of
  9001. items, with their variety of relevance, can coexist in one actual entity, then
  9002. the group, as thus variously relevant, is a compatible group. The various
  9003. specific essences of one genus, whereby an actual entity may belong to one
  9004. or other of the species but cannot belong to more than one, illustrate the
  9005. incompatibility between two groups of items. Also in so far as a specific
  9006. essence is complex, the specific essence is necessarily composed of com-
  9007. patible items, if there has been any exemplification of that species. But
  9008. 'feelings' are the entities which are primarily 'compatible 7 or 'incom-
  9009. patible/ All other usages of these terms are derivative.
  9010.  
  9011. The words 'real' and 'potential 7 are, in this exposition, taken in senses
  9012. which are antithetical. In their primary senses, they qualify the 'eternal
  9013. objects/ These eternal objects determine how the world of actual entities
  9014. enters into the constitution of each one of its members via its feelings.
  9015.  
  9016.  
  9017.  
  9018. From Descartes To Kant 149
  9019.  
  9020. And they also express how the constitution of any one actual entity is
  9021. analysable into phases, related as presupposed and presupposing. Eternal
  9022. objects express how the predecessor-phase is absorbed into the successor-
  9023. phaset without limitation of itself, but with additions necessary for the
  9024. determination of an actual unity in the form of individual satisfaction. The
  9025. actual entities enter into each others' constitutions under limitations im-
  9026. posed by incompatibilities 4 of feelings. Such incompatibilities relegate
  9027. various elements in the constitutions of felt objects to the intensive zero,
  9028. which is termed 'irrelevance/ The preceding phases enter into their succes-
  9029. sors with additions which eliminate the inde- [226] terminations. The how
  9030. of the limitations, and the how of the additions, are alike the realization of
  9031. eternal objects in the constitution of the actual entity in question. An
  9032. eternal object in abstraction from any one particular actual entity is a
  9033. potentiality for ingression into actual entities. In its ingression into any
  9034. one actual entity, either as relev9.it or as irrelevant, it retains its poten-
  9035. tiality of indefinite diversity of modes of ingression, a potential indeter-
  9036. mination rendered determinate in this instance. The definite ingression
  9037. into a particular actual entity is not to be conceived as the sheer evocation
  9038. of that eternal object from 'not-being' into 'being'; it is the evocation of
  9039. determination out of indetermination. Potentiality becomes reality; and
  9040. yet retains its message of alternatives which the actual entity has avoided.
  9041. In the constitution of an actual entity: —what ever component is red, might
  9042. have been green; and whatever component is loved, might have been
  9043. coldly esteemed. The term 'universal' is unfortunate in its application to
  9044. eternal objects; for it seems to deny, and in fact it was meant to deny, that
  9045. the actual entities also fall within the scope of the principle of relativity.
  9046. If the term 'eternal objects' is disliked, the term 'potentials' would be
  9047. suitable. The eternal objects are the pure potentials of the universe; and
  9048. the actual entities differ from each other in their realization of potentials.
  9049. Locke's term 'idea,' in his primary use of it in the first two books of the
  9050. Essay, means the determinate ingression of an eternal object into the ac-
  9051. tual entity in question. But he also introduces the limitation t to conscious
  9052. mentality, which is here abandoned.
  9053.  
  9054. Thus in the philosophy of organism, Locke's first use of the term 'idea'
  9055. is covered by the doctrine of the 'ingression 7 of eternal objects into actual
  9056. entities; and his second use of the same term is covered by the doctrine of
  9057. the 'objectification' of actual entities. The two doctrines cannot be ex-
  9058. plained apart from each other: they constitute explanations of the two
  9059. fundamental principles— [227] the ontological principle and the principle
  9060. of relativity.
  9061.  
  9062. The four stages constitutive of an actual entity have been stated above
  9063. in Part II, Chapter III, Section I. They can be named, datum, process,
  9064.  
  9065. 4 Dr. H. M. Sheffer has pointed out the fundamental logical importance of the
  9066. notion of 'incompatibility'; cf. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc.,f Vol. XIV, pp. 481-
  9067. 488; and Introduction to Vol. 1 of Principia Mathematica (2nd edition).
  9068.  
  9069.  
  9070.  
  9071. 150 Discussions and Applications
  9072.  
  9073. satisfaction, decision. The two terminal stages have to do with 'becoming'
  9074. in the sense of the transition from the settled actual world to the new-
  9075. actual entity relatively to which that settlement is defined. But such
  9076. 'definition* must be found as an element in the actual entities concerned.
  9077. The 'settlement' which an actual entity 'finds' is its datum. It is to be con-
  9078. ceived as a limited perspective of the 'settled' world provided by the
  9079. eternal objects concerned. This datum is 'decided' by the settled world.
  9080. It is 'prehended' by the new superseding entity. The datum is the ob-
  9081. jective content of the experience. The decision, providing the datum, is a
  9082. transference of self-limited appetition; the settled world provides the 'real
  9083. potentiality' that its many actualities be felt compatibly; and the new
  9084. concrescence starts from this datum. The perspective is provided by the
  9085. elimination of incompatibilities. The final stage, the 'decision/ is how the
  9086. actual entity, having attained its individual 'satisfaction/ thereby adds a
  9087. determinate condition to the settlement for the future beyond itself. Thus
  9088. the 'datum' is the 'decision received/ and the 'decision' is the 'decision
  9089. transmitted/ Between these two decisions, received and transmitted, there
  9090. lie the two stages, 'process 7 and 'satisfaction.' The datum is indeterminate
  9091. as regards the final satisfaction. The 'process' is the addition of those ele-
  9092. ments of feeling whereby these indeterminations are dissolved into de-
  9093. terminate linkages attaining the actual unity of an individual actual entity.
  9094. The actual entity, in becoming itself, also solves the question as to what
  9095. it is to be. Thus process is the stage in which the creative idea works
  9096. towards the definition and attainment of a determinate individuality.
  9097. Process is the growth and attainment of a final end. The progressive defini-
  9098. [228] tion of the final end is the efficacious condition for its attainment.
  9099. The determinate unity of an actual entity is bound together by the final
  9100. causation towards an ideal progressively defined by its progressive relation
  9101. to the determinations and indeterminations of the datum. The ideal, itself
  9102. felt, defines what 'self shall arise from the datum; and the ideal is also
  9103. an element in the self which thus arises.
  9104.  
  9105. According to this account, efficient causation expresses the transition
  9106. from actual entity to actual entity; and final causation expresses the in-
  9107. ternal process whereby the actual entity becomes itself. There is the be-
  9108. coming of the datum, which is to be found in the past of the world; and
  9109. there is the becoming of the immediate self from the datum. This latter
  9110. becoming is the immediate actual process. An actual entity is at once the
  9111. product of the efficient past, and is also, in Spinoza's phrase, causa sui.
  9112. Every philosophy recognizes, in some form or other, this factor of self-
  9113. causation, in what it takes to be ultimate actual fact. Spinoza's words have
  9114. already been quoted. Descartes' argument, from the very fact of thinking,
  9115. assumes that this freely determined operation is thereby constitutive of an
  9116. occasion in the endurance of an actual entity. He writes (Meditation II) :
  9117. "I am, I exist, is necessarily true each time that I pronounce it, or that I
  9118.  
  9119.  
  9120.  
  9121. From Descartes To Kant 151
  9122.  
  9123. mentally conceive it." Descartes in his own philosophy conceives the
  9124. thinker as creating the occasional thought. The philosophy of organism
  9125. inverts the order, and conceives the thought as a constituent operation in
  9126. the creation of the occasional thinker. The thinker is the final end whereby
  9127. there is the thought. In this inversion we have the final contrast between a
  9128. philosophy of substance and a philosophy of organism. The operations of
  9129. an organism are directed towards the organism as a 'superject/ and are not
  9130. directed from the organism as a 'subject/ The operations are directed from
  9131. antecedent organisms and to the immediate organism. They are Vectors/
  9132. in that they convey the many [229] things into the constitution of the
  9133. single super ject. The creative process is rhythmic: it swings from the
  9134. publicity of many things to the individual privacy; and it swings back from
  9135. the private individual to the publicity of the objectified individual. The
  9136. former swing is dominated by the final cause, which is the ideal; and the
  9137. latter swing is dominated by the efficient cause, t which is actual.
  9138.  
  9139. SECTION IV
  9140.  
  9141. From the point of view of the philosophy of organism, the credit must
  9142. be given to Hume that he emphasized the 'process' inherent in the fact of
  9143. being a mind. His analysis of that process is faulty in its details. It was
  9144. bound to be so; because, with Locke, he misconceived his problem to be
  9145. the analysis of mental operations. He should have conceived it as the anal-
  9146. ysis of operations constituent of actual entities. He would then have
  9147. found mental operations in their proper place. Kant followed Hume in
  9148. this misconception; and was thus led to balance the world upon thought-
  9149. oblivious to the scanty supply of thinking. But Hume, Kant, and the
  9150. philosophy of organism agree that the task of the critical reason is the
  9151. analysis of constructs; and 'construction' is 'process/ Hume's analysis of
  9152. the construct which constitutes a mental occasion is: impressions of sen-
  9153. sation, ideas of impressions of sensation, impressions of reflection, ideas of
  9154. impressions of reflection. This analysis may be found obscurely in Locke.
  9155. But Hume exhibits it as an orderly process; and then endeavours— and
  9156. fails— to express in terms of it our ordinary beliefs, in which he shares.
  9157.  
  9158. For subsequent empiricists the pleasure of the dogma has overcome the
  9159. metaphysical rule of evidence: that we must bow to those presumptions,
  9160. which, in despite of criticism, we still employ for the regulation of our
  9161. lives. Such presumptions are imperative in experience. Rationalism is
  9162. the search for the coherence of such presumptions. Hume, in his series of
  9163. ideas and of impressions, derivates from impressions of sensation, im-
  9164. plicitly allows \230) that the building-up of experience is a process of addi-
  9165. tion to original data. The philosophy of organism, in this respect, agrees with
  9166. Hume. It disagrees with Hume as to the proper characterization of the
  9167. primary data. In Hume's philosophy the primary impressions are char-
  9168. acterized in terms of universals, e.g., in the first section of his Treatise he
  9169.  
  9170.  
  9171.  
  9172. 152 Discussions and Applications
  9173.  
  9174. refers to the colour 'red 7 as an illustration. This is also the doctrine of the
  9175. first two books of Locke's Essay. But in Locke's third book a different
  9176. doctrine appears, and the primary data are explicitly said to be 'ideas of
  9177. particular existents.' According to Locke's second doctrine, the ideas of
  9178. universals are derived from these primary data by a process of comparison
  9179. and analysis. The philosophy of organism agrees in principle with this
  9180. second doctrine of Locke's. It is difficult, and trifling, to determine the
  9181. exact extent of the agreement; because the expositions of Locke and Hume
  9182. bring in the very derivative operations involving consciousness. The or-
  9183. ganic philosophy does not hold that the 'particular existents' are prehended
  9184. apart from universals; on the contrary, it holds that they are prehended by
  9185. the mediation of universals. In other words, each actuality is prehended
  9186. by means of some element of its own definiteness. This is the doctrine of
  9187. the 'objectification' of actual entities. Thus the primary stage in the con-
  9188. crescence of an actual entity is the way in which the antecedent universe
  9189. enters into the constitution of the entity in question, so as to constitute the
  9190. basis of its nascent individuality. A converse way of looking at this truth is
  9191. that the relevance to other actual entities of its own status in the actual
  9192. world t is the initial datum in the process of its concrescence. When it is
  9193. desired to emphasize this interpretation of the datum, the phrase 'objec-
  9194. tive content' will be used synonymously with the term 'datum. 7 Of course,
  9195. strictly speaking, the universals, to which Hume confines the datum, are
  9196. also 'objects'; but the phrase 'objective content' is meant to emphasize the
  9197. doctrine of 'objectificarion' of actual entities. If experi- \231] ence be not
  9198. based upon an objective content, there can be no escape from a solipsist
  9199. subjectivism. But Hume, and Locke in his main doctrine, fail to provide
  9200. experience with any objective content. Kant, fort whom 'process' is
  9201. mainly a process of thought, accepts Hume's doctrine as to the 'datum'
  9202. and turns the 'apparent' objective content into the end of the construct.
  9203. So far, Kant's 'apparent' objective content seems to take the place of the
  9204. 'satisfaction' in the philosophy of organism. In this way there can be no
  9205. real escape from the solipsist difficulty. But Kant in his appeal to 'practical
  9206. reason' admits also the 'satisfaction' in a sense analogous to that in the
  9207. philosophy of organism; and by an analysis of its complex character he
  9208. arrives at ultimate actualities which, according to his account, cannot be
  9209. discovered by any analysis of 'mere appearance.' This is a very complex
  9210. doctrine, which has been reproduced in all philosophies derivative from
  9211. Kant. The doctrine gives each actual entity two worlds, one world of mere
  9212. appearance, and the other world compact of ultimate substantial fact. On
  9213. this point, as to the absence of 'objective content' in the datum for ex-
  9214. perience, Santayana 5 seems to agree with Hume and Kant. But if his in-
  9215. troduction of 'animal faith' is to be taken as a re-examination of the datum
  9216. under the influence of the sceptical conclusion from Hume's doctrine, then
  9217. 5 Cf . Scepticism and Animal Faith.
  9218.  
  9219.  
  9220.  
  9221. From Descartes To Kant 153
  9222.  
  9223. he, as his second doctrine, is practically reasserting Locke's second doc-
  9224. trine. But if he is appealing to 'practice' away from the critical examina-
  9225. tion of our sources of information, he must be classed with Hume and
  9226. Kant, although differing from them in every detail of procedure.
  9227.  
  9228. In view of the anti-rationalism of Hume's contented appeal to 'practice/
  9229. it is very difficult to understand— except as another example of anti-ra-
  9230. tionalism— the strong objection, entertained by Hume and by his 'em-
  9231. piricist' followers, to the anti-rationalistic basis of some forms of religious
  9232. faith. This strain of anti-rationalism [232] which Locke and Hume ex-
  9233. plicitly introduced into philosophy marks the final triumph of the anti-
  9234. rationalistic reaction against the rationalism of the Middle Ages. Ration-
  9235. alism is the belief that clarity can only be reached by pushing explanation
  9236. to its utmost limits. Locke, who hoped to attain final clarity in his analysis
  9237. of human understanding in divorce from metaphysics, was, so far, an anti-
  9238. rationalist. But Hume, in so far as he is to be construed as remaining con-
  9239. tent with two uncoordinated sets of beliefs, one based on the critical ex-
  9240. amination of our sources of knowledge, and the other on the uncritical +
  9241. examination of beliefs involved in 'practice,' reaches the high watermark
  9242. of anti-rationalism in philosophy; for 'explanation' is the analysis of
  9243. coordination.
  9244.  
  9245. SECTION V
  9246.  
  9247. The process whereby an actual entity, starting from its objective con-
  9248. tent, attains its individual satisfaction, will be more particularly analysed
  9249. in Part III. The primary character of this process is that it is individual to
  9250. the actual entity; it expresses how the datum, which involves the actual
  9251. world, becomes a component in the one actual entity. There must there-
  9252. fore be no further reference to other actual entities; the elements available
  9253. for the explanation are simply, the objective content, eternal objects, and
  9254. the selective concrescence of feelings whereby an actual entity becomes
  9255. itself. It must be remembered that the objective content is analysable into
  9256. actual entities under limited perspectives provided by their own natures:
  9257. these limited perspectives involve eternal objects in grades of relevance. If
  9258. the 'process' were primarily a process of understanding, we should have to
  9259. note that 'grades of relevance' are only other eternal objects in grades of
  9260. relevance, and so on indefinitely. But we have not the sort of understand-
  9261. ings which embrace such indefinite progressions. Accordingly there is here
  9262. a vicious regress, if the process be essentially a process of understanding.
  9263. But this is not the primary [233] description of it; the process is a process
  9264. of 'feeling.' In feeling, what is felt is not necessarily analysed; in under-
  9265. standing, what is understood is analysed, in so far as it is understood. Un-
  9266. derstanding is a special form of feeling. Thus there is no vicious regress in
  9267. feeling, by reason of the indefinite complexity of what is felt. Kant, in his
  9268.  
  9269.  
  9270.  
  9271. 154 Discussions and Applications
  9272.  
  9273. 'Transcendental Aesthetic/ 1 emphasizes the doctrine that in intuition a
  9274. complex datum is intuited as one.
  9275.  
  9276. Again the selection involved in the phrase 'selective concrescence* is not
  9277. a selection among the components of the objective content; for, by hy-
  9278. pothesis, the objective content is a datum. The compatibilities and in-
  9279. compatibilities which impose the perspective, transforming the actual
  9280. world into the datum, are inherent in the nature of things. Thus the
  9281. selection is a selection of relevant eternal objects whereby what is a
  9282. datum from without is transformed into its complete determination as a
  9283. fact within. The problem whicht the concrescence solves is, how the many
  9284. components of the objective content are to be unified in one felt content
  9285. with its complex subjective form. This one felt content is the 'satisfaction/
  9286. whereby the actual entity is its particular individual self; to use Descartes'
  9287. phrase, 'requiring nothing but itself in order to exist/ In the conception of
  9288. the actual entity in its phase of satisfaction, the entity has attained its in-
  9289. dividual separation from other things; it has absorbed the datum, and it
  9290. has not yet lost itself in the swing back to the 'decision' whereby its ap-
  9291. petition becomes an element in the data of other entities superseding it.
  9292. Time has stood still—if only it could.
  9293.  
  9294. Thus process is the admission of eternal objects in their new role of
  9295. investing the datum with the individuality of the subject. The datum,*
  9296. quat mere datum, includes the many individualities of the actual world.
  9297. The satisfaction includes these many individualities as subordinate con-
  9298. tributors to the one individuality. The process admits or rejects t eternal
  9299. objects which by their absorption into the subjective forms of the many
  9300. feelings [234] effect this integration. The attainment of satisfaction rele-
  9301. gates all eternal objects which are not 'felt' either as determinants of
  9302. definiteness in the data,t or as determinants of definiteness in the subjective
  9303. form of the satisfaction, into the status of contraries to the eternal objects
  9304. which are thus felt. Thus all indeterminations respecting the potentialities
  9305. of the universe are definitely solved so far as concerns the satisfaction of
  9306. the subject in question.
  9307.  
  9308. The process can be analysed genetically into a series of subordinate
  9309. phases which presuppose their antecedents. Neither the intermediate
  9310. phases, nor the datum which is the primary phase of all, determine the
  9311. final phase of determinate individualization. Thus an actual entity, on its
  9312. ^subjective side, is nothing else than what the universe is for it, including
  9313. its own reactions. The reactions are the subjective forms of the feelings,
  9314. elaborated into definiteness through stages of process. An actual entity
  9315. achieves its own unity by its determinate feelings respecting every item of
  9316. the datum. Every individual objectification in the datum has its perspec-
  9317. tive defined by its own eternal objects with their own relevance compatible
  9318. with the relevance of other objectifications. Each such objectification, and
  9319. each such complex of objectifications, in the datum is met with a corre-
  9320. spondent feeling, with its determinate subjective form, until the many
  9321.  
  9322.  
  9323.  
  9324. From Descartes To Kant 155
  9325.  
  9326. become one experience, the satisfaction. The philosophies of substance
  9327. presuppose a subject which then encounters a datum, and then reacts to
  9328. the datum. The philosophy of organism presupposes a datum which is met
  9329. with feelings, and progressively attains the unity of a subject. But with
  9330. this doctrine, 'superject' would be a better term than 'subject/ Locke's
  9331. 'ideas of reflection' are the feelings, in so far as they have entered into
  9332. consciousness.
  9333.  
  9334. It is by reference to feelings that the notion of 'immediacy' obtains its
  9335. meaning. The mere objectification of actual entities by eternal objects
  9336. lacks 'immediacy/ It is 'repetition'; and this is a contrary to 'immediacy.'
  9337. [235] But 'process' is the rush of feelings whereby second-handedness at-
  9338. tains subjective immediacy; in this way, subjective form overwhelms repe-
  9339. tition, and transforms it into immediately felt satisfaction; objectivity is
  9340. absorbed into subjectivity. It is useful to compare this analysis of the
  9341. construction of an act of experience with Kant's. In the first place Kant's
  9342. act of experience is essentially knowledge. Thus whatever is not knowledge
  9343. is necessarily inchoate, and merely on its way to knowledge. In comparing
  9344. Kant's procedure with that of the philosophy of organism, it must be
  9345. remembered that an 'apparent' objective content is the end of Kant's
  9346. process, and thus takes the place of 'satisfaction' in the process as analysed
  9347. in the philosophy of organism. In Kant's phraseology at the beginning of
  9348. the Critique of Pure Reason, this 'apparent' objective content is referred to
  9349. as 'objects.' He also accepts Hume's sensationalist account of the datum.
  9350. Kant places this sentence at the commencement of the Critique: "Objects
  9351. therefore are given to us through our sensibility. Sensibility alone supplies
  9352. us with intuitions. These intuitions become thought through the under-
  9353. standing, and hence arise conceptions." 6 This is expanded later in a form
  9354. which makes Kant's adhesion to Hume's doctrine of the datum more
  9355. explicit:
  9356.  
  9357. And here we see that the impressions of the senses give the first im-
  9358. pulse to the whole faculty of knowledge with respect to them, and
  9359. thus produce experience which consists of two very heterogeneous
  9360. elements, namely, matter for knowledge, derived from the senses \eine
  9361. Materiel zur Erkenntniss aus den Sinnen] f and a certain form accord-
  9362. ing to which it is arranged, derived from the internal source of pure
  9363. intuition and pure thought, first brought into action by the former,
  9364. and then producing concepts. 7
  9365. Also:
  9366.  
  9367. Thoughts with- [236] out content are empty, intuitions without con-
  9368. cepts are blind. 8
  9369.  
  9370. 6 "Vermittelst der Sinnlichkeit also werden uns Gegenstande gegeben, und sic
  9371. allein liefert uns Anschauungenjf durch den Verstand aber werden sie gedacht,
  9372. und von ihm entspringen BegrirTe." Translation in the text is Max Muller's.
  9373.  
  9374. 7 Transcendental Analytic,' f Ch. II, Sect. I (Max Muller).
  9375.  
  9376. 8 'Transcendental Logic,' Introduction, Sect. L*
  9377.  
  9378.  
  9379.  
  9380. 156 Discussions and Applications
  9381.  
  9382. In this last statement the philosophy of organism is in agreement with
  9383. Kant; but for a different reason. It is agreed that the functioning of
  9384. concepts is an essential factor in knowledge, so that 'intuitions without
  9385. concepts are blind/ But for Kant, apart from concepts there is nothing to
  9386. know; since objects related in a knowable world are the product of con-
  9387. ceptual functioning whereby categoreal form is introduced into the sense-
  9388. datum, which otherwise is intuited in the form of a mere spatio-temporal
  9389. flux of sensations. Knowledge requires that this mere flux be particularized
  9390. by conceptual functioning, whereby the flux is understood as a nexus of
  9391. 'objects/ Thus for Kant the process whereby there is experience is a
  9392. process from subjectivity to apparent objectivity. The philosophy of or-
  9393. ganism inverts this analysis, and explains the process as proceeding from
  9394. objectivity to subjectivity, namely, from the objectivity, whereby the ex-
  9395. ternal world is a datum, to the subjectivity, whereby there is one in-
  9396. dividual experience. Thus, according to the philosophy of organism, in
  9397. every act of experience there are objects for knowledge; but, apart from
  9398. the inclusion of intellectual functioning in that act of experience, there is
  9399. no knowledge.
  9400.  
  9401. We have now come to Kant, the great philosopher who first, fully and
  9402. explicitly, introduced into philosophy the conception of an act of ex-
  9403. perience as a constructive functioning, transforming subjectivity into ob-
  9404. jectivity 7 , or objectivity into subjectivity; the order is immaterial in com-
  9405. parison with the general idea. We find the first beginnings of the notion in
  9406. Locke and in Hume. Indeed, in Locke, the process is conceived in its
  9407. correct order, at least in the view of the philosophy of organism. But the
  9408. whole notion is only vaguely and inadequately conceived. The full sweep
  9409. of the notion is due to Kant. The second half of the modern period of
  9410. philosophical thought is to be dated from Hume and Kant. In it the [237]
  9411. development of cosmology has been hampered by the stress laid upon one,
  9412. or other, of three misconceptions:
  9413.  
  9414. (i) The substance-quality doctrine of actuality.
  9415.  
  9416. (ii) The sensationalist doctrine of perception.
  9417.  
  9418. (iii) The Kantian doctrine of the objective world as a construct from
  9419. subjective experience.
  9420.  
  9421. The combined influence of these allied errors has been to reduce philos-
  9422. ophy to a negligible influence in the formation of contemporary modes
  9423. of thought. Hume himself introduces the ominous appeal to 'practice-
  9424. not in criticism of his premises, but in supplement to his conclusions.
  9425. Bradley, who repudiates Hume, finds the objective world in which we live,
  9426. and move, and have our being, 'inconsistent if taken as real/ Neither side
  9427. conciliates philosophical conceptions of a real world with the world of
  9428. daily experience.
  9429.  
  9430.  
  9431.  
  9432. CHAPTER VII
  9433. THE SUBJECTIVIST PRINCIPLE
  9434.  
  9435. SECTION I
  9436.  
  9437. [238] It is impossible to scrutinize too carefully the character to be as-
  9438. signed to the datum in the act of experience. The whole philosophical
  9439. system depends on it. Hume's doctrine of 'impressions of sensation' (Trea-
  9440. tise, Book I, Part I, Sect. II) is twofold. I will call one part of his doctrine
  9441. 'The Subjectivist Principle' and the other part 'The Sensationalist Prin-
  9442. ciple/ It is usual to combine the two under the heading of the 'sensation-
  9443. alist doctrine'; but two principles are really involved, and many philos-
  9444. ophers—Locke, for instance— are not equally consistent in their adhesion
  9445. to both of them. The philosophy of organism denies both of these doc-
  9446. trines, in the form in which they are considered in this chapter, though it
  9447. accepts a reformed subjectivist principle (cf. Sect. Vf below and Part II,
  9448. Ch. IX). Locke accepted the sensationalist principle, and was inconsistent
  9449. in his statements respecting the subjectivist principle. With the exception
  9450. of some lapses, he accepted the latter in the first two books of his Essay,
  9451. and rejected it tacitly, but persistently, in the third and fourth books.
  9452. Kant (in the Critique of Pure Reason) accepted the subjectivist principle,
  9453. and rejected the sensationalist principle.
  9454.  
  9455. The sensationalist principle acquires dominating importance, if the
  9456. subjectivist principle be accepted. Kant's realization of this importance
  9457. constituted the basis of his contribution to philosophy. The history of
  9458. modern philosophy is the story of attempts to evade the inflexible con-
  9459. sequences of the subjectivist principle, explicitly or implicitly accepted.
  9460. The great merit of Hume and of [239] Kant is the explicitness with which
  9461. they faced the difficulty.
  9462.  
  9463. The subjectivist principle is, that the datum in the act of experience can
  9464. be adequately analysed purely in terms of universals.
  9465.  
  9466. The sensationalist principle is, that the primary activity in the act of
  9467. experience is the bare subjective entertainment of the datum, devoid of
  9468. any subjective form of reception. This is the doctrine of mere sensation.
  9469.  
  9470. The subjectivist principle follows from three premises: (i) The ac-
  9471. ceptance of the 'substance-quality' concept as expressing the ultimate on-
  9472. tological principle, (ii) The acceptance of Aristotle's definition of a pri-
  9473. mary substance, as always a subject and never a predicate, (in) The
  9474. assumption that the experient subject is a primary substance. The first
  9475. premise states that the final metaphysical fact is always to be expressed as
  9476.  
  9477. 157
  9478.  
  9479.  
  9480.  
  9481. 158 Discussions and Applications
  9482.  
  9483. a quality inhering in a substance. The second premise divides qualities and
  9484. primary substances into two mutually exclusive classes. The two premises
  9485. together are the foundation of the traditional distinction between uni-
  9486. versal and particulars. The philosophy of organism denies the premises on
  9487. which this distinction is founded. It admits two ultimate classes of entities,
  9488. mutually exclusive. One class consists of 'actual entities/ which in the
  9489. philosophical tradition are mis-described as 'particulars'; and the other
  9490. class consists of forms of definiteness, here named 'eternal objects/ which
  9491. in comparison with actual entities are mis-described as 'universals.' These
  9492. mis-descriptions have already been considered (Part II, Ch. I, Sect. V).
  9493.  
  9494. Descartes held, with some flashes of inconsistency arising from the use
  9495. of 'realitas objectiva/ the subjectivist principle as to the datum. But he
  9496. also held that this mitigation of the subjeetivist* principle enabled the
  9497. 'process' within experience to include a sound argument for the existence
  9498. of God; and thence a sound argument for the general veridical character of
  9499. those presumptions [240] as to the external world which somehow arise
  9500. in the process.
  9501.  
  9502. According to the philosophy of organism, it is only by the introduction
  9503. of covert inconsistencies into the subjectivist principle, as here stated, that
  9504. there can be any escape from what Santayana calls, 'solipsism of the pres-
  9505. ent moment/ Thus Descartes' mode of escape is either illusory, or its
  9506. premises are incompletely stated. This covert introduction is always arising
  9507. because common sense is inflexibly objectivist. We perceive other things
  9508. which are in the world of actualities in the same sense as we are. Also our
  9509. emotions are directed towards other things, including of course our bodily
  9510. organs. These are our primary beliefs which philosophers proceed to
  9511. dissect.
  9512.  
  9513. Now philosophy has always proceeded on the sound principle that its
  9514. generalizations f must be based upon the primary elements in actual ex-
  9515. perience as starting-points. Greek philosophy had recourse to the common
  9516. forms of language to suggest its generalizations. It found the typical state-
  9517. ment, 'That stone is grey'; and it evolved the generalization that the actual
  9518. world can be conceived as a collection of primary substances qualified by
  9519. universal qualities. Of course, this was not the only generalization evolved:
  9520. Greek philosophy was subtle and multiform, also it was not inflexibly
  9521. consistent. But this general notion was always influencing thought, ex-
  9522. plicitly or implicitly.
  9523.  
  9524. A theory of knowledge was also needed. Again philosophy started on a
  9525. sound principle, that all knowledge is grounded on perception. Perception
  9526. was then analysed, and found to be the awareness that a universal quality
  9527. is qualifying a particular substance. Thus perception is the catching of a
  9528. universal quality in the act of qualifying a particular substance. It was
  9529. then asked, how the perceiver perceives; and the answer is,t by his organs
  9530. of sensation. Thus the universal qualities which qualify the perceived
  9531. substances are, in respect to the [24 1] perceiver, his private sensations re-
  9532.  
  9533.  
  9534.  
  9535. The Subjectivist Principle 159
  9536.  
  9537. ferred to particular substances other than himself. So far, the tradition of
  9538. philosophy includes, among other elements, a factor of extreme ob-
  9539. jectivism in metaphysics, whereby the subject-predicate form of proposition
  9540. is taken as expressing a fundamental metaphysical truth. Descartes modi-
  9541. fied traditional philosophy in two opposite ways. He increased the meta-
  9542. physical emphasis on the substance-quality forms of thought. The actual
  9543. things 'required nothing but themselves in order to exist/ and were to be
  9544. thought of in terms of their qualities, some of them essential attributes,
  9545. and others accidental modes. He also laid down the principle, that those
  9546. substances which are the subjects enjoying conscious experiences t provide
  9547. the primary data for philosophy, namely, themselves as in the enjoyment
  9548. of such experience. This is the famous subjectivist bias which entered into
  9549. modern philosophy through Descartes. In this doctrine Descartes undoubt-
  9550. edly made the greatest philosophical discovery since the age of Plato and
  9551. Aristotle. For his doctrine directly traversed the notion that the proposi-
  9552. tion, 'This stone is grey/ expresses a primary form of known fact from
  9553. which metaphysics can start its generalizations. If we are to go back to the
  9554. subjective enjoyment of experience, the type of primary starting-point is
  9555. 'my perception of this stone as grey.' Primitive men were not metaphysi-
  9556. cians, nor were they interested in the expression of concrete experience.
  9557. Their language merely expressed useful abstractions, such as 'greyness of
  9558. the stone/ But like Columbus who never visited America, Descartes missed
  9559. the full sweep of his own discovery, and he and his successors, Locke and
  9560. Hume, continued to construe the functionings of the subjective enjoyment
  9561. of experience according to the substance-quality categories. Yet if the
  9562. enjoyment of experience be the constitutive subjective fact, these cate-
  9563. gories have lost all claim to any fundamental character in metaphysics.
  9564. Hume — to proceed at once to the consistent exponent of the method-
  9565. looked for a [242] universal quality to function as qualifying the mind, by
  9566. way of explanation of its perceptive enjoyment. Now if we scan 'my per-
  9567. ception of this stone as grey' in order to find a universal, the only available
  9568. candidate is 'greyness/ Accordingly for Hume, 'greyness/ functioning as a
  9569. sensation qualifying the mind, is a fundamental type of fact for meta-
  9570. physical generalization. The result is Hume's simple impressions of sensa-
  9571. tion, which form the starting-point of his philosophy. But this is an entire
  9572. muddle, f for the perceiving mind is not grey, and so grey is now made to
  9573. perform a new role. From the original fact 'my perception of this stone as
  9574. grey/ Hume extracts 'Awareness of sensation of greyness'; and puts it
  9575. forward as the ultimate datum in this element of experience.
  9576.  
  9577. He has discarded the objective actuality of the stone-image in his search
  9578. for a universal quality: this 'objective actuality' is Descartes' 'realitas ob-
  9579. jective! \ Hume's search was undertaken in obedience to a metaphysical
  9580. principle which had lost all claim to validity, if the Cartesian discovery be
  9581. accepted. He is then content with 'sensation of greyness/ which is just as
  9582. much a particular as the original stone-image. He is aware of 'this sensa-
  9583.  
  9584.  
  9585.  
  9586. 160 Discussions and Applications
  9587.  
  9588. tion of greyness.' What he has done is to assert arbitrarily the 'subjectivism
  9589. and 'sensationalist' principles as applying to the datum for experience: the
  9590. notion 'this sensation of greyness' has no reference to any other actual
  9591. entity. Hume thus applies to the experiencing subject Descartes' principle,
  9592. that it requires no other actual entity in order to exist. The fact that fi-
  9593. nally Hume criticizes the Cartesian notion of mindt does not alter the
  9594. other fact that his antecedent arguments presuppose that notion.
  9595.  
  9596. It is to be noticed that Hume can only analyse the sensation in terms of
  9597. af universal and of its realization in the prehending mind. For example,
  9598. to take the first examples which in his Treatise he gives of such analysis, we
  9599. find 'red/ 'scarlet/ 'orange/ 'sweet/ 'bitter/ Thus Hume describes 'im-
  9600. pressions of sensation' in the exact terms in which the philosophy of or-
  9601. ganism describes con- [243] ceptual feelings. They are the particular feel-
  9602. ings of universals, and are not feelings of other particular existents ex-
  9603. emplifying universals. Hume admits this identification, and can find no
  9604. distinction except in 'force and vivacity/ He writes: "The first circum-
  9605. stance that strikes my eye, is the great resemblance between our impres-
  9606. sions and ideas in every particular except their degree of force and
  9607. vivacity/'*
  9608.  
  9609. In contrast to Hume, the philosophy of organism keeps 'this stone as
  9610. grey' in the datum for the experience in question. It is, in fact, the 'objec-
  9611. tive datum' of a certain physical feeling, belonging to a derivative type in
  9612. a late phase of a concrescence. But this doctrine fully accepts Descartes'
  9613. discovery that subjective experiencing is the primary metaphysical situa-
  9614. tion which is presented to metaphysics for analysis. This doctrine is the
  9615. 'reformed subjectivist principle,' t mentioned earlier in this chapter. Ac-
  9616. cordingly, the notion 'this stone as grey' is a derivative abstraction, neces-
  9617. sary indeed as an element in the description of the fundamental experien-
  9618. tial feeling, but delusive as a metaphysical starting-point. This derivative
  9619. abstraction is called an 'objectification/
  9620.  
  9621. The justification for this procedure is, first, common sense, and, sec-
  9622. ondly, the avoidance of the difficulties which have dogged the subjectivist
  9623. and sensationalist principles of modern philosophy. Descartes' discovery
  9624. on the side of subjectivism requires balancing by an 'objectivist' principle
  9625. as to the datum for experience. Also, with the advent of Cartesian subjec-
  9626. tivism, the substance-quality category has lost all claim to metaphysical
  9627. primacy; and, with this disposition of substance-quality, we can reject the
  9628. notion of individual substances, each with its private world of qualities
  9629. and sensations.
  9630.  
  9631. SECTION II
  9632.  
  9633. In the philosophy of organism knowledge is relegated to the intermedi-
  9634. ate phase of j>rocess. Cognizance belongs to the genus of subjective forms
  9635. which are admitted, or [244] not admitted, to the function of absorbing
  9636. the objective content into the subjectivity of satisfaction. Its 'importance'
  9637.  
  9638.  
  9639.  
  9640. The Subjectivist Principle 161
  9641.  
  9642. is therefore no necessary element in the concrete actual entity. In the case
  9643. of any one such entity, it may merely constitute an instance of what
  9644. Locke terms 'a capacity/ If we are considering the society of successive
  9645. actual occasions in the historic route forming the life of an enduring ob-
  9646. ject, some of the earlier actual occasions may be without knowledge, and
  9647. some of the later may possess knowledge. In such a case, the unknowing
  9648. man has become knowing. There is nothing surprising in this conclusion;
  9649. it happens daily for most of us, when we sleep at night and wake in the
  9650. morning. Every actual entity has the capacity for knowledge, and there is
  9651. graduation in the intensity of various items of knowledge; but, in gen-
  9652. eral, knowledge seems to be negligible apart from a peculiar complexity in
  9653. the constitution of some actual occasion.
  9654.  
  9655. We— as enduring objects with personal order— objectify the occasions of
  9656. our own past with peculiar completeness in our immediate present. We
  9657. find in those occasions, as known from our present standpoint, a surprising
  9658. variation in the range and intensity of our realized knowledge. We sleep;
  9659. we are half-awake; we are aware of our perceptions, but are devoid of
  9660. generalities in thought; we are vividly absorbed within a small region of
  9661. abstract though while oblivious to the world around; we are attending to
  9662. our emotions— some torrent of passion— to them and to nothing else; we
  9663. are morbidly discursive in the width of our attention; and finally we sink
  9664. back into temporary obliviousness, sleeping or stunned. Also we can re-
  9665. member factors experienced in our immediate past, which at the time we
  9666. failed to notice. When we survey the chequered history of our own capac-
  9667. ity for knowledge, does common sense allow us to believe that the opera-
  9668. tions of judgment, operations which require definition in terms of con-
  9669. scious apprehension, are those operations which are foundational in exist-
  9670. ence either as \245] an essential attribute for an actual entity, or as the
  9671. final culmination whereby unity of experience is attained?!
  9672.  
  9673. The general case x of conscious perception is the negative perception,
  9674. namely, 'perceiving this stone as not grey/ The 'grey' then has ingression
  9675. in its full character of a conceptual novelty, illustrating an alternative. In
  9676. the positive case, 'perceiving this stone as grey/ the grey has ingression in
  9677. its character of a possible novelty, but in fact by its conformity empha-
  9678. sizing the dative grey, blindly felt. Consciousness is the feeling of nega-
  9679. tion: in the perception of 'the stone as grey/ such feeling is in barest
  9680. germ; in the perception of 'the stone as not grey/ such feeling is int full
  9681. development. Thus the negative perception is the triumph of conscious-
  9682. ness. It finally rises to the peak of free imagination, in which the con-
  9683. ceptual novelties search through a universe in which they are not datively
  9684. exemplified.
  9685.  
  9686. Consciousness is the subjective form involved in feeling the contrast
  9687. between the 'theory' which may be erroneous and the fact which is 'given/
  9688. Thus consciousness involves the rise into importance of the contrast be-
  9689.  
  9690. 1 Cf. Part III, for the full account.
  9691.  
  9692.  
  9693.  
  9694. 162 Discussions and Applications
  9695.  
  9696. tween the eternal objects designated by the words 'any' and 'just that/
  9697. Conscious perception is ? therefore, the most primitive form of judgment.
  9698. The organic philosophy holds that consciousness only arises in a Jate
  9699. derivative phase of complex integrations. If an actual occasion be such
  9700. that phases of this sort are negligible in its concrescence, then in its ex-
  9701. perience there is no knowledge;! owing to the fact that consciousness is a
  9702. subjective form belonging to the later phases, the prehensions which it
  9703. directly irradiates are those of an 'impure' type. Consciousness only il-
  9704. luminates the more primitive types of prehension so far as these prehen-
  9705. sions are still elements in the products of integration. Thus those elements
  9706. of our experience which stand out clearly and distinctly in our conscious-
  9707. ness are not its basic facts; they are the derivative modifications which
  9708. arise in the process. For [246] example, consciousness only dimly illumi-
  9709. nates the prehensions in the mode of causal efficacy, because these pre-
  9710. hensions are primitive elements in our experience. But prehensions in the
  9711. mode of presentational immediacy are among those prehensions which we
  9712. enjoy with the most vivid consciousness. These prehensions are late
  9713. derivatives in the concrescence of an experient subject. The consequences
  9714. of the neglect of this law, that the late derivative elements are more clearly
  9715. illuminated by consciousness than the primitive elements, have been fatal
  9716. to the proper analysis of an experient occasion. In fact, most of the diffi-
  9717. culties of philosophy are produced by it. Experience has been explained in
  9718. a thoroughly topsy-turvy fashion, the wrong end first. In particular, emo-
  9719. tional and purposeful experience have been made to follow upon Hume's
  9720. impressions of sensation.
  9721.  
  9722. To sum up: (i) Consciousness is a subjective form arising in the higher
  9723. phases of concrescence, (ii) Consciousness primarily illuminates the higher
  9724. phase in which it arises, and only illuminates earlier phases derivatively, as
  9725. they remain components in the higher phase, (iii) It follows that the
  9726. order of dawning, clearly and distinctly, in consciousness is not the order
  9727. of metaphysical priority.
  9728.  
  9729. SECTION III
  9730.  
  9731. The primitive form of physical experience is emotional— blind emo-
  9732. tion—received as felt elsewhere in another occasion and conformally ap-
  9733. propriated as a subjective passion. In the language appropriate to the
  9734. higher stages of experience, the primitive element is sympathy, that is,
  9735. feeling the feeling in another and feeling conformally with another. We
  9736. are so used to considering the high abstraction, 'the stone as green/ that
  9737. we have difficulty in eliciting into consciousness the notion of 'green' as
  9738. the qualifying character of an emotion. Yet, the aesthetic feelings, whereby
  9739. there is pictorial art, are nothing else than products of the contrasts [247]
  9740. latent in a variety of colours qualifying emotion, contrasts which are made
  9741. possible by their patterned relevance to each other. The separation of the
  9742.  
  9743.  
  9744.  
  9745. The Sub jecti vist Principle 163
  9746.  
  9747. emotional experience from the presentational intuition is a high abstrac-
  9748. tion of thought. Thus the primitive experience is emotional feeling, f felt
  9749. in its relevance to a world beyond. The feeling is blind and the relevance
  9750. is vague. Also feeling, and reference to an exterior world, t pass into ap-
  9751. petition, which is the feeling of determinate relevance to a world about to
  9752. be. In the phraseology of physics, this primitive experience is 'vector
  9753. feeling/ that is to say, feeling from a beyond which is determinate and
  9754. pointing to a beyond which is to be determined. But the feeling is sub-
  9755. jectively rooted in the immediacy of the present occasion: it is what the
  9756. occasion feels for itself, as derived from the past and as merging into the
  9757. future. In this vector transmission of primitive feeling the primitive pro-
  9758. vision of width for contrast is secured by pulses of emotion, which in the
  9759. coordinate division of occasions (cf. Part IV) appear as wave-lengths and
  9760. vibrations. In any particular cosmic epoch, the order of nature has secured
  9761. the necessary differentiation of function, so as to avoid incompatibilities,
  9762. by shepherding the sensa characteristic of that epoch each into association
  9763. with a definite pulse. Thus the transmission of each sensum is associated
  9764. with its own wave-length. In physics, such transmission can be conceived
  9765. as corpuscular or undulatory, according to the special importance of par-
  9766. ticular features in the instance considered. The higher phases of experi-
  9767. ence increase the dimension of width, and elicit contrasts of higher types.
  9768. The clash of uncoordinated emotions in the lower categories isf avoided:
  9769. the aspect of inhibition and of transitory satisfaction is diminished. Ex-
  9770. perience realizes itself as an element in what is everlasting (cf. Part V, Ch.
  9771. II), and as embodying in itself the everlasting component of the universe.
  9772. This gain does not necessarily involve consciousness. Also it involves en-
  9773. hanced subjective emphasis. The occasion [248] has become less of a detail
  9774. and more of a totality, so far as its subjective experience is concerned. The
  9775. feeling of this width, with its enhancement of permanence, takes the form
  9776. of blind zest, which can become self-defeating by excess of subjective em-
  9777. phasis. The inhibitions of zest by lack of adequate width to combine the
  9778. contraries inherent in the environment lead to the destruction of the type
  9779. of order concerned. Every increase of sensitivity requires an evolution
  9780. towards adaptation. It must be remembered, however, that emotion in
  9781. human experience, or even in animal experience, is not bare emotion. It
  9782. is emotion interpreted, integrated, and transformed into higher categories
  9783. of feeling. But even so, the emotional appetitive elements in our conscious
  9784. experience are those which most closely resemble the basic elements of all
  9785. physical experience.
  9786.  
  9787. SECTION IV
  9788.  
  9789. The distinction between the various stages of concrescence consists in
  9790. the diverse modes of ingression of the eternal objects involved. The im-
  9791. manent decision, whereby there is a supervening of stages in an actual
  9792.  
  9793.  
  9794.  
  9795. 164 Discussions and Applications
  9796.  
  9797. entity, is always the determinant of a process of integration whereby com-
  9798. pletion is arrived at— at least, such 'formal' completion as is proper to a
  9799. single actual entity. This determination originates with conceptual pre-
  9800. hensions which enter into integration with the physical prehensions,!
  9801. modifying both the data and the subjective forms.
  9802.  
  9803. The limitation whereby there is a perspective relegation of eternal ob-
  9804. jects to the background is the characteristic of decision. Transcendent
  9805. decision includes God's decision. He is the actual entity in virtue of which
  9806. the entire multiplicity of eternal objects obtains its graded relevance to
  9807. each stage of concrescence. Apart from God, there could be no relevant
  9808. novelty. Whatever arises in actual entities from God's decision, arises first
  9809. conceptually, and is transmuted into the physical world (cf. Part III). In
  9810. 'transcendent decision' there is transi- [249] tion from the past to the im-
  9811. mediacy of the present; and in 'immanent decision' there is the process of
  9812. acquisition of subjective form and the integration of feelings. In this
  9813. process the creativity, universal throughout actuality, is characterized by
  9814. the datum from the past; and it meets this dead datum— universalized
  9815. into a character of creativity— by the vivifying novelty of subjective form
  9816. selected from the multiplicity of pure potentiality. In the process, the old
  9817. meets the new, and this meeting constitutes the satisfaction of an im-
  9818. mediate particular individual.
  9819.  
  9820. Eternal objects in any one of their modes of subjective ingrcssion are
  9821. then functioning in the guise of subjective novelty meeting the objective
  9822. datum from the past. This word 'feeling' is a mere technical term; but it
  9823. has been chosen to suggest that functioning through which the con-
  9824. crescent actuality appropriates the datum so as to make it its own. There
  9825. are three successive phases of feelings, namely, a phase of 'conformal'f
  9826. feelings, one of 'conceptual' feelings, and one of 'comparative' feelings,
  9827. including 'propositional' feelings in this last species. In the conformal
  9828. feelings the how of feeling reproduces what is felt. Some conformation is
  9829. necessary as a basis of vector transition, whereby the past is synthesized
  9830. with the present. The one eternal object in its two-way function, as a
  9831. determinant of the datum and as a determinant of the subjective form, is
  9832. thus relational. In this sense the solidarity of the universe is based on the
  9833. relational functioning of eternal objects. The two latter? phases can be
  9834. put together as the 'supplemental' phase.
  9835.  
  9836. An eternal object when it has ingression through its function of ob-
  9837. jectifying the actual world, so as to present the datum for prehension, is
  9838. functioning 'datively.' Hence, to sum up, there are four modes of func-
  9839. tioning whereby an eternal object has ingression into the constitution of
  9840. an actual entity: (i) as dative ingression, (ii) in conformal physical feeling,
  9841. (iii) in conceptual feeling, (iv) in comparative feeling.
  9842.  
  9843. \2S0] But the addition of diverse eternal objects is not of the essence of
  9844. 'supplementation': the essence consists in the adjustment of subjective
  9845. importance by functioning of subjective origin. The graduated emotional
  9846.  
  9847.  
  9848.  
  9849. The Subjectivist Principle 165
  9850.  
  9851. intensity of the subject is constituting itself by reference to the physical
  9852. data, datively there and conformally felt. All references to 'attention'
  9853. usually refer to such supplementation in which the addition of diverse
  9854. eternal objects is at a minimum; whereas references to 'emotion' usually
  9855. refer to such supplementation complicated by profuse addition of diverse
  9856. eternal objects. Supplementary feeling is emotional and purposeful, be-
  9857. cause it is what is felt by mere reason of the subjective appropriation of
  9858. the objective data. But it is of the essence of supplementary feeling that it
  9859. does not challenge its initial phase of conformal feeling by any reference to
  9860. incompatibility. The stages of the subjective ingression of eternal objects
  9861. involve essential compatibility. The process exhibits an inevitable con-
  9862. tinuity of functioning. Each stage carries in itself the promise of its suc-
  9863. cessor, and each succeeding stage carries in itself the antecedent out of
  9864. which it arose. For example, t the complexity of the datum carries in itself
  9865. the transition from the conformal feelings to supplementary feelings in
  9866. which contrasts, latent in the datum, achieve real unity between the com-
  9867. ponents. Thus components in the datum, which qua dative, are diverse,
  9868. become united in specific realized contrast. As elements in the datum, the
  9869. components are individually given, with the potentiality for a contrast,
  9870. which in the supplementary stage is either included or excluded. The con-
  9871. formal stage merely transforms the objective content into subjective feel-
  9872. ings. But the supplementary stage adds, or excludes, the realization of the
  9873. contrasts by which the original datum passes into its emotional unity.
  9874.  
  9875. This account enables us to conceive the stage of consciousness as a pro-
  9876. longation of the stage of supplementation. The concrescence is an in-
  9877. dividualization of the whole universe. Every eternal object, whether rele-
  9878. vant [25 J] or irrelevant to the datum, is still patient of its contrasts with
  9879. the datum. The process by which such contrasts are admitted or rejected
  9880. involves the stage of conceptual feeling; and consciousness is evidently
  9881. only a further exhibition of this stage of supplementary feeling. Concep-
  9882. tual feelings do not necessarily involve consciousness. This point is
  9883. elaborated in detail in Part III.
  9884.  
  9885. Again in this explanation, 'contrast' has appeared as the general case;
  9886. while 'identification' is a sub-species arising when one and the same
  9887. eternal object is contrasted in its two modes of functioning.
  9888.  
  9889. Thus the two latter stages of feeling are constituted by the realization of
  9890. specific modes of diversity and identity, the realization also involving an
  9891. adjustment of intensities of relevance. Mere diversity, and mere identity,
  9892. are generic terms. Two components in the constitution of an actual entity
  9893. are specifically diverse and specifically identical by reason of the definite
  9894. potential contrast involved in the diversity of the implicated eternal ob-
  9895. jects, and by reason of the definite self-identity of each eternal object. The
  9896. specific identity arising from the synthesis of diverse modes of functioning
  9897. of one eternal object is the 'individual essence' of that eternal object. But
  9898. the concrescence reaches the goal required by the Category of Objective
  9899.  
  9900.  
  9901.  
  9902. 166 Discussions and Applications
  9903.  
  9904. Unity, that in any subject one entity can only be felt once. Nothing can be
  9905. duplicated. The many potentialities for one entity must be synthesizedt
  9906. into one fact. Hence arise the incompatibilities productive of elimination.
  9907.  
  9908. Properly speaking, modes of functioning are compared, thereby evoking
  9909. specific contrasts and specific identifications. The two latter stages of feel-
  9910. ing are the stages of comparison; these stages involve comparisons, and
  9911. comparisons of comparisons; and the admission, or exclusion, of an in-
  9912. definite complexity of potentialities for comparison, in ascending grades.
  9913.  
  9914. The ultimate attainment is 'satisfaction/ This is the final characteriza-
  9915. tion of the unity of feeling of the one [252] actual entity, the 'superject'
  9916. which is familiarly termed the 'subject/ In a sense this satisfaction is two-
  9917. dimensional. It has a dimension of narrowness, and a dimension of width.
  9918. The dimension of narrowness refers to the intensities of individual emo-
  9919. tions arising out of individual components in the datum. In this dimen-
  9920. sion, the higher levels of coordination are irrelevant. The dimension of
  9921. width arises out of the higher levels of coordination, by which the in-
  9922. tensities in the dimension of narrowness become subordinated to a co-
  9923. ordination which depends upon the higher levels of comparison. The
  9924. savouring of the complexity of the universe can enter into satisfaction
  9925. only through the dimension of width. The emotional depths at the low
  9926. levels have their limits: the function of width is to deepen the ocean of
  9927. feeling, and to remove the diminutions of depth produced by the inter-
  9928. ference of diverse emotions uncoordinated at a higher level. In the place
  9929. of the Hegelian hierarchy of categories of thought, the philosophy of
  9930. organism finds a hierarchy of categories of feeling.
  9931.  
  9932. SECTION V
  9933.  
  9934. The reformed subjectivist principle adopted by the philosophy of or-
  9935. ganism is merely an alternative statement of the principle of relativity (the
  9936. fourth Category of Explanation). This principle states that it belongs to
  9937. the nature of a 'being that it is a potential for every 'becoming/ Thus all
  9938. things are to be conceived as qualifications of actual occasions. According
  9939. to the ninth Category of Explanation, how an actual entity becomes con-
  9940. stitutes what that actual entity is. This principle states that the being of a
  9941. res vera is constituted by its 'becoming/ The way in which one actual
  9942. entity is qualified by other actual entities is the 'experience' of the actual
  9943. world enjoyed by that actual entity, as subject. The subjectivist principle**
  9944. is that the whole universe consists of elements disclosed in the analysis of
  9945. the experiences of subjects. Process is the becoming of experience. [253] It
  9946. follows that the philosophy of organism entirely accepts the subjectivist
  9947. bias of modern philosophy. It also accepts Hume's doctrine that nothing
  9948. is to be received into the philosophical scheme which is not discoverable
  9949. as an element in subjective experience. This is the ontological principle.
  9950. Thus Hume's demand that causation be describable as an element in ex-
  9951.  
  9952.  
  9953.  
  9954. The Subjectivist Principle 167
  9955.  
  9956. perience is, on these principles, entirely justifiable. The point of the crit-
  9957. icisms of Hume's procedure is that we have direct intuition of inheritance
  9958. and memory: thus the only problem is, so to describe the general character
  9959. of experience that these intuitions may be included. It is here that Hume
  9960. fails. Also those modern empiricists who substitute law' for 'causation'
  9961. fail even worse than Hume. For 'law' no more satisfies Hume's tests than
  9962. does 'causation/ There is no 'impression' of law, or of lawfulness. Even
  9963. allowing memory, according to Humian principles what has happened in
  9964. experience has happened in experience, and that is all that can be said.
  9965. Everything else is bluff, combined with the fraudulent insertion of 'prob-
  9966. ability' into a conclusion which demands 'blank ignorance.'
  9967.  
  9968. The difficulties of all schools of modern philosophy lie in the fact that,
  9969. having accepted the subjectivist principle,** they continue to use philosoph-
  9970. ical categories derived from another point of view. These categories are not
  9971. wrong, but they deal with abstractions unsuitable for metaphysical use.
  9972. It is for this reason that the notions of the 'extensive continuum' and of
  9973. 'presentational t immediacy' require such careful discussion from every
  9974. point of view. The notions of the 'green leaf and of the 'round ball' are
  9975. at the base of traditional metaphysics. They have generated two miscon-
  9976. ceptions: one is the concept of vacuous actuality, void of subjective ex-
  9977. perience; and the other is the concept of quality inherent in substance.
  9978. In their proper character, as high abstractions, both of these notions are of
  9979. the utmost pragmatic use. In fact, language has been formed chiefly to
  9980. express such con- \2S4) cepts. It is for this reason that language, in its
  9981. ordinary usages, penetrates but a short distance into the principles of
  9982. metaphysics. Finally, the reformed subjectivist principle must be repeated:
  9983. that apart from the experiences of subjects there is nothing, nothing,
  9984. nothing, bare nothingness.
  9985.  
  9986. It is now evident that the final analogy to philosophies of the Hegelian
  9987. school, noted in the Preface, is not accidental. The universe is at once the
  9988. multiplicity of res verae] and the solidarity of res verae. The solidarity is
  9989. itself the efficiency of the macroscopic res vera, embodying the principle
  9990. of unbounded permanence acquiring novelty through flux. The multiplicity
  9991. is composed of microscopic res verae, each embodying the principle of
  9992. bounded flux acquiring 'everlasting' permanence. On one side, the one
  9993. becomes many; and on the other side, the many become one. But what
  9994. becomes is always a res vera, and the concrescence t of a res vera is the
  9995. development of a subjective aim. This development is nothing else than
  9996. the Hegelian development of an idea. The elaboration of this aspect of
  9997. the philosophy of organism, with the purpose of obtaining an interpre-
  9998. tation of the religious experience of mankind, is undertaken in Part V of
  9999. these lectures.
  10000.  
  10001. Cosmological story, in every part and in every chapter, relates the inter-
  10002. play of the static vision and the dynamic history. But the whole story is
  10003. comprised within the account of the subjective concrescence of res verae.
  10004.  
  10005.  
  10006.  
  10007. CHAPTER VIII
  10008. SYMBOLIC REFERENCE
  10009.  
  10010. SECTION I
  10011.  
  10012. [255] The pure mode of presentational immediacy gives no information
  10013. as to the past or the future. It merely presents an illustrated portion of
  10014. the presented duration. It thereby defines a cross-section of the universe:
  10015. hut does not in itself define on which side lies the past, and on which
  10016. side the future. In order to solve such questions we now come to the
  10017. interplay between the two pure modes. This mixed mode of perception is
  10018. here named 'symbolic reference/ The failure to lay due emphasis on
  10019. symbolic reference is one of the reasons for metaphysical difficulties; it has
  10020. reduced the notion of 'meaning' to a mystery.
  10021.  
  10022. The first principle, explanatory of symbolic reference, is that for such
  10023. reference a 'common ground' is required. By this necessity for a 'common
  10024. ground' it is meant that there must be components in experience which
  10025. are directly recognized as identical in each of the pure perceptive modes.
  10026. In the transition to a higher phase of experience, there is a concrescence in
  10027. which prehensions in the two modes are brought into a unity of feeling:
  10028. this concrescent unity arises from a congruity of their subjective forms in
  10029. virtue of the identity relation between the two prehensions, owing to some
  10030. components in common. Thus the symbolic reference belongs to one of
  10031. the later originative phases of experience. These later phases are dis-
  10032. tinguished by their new element of originative freedom. Accordingly,
  10033. while the two pure perceptive modes are incapable of error, symbolic
  10034. reference introduces this possibility. When human experience is in ques-
  10035. tion, 'per- \256] ception' almost always means 'perception in the mixed
  10036. mode of symbolic reference/ Thus, in general, human perception is sub-
  10037. ject to error, because, in respect to those components most clearly in
  10038. consciousness, it is interpretative. In fact, error is the mark of the higher
  10039. organisms, and is the schoolmaster by whose agency there is upward
  10040. evolution. For example, the evolutionary use of intelligence is that it
  10041. enables the individual to profit by error without being slaughtered
  10042. by it. But at present, we are not considering conceptual or intellectual
  10043. functioning.
  10044.  
  10045. One main element of common ground, shared between the two pure
  10046. modes, is the presented locus. This locus enters subordinately into the
  10047. perceptive mode of causal efficacy, vaguely exemplifying its participation
  10048. in the general scheme of extensive interconnection, involved in the real
  10049.  
  10050. 168
  10051.  
  10052.  
  10053.  
  10054. Symbolic Reference 169
  10055.  
  10056. potentiality. It is not disclosed by that perceptive mode in any other way;
  10057. at least it is not directly disclosed. The further disclosure must be in-
  10058. direct, since contemporary events are exactly those which are neither
  10059. causing, nor caused by, the percipient actual occasion. Now, although the
  10060. various causal pasts (i.e., 'actual worlds') of the contemporary actual occa-
  10061. sions are not wholly identical with the causal past of the percipient actual
  10062. occasion, yet, so far as important relevance is concerned, these causal pasts
  10063. are practically identical. Thus there is, in the mode of causal efficacy, a
  10064. direct perception of those antecedent actual occasions which are causally
  10065. efficacious both for the percipient and for the relevant events in the pre-
  10066. sented locus. The percipient therefore, under the limitation of its own
  10067. perspective, prehends the causal influences to which the presented locus in
  10068. its important regions is subjected. This amounts to an indirect perception
  10069. of this locus, a perception in which the direct components belong to the
  10070. pure mode of causal efficacy. If we now turn to the perceptive mode of
  10071. presentational immediacy, the regions, perceived by direct and indirect
  10072. knowledge respectively, are inverted in comparison with the other mode.
  10073. The presented locus is directly illus- [257] trated by the sensa; while the
  10074. causal past, the causal future, and the other contemporary events, are only
  10075. indirectly perceived by means of their extensive relations to the presented
  10076. locus. It must be remembered that the presented locus has its fourth
  10077. dimension of temporal thickness 'spatialized' as the specious present of
  10078. the percipient. Thus the presented locus, with the animal body of the
  10079. percipient as the region from which perspectives are focussed, is the re-
  10080. gional origin by reference to which in this perceptive mode the complete
  10081. scheme of extensive regions is rendered determinate. The respective roles
  10082. of the two perceptive modes in experience are aptly exemplified by the
  10083. fact that all scientific observations, such as measurements, determinations
  10084. of relative spatial position, determinations of sense-data such as colours,
  10085. sounds, tastes, smells, temperature feelings, touch feelings, etc., are made
  10086. in the perceptive mode of presentational immediacy: and that great care is
  10087. exerted to keep this mode pure, that is to say, devoid of symbolic reference
  10088. to causal efficacy. In this way accuracy is secured, in the sense that the
  10089. direct observation is purged of all interpretation. On the other hand all
  10090. scientific theory is stated in terms referring exclusively to the scheme of
  10091. relatedness, which, so far as it is observed, involves the percepta in the
  10092. pure mode of causal efficacy. It thus stands out at once, that what we
  10093. want to know about, from the point of view either of curiosity or of tech-
  10094. nology, chiefly resides in those aspects of the world disclosed in causal
  10095. efficacy: but that what we can distinctly register is chiefly to be found
  10096. among the percepta in the mode of presentational immediacy.
  10097.  
  10098. The presented locus is a common ground for the symbolic reference,
  10099. because it is directly and distinctly perceived in presentational immediacy,
  10100. and is indistinctly and indirectly perceived in causal efficacy. In the latter
  10101. mode, the indistinctness is such that the detailed geometrical relationships
  10102.  
  10103.  
  10104.  
  10105. 170 Discussions and Applications
  10106.  
  10107. are, for the most part, incurably vague. Particular regions are, in this per-
  10108. ceptive mode, [258] in general not distinguishable. In this respect, causal
  10109. efficacy stands in contrast to presentational immediacy with its direct
  10110. illustration of certain distinct regions.
  10111.  
  10112. But there are exceptions to this geometrical indistinctness of causal
  10113. efficacy. In the first place, the separation of the potential extensive scheme
  10114. into past and future lies with the mode of causal efficacy and not with that
  10115. of presentational immediacy. The mathematical measurements, derivable
  10116. from the latter, are indifferent to this distinction; whereas the physical
  10117. theory, expressed in terms of the former, is wholly concerned with it. In
  10118. the next place, the animal body of the percipient is a region for which
  10119. causal efficacy acquires some accuracy in its distinction of regions—not all
  10120. the distinctness of the other mode, but sufficient to allow of important
  10121. identifications. For example, we see with our eyes, we taste with our
  10122. palates, we touch with our hands, etc.: here the causal efficacy defines
  10123. regions which are identified with themselves as perceived with greater
  10124. distinctness by the other mode. To take one example, the slight eye-strain
  10125. in the act of sight is an instance of regional definition by presentational
  10126. immediacy. But in itself it is no more to be correlated with projected sight
  10127. than is a contemporary stomach-ache, or a throb in the foot. The obvious
  10128. correlation of the eye-strain with sight arises from the perception, in the
  10129. other mode, of the eye as efficacious in sight. This correlation takes place
  10130. in virtue of the identity of the two regions, the region of the eye-strain, and
  10131. the region of eye-efficacy. But the eye-strain is so immeasurably the su-
  10132. perior in its power of regional definition that, as usual, we depend upon
  10133. it for explicit geometrical correlations with other parts of the body. In
  10134. this way, the animal body is the great central ground underlying all sym-
  10135. bolic reference. In respect to bodily perceptions the two modes achieve the
  10136. maximum of symbolic reference, and pool their feelings referent to identi-
  10137. cal regions. Every statement about the geometrical relationships of physi-
  10138. cal bodies in the world is ultimately [259] referable to certain definite
  10139. human bodies as origins of reference. A traveller, who has lost his way,
  10140. should not ask, Where am I? What he really wants to know is, Where are
  10141. the other places? He has got his own body, but he has lost them.
  10142.  
  10143.  
  10144.  
  10145. SECTION II
  10146.  
  10147. The second 'ground' for symbolic reference is the connection between
  10148. the two modes effected by the identity of an eternal object ingredient in
  10149. both of them. It will be remembered that the former 'ground' was the
  10150. identity of the extensive region throughout such stages of direct percep-
  10151. tion and synthesis, when there was a diversity of eternal objects, for ex-
  10152. ample, eye-region, visual sensa, eye-strain. But now we pass to a diversity of
  10153. regions combined with an identity of the eternal object, for example, visual
  10154. sensa given by efficacy of eye-region, and the region of the stone perceived
  10155.  
  10156.  
  10157.  
  10158. Symbolic Reference 171
  10159.  
  10160. in the mode of presentational immediacy under the illustration of the
  10161. same visual sensa.t In this connection the 'make-believe' character of mod-
  10162. ern empiricism is well shown by putting into juxtaposition f two widely
  10163. separated passages x from Hume's Treatise: "Impressions may be divided
  10164. into two kinds, those of sensation, and those of reflection. The first kind
  10165. arises in the soul originally, from unknown causes. 7 ' And "If it be per-
  10166. ceived by the eyes, it must be a colour; . . ."
  10167.  
  10168. The earlier passage is Hume's make-believe, when he is thinking of his
  10169. philosophical principles. He then refers the visual sensations 'in the soul'
  10170. to 'unknown causes.' But in the second passage, the heat of argument
  10171. elicits his real conviction— everybody's real conviction— that visual sensa-
  10172. tions arise 'by the eyes.' The causes are not a bit 'unknown,' and among
  10173. them there is usually to be found the efficacy of the eyes. If Hume had
  10174. stopped to investigate the alternative causes for the occurrence of visual
  10175. sensations— for example, eye-sight, or excessive consumption of alcohol-
  10176. he might have hesitated in his [260] profession of ignorance. If the causes
  10177. be indeed unknown, it is absurd to bother about eye-sight and intoxica-
  10178. tion. The reason for the existence of oculists and prohibitionists is that
  10179. various causes are known.
  10180.  
  10181. We can now complete our account of presentational immediacy. In this
  10182. perceptive mode the sensa are 'given' for the percipient, but this donation
  10183. is not to be ascribed to the spatial object which is thereby presented, the
  10184. stone, for example. Now it is a primary doctrine that what is 'given' is
  10185. given by reason of objectifications of actual entities from the settled past.
  10186. We therefore seek for the actual occasions to whose objectifications this
  10187. donation is to be ascribed. In this procedure we are only agreeing with the
  10188. spirit of Descartes' fifty-second principle (Part I): "For this reason, when
  10189. we perceive any attribute, we therefore conclude that some existing thing
  10190. or substance to which it may be attributed, is necessarily present." Com-
  10191. mon sense, physical theory, and physiological theory, combine to point out
  10192. a historic route of inheritance, from actual occasion to succeeding actual
  10193. occasion, first physically in the external environment, then physiologi-
  10194. cally—through the eyes in the case of visual data— up the nerves, into the
  10195. brain. The donation— taking sight as an example— is not confined to defi-
  10196. nite sensa, such as shades of colour: it also includes geometrical relation-
  10197. ships to the general environment. In this chain of inheritances, the eye is
  10198. picked out to rise into perceptive prominence, because another historic
  10199. route of physiological inheritance starts from it, whereby a later occa-
  10200. sion (almost identical with the earlier) is illustrated by the sensum 'eye-
  10201. strain' in the mode of presentational immediacy; but this eye-strain is an-
  10202. other allied story. In the visual datum for the percipient there are first these
  10203. components of colour-sensa combined with geometrical relationships to
  10204. the external world of the settled past: secondly, there are also in the datum
  10205. the general geometrical relationships forming the completion of this po-
  10206. tential scheme into the contemporary world, and into [261] the future.
  10207.  
  10208. 1 Book I, Part I, Sects. II and VI (italics mine).*
  10209.  
  10210.  
  10211.  
  10212. 1 72 Discussions and Applications
  10213.  
  10214. The responsive phase absorbs these data as material for a subjective unity
  10215. of feeling: the supplemental stage heightens the relevance of the colour-
  10216. sensa, and supplements the geometrical relationships of the past by picking
  10217. out the contemporary region of the stone to be the contemporary repre-
  10218. sentative of the efficacious historic routes. There then results in the mode
  10219. of presentational immediacy, the perception of the region illustrated by the
  10220. sensum termed 'grey/ The term 'stone' is primarily applied to a certain
  10221. historic route in the past, which is an efficacious element in this train of
  10222. circumstance. It is only properly applied to the contemporary region il-
  10223. lustrated by 'grey' on the assumption that this contemporary region is the
  10224. prolongation, of that historic route, into the presented locus. This assump-
  10225. tion may, or may not, be true. Further, the illustration of the contemporary
  10226. region of *grey ? may be due to quite other efficacious historic routes— for
  10227. example, to lighting effects arranged by theatrical producers— and in such
  10228. a case, the term 'stone' may suggest an even more violent error than in the
  10229. former example. What is directly perceived, certainly and without shadow
  10230. of doubt, is a grey region of the presented locus. Any further interpretation,
  10231. instinctive or by intellectual judgment, must be put down to symbolic
  10232. reference.
  10233.  
  10234. This account makes it plain that the perceptive mode of presentational
  10235. immediacy arises in the later, originative, integrative phases of the process
  10236. of concrescence. The perceptive mode of causal efficacy is to be traced to
  10237. the constitution of the datum by reason of which there is a concrete per-
  10238. cipient entity. Thus we must assign the mode of causal efficacy to the
  10239. fundamental constitution of an occasion so that in germ this mode be-
  10240. longs even to organisms of the lowest grade; while the mode of presenta-
  10241. tional immediacy requires the more sophistical activity of the later stages
  10242. of process, so as to belong only to organisms of a relatively high grade. So
  10243. far as we can judge, such high-grade organisms are relatively few, in [262]
  10244. comparison with the whole number of organisms in our immediate en-
  10245. vironment. Presentational immediacy is an outgrowth from the complex
  10246. datum implanted by causal efficacy. But, by the originative power of the
  10247. supplemental phase, what was vague, ill defined, and hardly relevant in
  10248. causal efficacy, becomes distinct, well defined, and importantly relevant in
  10249. presentational immediacy. In the responsive phase, the grey colour, t and
  10250. the geometrical relations between the efficacious, bodily routes and the
  10251. contemporary occasions, were subjective sensationst associated with barely
  10252. relevant geometrical relations: they represented the vivid sensational qual-
  10253. ities in the enjoyment of which the percipient subject barely distinguished
  10254. vague indirect relationships to the external world. The supplemental phase
  10255. lifts the presented duration into vivid distinctness, so that the vague effi-
  10256. cacy of the indistinct external world in the immediate past is precipitated
  10257. upon the representative regions in the contemporary present. In the usual
  10258. language, the sensations are projected. This phraseology is unfortunate;
  10259. for there never were sensations apart from these geometrical relations.
  10260.  
  10261.  
  10262.  
  10263. Symbolic Reference 173
  10264.  
  10265. Presentational immediacy is the enhancement of the importance of rela-
  10266. tionships which were already in the datum, vaguely and with slight rele-
  10267. vance. This fact, that presentational immediacy' deals with the same
  10268. datum as does 'causal efficacy/ gives the ultimate reason why there is a
  10269. common 'ground' for 'symbolic reference/ The two modes express the
  10270. same datum under different proportions of relevance. The two genetic-
  10271. processes involving presentational immediacy must be carefully distin-
  10272. guished. There is first the complex genetic process in which presentational
  10273. immediacy originates. This process extends downwards even to occasions
  10274. which belong to the historic routes of certain types of inorganic enduring
  10275. objects, namely, to those enduring objects whose aggregates form the
  10276. subject-matter of the science of Newtonian dynamics. t Secondly, prehen-
  10277. sions in the mode of presentational immediacy are involved as components
  10278. in [263] integration with other prehensions which are usually, though not
  10279. always, f in other modes. These integrations often involve various types of
  10280. 'symbolic reference/ This symbolic reference is the interpretativet element
  10281. in human experience. Language almost exclusively refers to presentational
  10282. immediacy as interpreted by symbolic reference. For example, we say that
  10283. 'we see the stone 7 where stone is an interpretation of stone-image: also
  10284. we say that 'we see the stone-image with our eyes'; this is an interpreta-
  10285. tion arising from the complex integration of (i) the causal efficacy of the
  10286. antecedent eye in the vision, (ii) the presentational immediacy of the
  10287. stone-image, (iii) the presentational immediacy of the eye-strain. When
  10288. we say that 'we see the stone with our eyes/ the interpretations of these
  10289. two examples are combined.
  10290.  
  10291. SECTION III
  10292.  
  10293. The discussion of the problem constituted by the connection between
  10294. causation and perception t has been conducted by the various schools of
  10295. thought derived from Hume and Kant under the misapprehension gen-
  10296. erated by an inversion of the true constitution of experience. The inversion
  10297. was explicit in the writings of Hume and of Kant: for both of them presen-
  10298. tational immediacy was the primary fact of perception, and any apprehen-
  10299. sion of causation was, somehow or other, to be .elicited from this primary
  10300. fact. This view of the relation between causation and perception, as items
  10301. in experience, was not original to these great philosophers. It is to be found
  10302. presupposed in Locke and Descartes; and they derived it from mediaeval
  10303. predecessors. But the modern critical movement in philosophy arose when
  10304. Hume and Kant emphasized the fundamental, inescapable, importance
  10305. which this doctrine possesses for any philosophy admitting its truth. The
  10306. philosophy of organism does not admit its truth, and thus rejects the
  10307. touchstone which is the neolithic weapon of 'criticaF philosophy. It must
  10308. be remembered that clearness in consciousness is no evidence \264] for
  10309. primitiveness in the genetic process: the opposite doctrine is more nearly
  10310. true.
  10311.  
  10312.  
  10313.  
  10314. 174 Discussions and Applications
  10315.  
  10316. Owing to its long dominance, it has been usual to assume as an obvious
  10317. fact the primacy of presentational immediacy. We open our eyes and our
  10318. other sense-organs; we then survey the contemporary world decorated with
  10319. sights, and sounds, and tastes; and then, by the sole aid of this information
  10320. about the contemporary world, thus decorated, we draw what conclusions
  10321. we can as to the actual world. No philosopher really holds that this is the
  10322. sole source of information: Hume and his followers appeal vaguely to
  10323. 'memory' and to 'practice/ in order to supplement their direct information;
  10324. and Kant wrote other Critiques^ in order to supplement his Critique of
  10325. Pure Reason. But the general procedure of modern philosophical 'criticism'
  10326. is to tie down opponents strictly to the front door of presentational im-
  10327. mediacy as the sole source of information, while one's own philosophy
  10328. makes its escape by a back door veiled under the ordinary usages of
  10329. language.
  10330.  
  10331. If this 'Humian' doctrine be true, certain conclusions as to 'behaviour't
  10332. ought to follow— conclusions which, in the most striking way, are not
  10333. verified. It is almost indecent to draw the attention of philosophers to the
  10334. minor transactions of daily life, away from the classic sources of philo-
  10335. sophic knowledge; but, after all, it is the empiricists who began this appeal
  10336. to Caesar.
  10337.  
  10338. According to Hume, our behaviour presupposing causation is due to the
  10339. repetition of associated presentational experiences. Thus the vivid present-
  10340. ment of the antecedent percepts should vividly generate the behaviour,
  10341. in action or thought, towards the associated consequent. The clear, dis-
  10342. tinct, overwhelming perception of the one is the overwhelming reason
  10343. for the subjective transition to the other. For behaviour, interpretable as
  10344. implying causation, is on this theory the subjective response to presenta-
  10345. tional immediacy. According to Hume this subjective response is the be-
  10346. ginning and the end of all that [26S] there is to be said about causation.
  10347. In Hume's theory the response is response to presentational immediacy,
  10348. and to nothing else. Also the situation elicited in response is nothing but
  10349. an immediate presentation, or the memory of one. Let us apply this ex-
  10350. planation to reflex action: In the dark, the electric light is suddenly turned
  10351. on and the man's eyes blink. There is a simple physiological explanation
  10352. of this trifling incident.
  10353.  
  10354. But this physiological explanation is couched wholly in terms of causal
  10355. efficacy: it is the conjectural record of the travel of a spasm of excitement
  10356. along nerves to some nodal centre, and of the return spasm of contraction
  10357. back to the eyelids. The correct technical phraseology would not alter the
  10358. fact that the explanation does not involve any appeal to presentational
  10359. immediacy either for actual occasions resident in the nerves, or for the
  10360. man. At the most there is a tacit supposition as to what a physiologist,
  10361. who in fact was not there, might have seen if he had been there, and if
  10362. he could have vivisected the man without affecting these occurrences, and
  10363. if he could have observed with a microscope which also in fact was absent.
  10364.  
  10365.  
  10366.  
  10367. Symbolic Reference 175
  10368.  
  10369. Thus the physiological explanation remains, from the point of view of
  10370. Hume's philosophy, a tissue of irrelevancies. It presupposes a side of the
  10371. universe about which, on Hume's theory, we must remain in blank ig-
  10372. norance.
  10373.  
  10374. Let us now dismiss physiology and turn to the private experience of the
  10375. blinking man. The sequence of percepts, in the mode of presentational
  10376. immediacy, ist flash of light, feeling of eye-closure, instant of darkness.
  10377. The three are practically simultaneous; though the flash maintains its
  10378. priority over the other two, and these two latter percepts are indistinguish-
  10379. able as to priority. According to the philosophy of organism, the man also
  10380. experiences another percept in the mode of causal efficacy. He feels that
  10381. the experiences of the eye in the matter of the flash are causal of the blink.
  10382. The man himself will have no doubt of it. In fact, it is the feeling [266] of
  10383. causality which enables the man to distinguish the priority of the flash;
  10384. and the inversion of the argument, whereby the temporal sequence 'flash
  10385. to blink' is made the premise for the 'causality' belief, has its origin in
  10386. pure theory. The man will explain his experience by saying, "The flash
  10387. made me blink'; and if his statement be doubted, he will reply, 'I know
  10388. it, because I felt it.'
  10389.  
  10390. The philosophy of organism accepts the man's statement, that the flash
  10391. made him blink. But Hume intervenes with another explanation. He first
  10392. points out that in the mode of presentational immediacy there is no per-
  10393. cept of the flash making the man blink. In this mode there are merely
  10394. the two percepts— the flash and the blink— combining the two latter of
  10395. the three percepts under the one term 'blink.' Hume refuses to admit the
  10396. man's protestation, that the compulsion to blink is just what he did feel.
  10397. The refusal is based on the dogma t that all percepts are in the mode of
  10398. presentational immediacy— a dogma not to be upset by a mere appeal to
  10399. direct experience. Besides,! Hume has another interpretation of the man's
  10400. experience: what the man really felt was his habit of blinking after flashes.
  10401. The word 'association' explains it all, according to Hume. But how can a
  10402. 'habit' be felt, when a 'cause' cannot be felt? Is there any presentational
  10403. immediacy in the feeling of a 'habit'? Hume by a sleight of hand confuses
  10404. a 'habit of feeling blinks after flashes' with a 'feeling of the habit of feel-
  10405. ing blinks after flashes/
  10406.  
  10407. We have here a perfect example of the practice of applying the test of
  10408. presentational immediacy to procure the critical rejection of some doc-
  10409. trines, and of allowing other doctrines to slip out by a back door, so as
  10410. to evade the test. The notion of causation arose because mankind lives
  10411. amid experiences in the mode of causal efficacy.
  10412.  
  10413. SECTION IV
  10414.  
  10415. We will keep to the appeal to ordinary experience, and \267] consider
  10416. another situation, which Hume's philosophy is ill equipped to explain.
  10417.  
  10418.  
  10419.  
  10420. 176 Discussions and Applications
  10421.  
  10422. The 'causal feeling' according to that doctrine arises from the long asso-
  10423. ciation of well-marked presentations of sensa, one precedent to the other.
  10424. It would seem therefore that inhibitions of sensa, given in presentational
  10425. immediacy, should be accompanied by a corresponding absence of 'causal
  10426. feeling'; for the explanation of how there is 'causal feeling' presupposes
  10427. the well-marked familiar sensa, in presentational immediacy. Unfortu-
  10428. nately the contrary is the case. An inhibition of familiar sensa is very apt
  10429. to leave us a prey to vague terrors respecting a circumambient world of
  10430. causal operations. In the dark there are vague presences, doubtfully feared:
  10431. in the silence, the irresistible causal efficacy of nature presses itself upon
  10432. us; in the vagueness of the low hum of insects in an August woodland, the
  10433. inflow into ourselves of feelings from enveloping nature overwhelms us;
  10434. in the dim consciousness of half-sleep, the presentations of sense fade
  10435. away, and we are left with the vague feeling of influences from vague
  10436. things around us. It is quite untrue that the feelings of various types of
  10437. influences are dependent upon the familiarity of well-marked sensa in
  10438. immediate presentment. Every way of omitting the sensa still leaves us a
  10439. prey to vague feelings of influence. Such feelings, divorced from immediate
  10440. sensa, are pleasant, or unpleasant, according to mood; but they are always
  10441. vague as to spatial and temporal definition, though their explicit domi-
  10442. nance in experience may be heightened in the absence of sensa.
  10443.  
  10444. Further, our experiences! of our various bodily parts are primarily per-
  10445. ceptions of them as reasons for 'projected' sensa : the hand] is the reason
  10446. for the projected touch-sensum, the eye is the reason for the projected
  10447. sight-sensum. Our bodily experience is primarily an experience of the de-
  10448. pendence of presentational immediacy upon causal efficacy. Hume's doc-
  10449. trine inverts this relationship by making causal efficacy, as an experience,
  10450. dependent upon presentational immediacy. This doc- [268] trine, whatever
  10451. be its merits, is not based upon any appeal to experience.
  10452.  
  10453. Bodily experiences, in the mode of causal efficacy, are distinguished by
  10454. their comparative accuracy of spatial definition. The causal influences from
  10455. the body have lost the extreme vagueness of those which inflow from the
  10456. external world. But, even for the body, causal efficacy is dogged with
  10457. vagueness compared to presentational immediacy. These conclusions are
  10458. confirmed if we descend* the scale of organic being. It does not seem
  10459. to be the sense of causal awareness that the lower living things lack, so
  10460. much as variety of sense-presentation, and then vivid distinctness of presen-
  10461. tational immediacy. But animals, and even vegetables, in low forms of
  10462. organism exhibit modes of behaviour directed towards self-preservation.
  10463. There is every indication of a vague feeling of causal relationship with
  10464. the external world, of some intensity, vaguely defined as to quality, and
  10465. with some vague definition as to locality. A jellyfish advances and with-
  10466. draws, and in so doing exhibits some perception of causal relationship with
  10467. the world beyond itself; a plant grows downwards to the damp earth, and
  10468. upwards towards the light. There is thus some direct reason for attributing
  10469.  
  10470.  
  10471.  
  10472. Symbolic Reference 177
  10473.  
  10474. dim, slow feelings of causal nexus, although we have no reason for any
  10475. ascription of the definite percepts in the mode of presentational im-
  10476. mediacy.
  10477.  
  10478. But the philosophy of organism attributes 'feeling' throughout the ac-
  10479. tual world. It bases this doctrine upon the directly observed fact that
  10480. 'feeling' survives as a known element constitutive of the 'formal' existence
  10481. of such actual entities as we can best observe. Also when we observe the
  10482. causal nexus, devoid of interplay with sense-presentation, the influx of
  10483. feeling with vague qualitative and 'vector' definition t is what we find. The
  10484. dominance of the scalar physical quantity, inertia, in the Newtonian
  10485. physics obscured the recognition of the truth that all fundamental phys-
  10486. ical quantities are vector and not scalar.
  10487.  
  10488. [269] When we pass to inorganic actual occasions, we have lost the two
  10489. higher originative phases in the 'process,' namely, the 'supplemental' phase,
  10490. and the 'mental' phase. They are lost in the sense that, so far as our ob-
  10491. servations go, they are negligible. The influx of objectifications of the
  10492. actualities of the world as organized vehicles of feeling is responded to by
  10493. a mere subjective appropriation of such elements of feeling in their re-
  10494. ceived relevance. The inorganic occasions are merely what the causal past
  10495. allows them to be.
  10496.  
  10497. As we pass to the inorganic world, causation never for a moment seems
  10498. to lose its grip. What is lost is originativeness, and any evidence of im-
  10499. mediate absorption in the present. So far as we can see, inorganic entities
  10500. are vehicles for receiving, for storing in a napkin, and for restoring with-
  10501. out loss or gain.
  10502.  
  10503. In the actual world we discern four grades of actual occasions, grades
  10504. which are not to be sharply distinguished from each other. First, and
  10505. lowest, there are the actual occasions in so-called 'empty space'; secondly,
  10506. there are the actual occasions which are moments in the life-histories of
  10507. enduring non-living objects, such as electrons or other primitive organ-
  10508. isms; thirdly, there are the actual occasions which are moments in the
  10509. life-histories of enduring living objects; fourthly, there are the actual oc-
  10510. casions which are moments in the life-histories of enduring objects with
  10511. conscious knowledge.
  10512.  
  10513. We may imaginatively conjecture that the first grade is to be identified
  10514. with actual occasions for which 'presented durations' are negligible ele-
  10515. ments among their data, negligible by reason of negligible presentational
  10516. immediacy. Thus no intelligible definition of rest and motion is possible
  10517. for historic routes including them, because they correspond to no inherent
  10518. spatializationf of the actual world.
  10519.  
  10520. The second grade is to be identified with actual occasions for which
  10521. 'presented durations' are important elements in their data, but with a limi-
  10522. tation only to be [270] observed in the lower moments of human experi-
  10523. ence. In such occasions the data of felt sensa, derived "from the more
  10524. primitive data of causal efficacy, are projected onto the contemporary
  10525.  
  10526.  
  10527.  
  10528. 178 Discussions and Applications
  10529.  
  10530. 'presented locus' without any clear illustration of special regions in that
  10531. locus. The past has been lifted into the present, but the vague differentia-
  10532. tions in the past have not been transformed into any precise differentia-
  10533. tions within the present. The enhancement of precision has not arrived.
  10534.  
  10535. The third grade is to be identified with occasions in which presentational
  10536. immediacy has assumed some enhanced precision, so that 'symbolic trans-
  10537. ference' has lifted into importance precisely discriminated regions in the
  10538. 'presented duration/ The delicate activities of self-preservation are now
  10539. becoming possible by the transference of the vague message of the past
  10540. onto the more precisely discriminated regions of the presented duration.
  10541. Symbolic transference is dependent upon the flashes of conceptual orig-
  10542. inality constituting life.
  10543.  
  10544. The fourth grade is to be identified with the canalized importance of
  10545. free conceptual functionings, whereby blind experience is analysed by
  10546. comparison with the imaginative realization of mere potentiality. In this
  10547. way, experience receives a reorganization in the relative importance of its
  10548. components by the joint operation of imaginative enjoyment and of judg-
  10549. ment. The growth of reason is the increasing importance of critical judg-
  10550. ment in the discipline of imaginative enjoyment.
  10551.  
  10552. SECTION V
  10553.  
  10554. One reason for the philosophical difficulties over causation is that Hume,
  10555. and subsequently Kant, conceived the causal nexus as, in its primary
  10556. character, derived from the presupposed sequence of immediate presenta-
  10557. tions. But if we interrogate experience, the exact converse is the case; the
  10558. perceptive mode of immediate presentation affords information about the
  10559. percepta in the more aboriginal mode of causal efficacy.
  10560.  
  10561. [271] Thus symbolic reference, though in complex human experience
  10562. it works both ways, is chiefly to be thought of as the elucidation of per-
  10563. cepta in the mode of causal efficacy by the fluctuating intervention of
  10564. percepta in the mode of presentational immediacy.
  10565.  
  10566. The former mode produces percepta which are vague, not to be con-
  10567. trolled, heavy with emotion: it produces the sense of derivation from an
  10568. immediate past, and of passage to an immediate future; a sense of emo-
  10569. tional feeling, belonging to oneself in the past, passing into oneself in
  10570. the present, and passing from oneself in the present towards oneself in the
  10571. future; a sense of influx of influence from other vaguer presences in the
  10572. past, localized and yet evading local definition, such influence modifying,
  10573. enhancing, inhibiting, diverting, the stream of feeling which we are re-
  10574. ceiving, unifying, enjoying, and transmitting. This is our general sense
  10575. of existence, as one item among others, in an efficacious actual world.
  10576.  
  10577. By diversion of attention we can inhibit its entry into consciousness;
  10578. but, whether mentally analysed or no, it remains the given uncontrolled
  10579. basis upon which our character weaves itself. Our bodies are largely con-
  10580.  
  10581.  
  10582.  
  10583. Symbolic Reference 179
  10584.  
  10585. trivances whereby some central actual occasion may inherit these basic
  10586. experiences of its antecedent parts. Thus organic bodies have their parts
  10587. coordinated by a peculiar vividness in their mutual inheritance. In a sense,
  10588. the difference between a living organism and the inorganic environment
  10589. is only a question of degree; but it is a difference of degree which makes
  10590. all the difference— in effect, it is a difference of quality.
  10591.  
  10592. The percepta in the mode of presentational immediacy have the con-
  10593. verse characteristics. In comparison, they are distinct, definite, controllable,
  10594. apt for immediate enjoyment, and with the minimum of reference to past,
  10595. or to future. We are subject to our percepta in the mode of efficacy, we
  10596. adjust our percepta in the mode of immediacy. But, in fact, our process
  10597. of self-construction for the achievement of unified experience produces!
  10598. a new [272] product, in which percepta in one mode, and percepta in the
  10599. other mode, are synthesized into one subjective feeling. For example, we
  10600. are perceiving before our eyes a grey stone.
  10601.  
  10602. We shall find that generally— though not always— the adjectival words
  10603. express information derived from the mode of immediacy, while the sub-
  10604. stantives convey our dim percepts in the mode of efficacy. For example,
  10605. 'grey' refers to the grey shape immediately before our eyes: this percept
  10606. is definite, limited, controllable, pleasant or unpleasant, and with no ref-
  10607. erence to past or to future. It is this sort of percept which has led to Des-
  10608. cartes' definition of substances as 'requiring nothing but themselves in
  10609. order to exist/ and to his notion of 'extension' as the principal f attribute
  10610. of a genus of substances. It has also led to Hume's notion of 'impressions
  10611. of sensation' t arising from unknown sources, and in complete indepen-
  10612. dence so far as any discerniblef nexus is concerned. But the other element
  10613. in the compound percept has a widely different character. The word
  10614. 'stone' is selected, no doubt, because its dictionary meaning will afford
  10615. some help in understanding the particular percepta meant. But the word
  10616. is meant to refer to particular feelings of efficacy in the immediate past,
  10617. combined with anticipations for the immediate future; this feeling is
  10618. vaguely localized, and conjecturallyt identified with the very definite
  10619. localization of the 'grey' perceptum.
  10620.  
  10621. Thus, so far as concerns conscious judgment, the symbolic reference is
  10622. the acceptance of the evidence of percepta, in the mode of immediacy,
  10623. as evidence for the localization and discrimination of vague percepta in
  10624. the mode of efficacy. So far as bodily feelings are concerned, there is some
  10625. direct check on this procedure; but, beyond the body, the appeal is to the
  10626. pragmatic consequences, involving some future state of bodily feelings
  10627. which can be checked up.
  10628.  
  10629. But throughout this discussion of perception there has been excessive
  10630. emphasis on the mental phase in the [273} experiential process. This is
  10631. inevitable because we can only discuss experiences which have entered into
  10632. conscious analysis. But perception is a feeling which has its seat in the two
  10633. earlier phases of the experiential! process, namely, the 'responsive' phase,
  10634.  
  10635.  
  10636.  
  10637. 1 80 Discussions and Appli ations
  10638.  
  10639. and the 'supplemental' phase. Perception, in these phases, is the appropri-
  10640. ation of the datum by the subject so as to transform the datum into a
  10641. unity of subjective feeling. The mode of efficacy belongs to the responsive
  10642. phase, in which the objectifications are felt according to their relevance
  10643. in the datum: the mode of immediacy belongs to the supplemental phase
  10644. in which the faint indirect relevance, in the datum, of relationships to re-
  10645. gions of the presented locus ist lifted into distinct, prominent, relevance.
  10646. The question as to which regions have their relatedness to other con-
  10647. stituents of the datum— such as 'grey/ for instance— thus accentuated,
  10648. depends upon the coordination of the bodily organs through which the
  10649. routes of inheritance pass. In a fortunately construed** animal body, this
  10650. selection is determined chiefly by the inheritance received by the super-
  10651. ficial organst=the skin, the eyes, etc.— from the external environment,
  10652. and preserves the relevance of the vector character of that external
  10653. inheritance. When this is the case, the perceptive mode of immediacy
  10654. has definite relevance to the future efficacy of the external environment,
  10655. and then indirectly illustrates the inheritance which the presented locus
  10656. receives from the immediate past.
  10657.  
  10658. But this illustration does not gain its first importance from any rational
  10659. analysis. The two modes are unified by a blind symbolic reference by which
  10660. supplemental feelings derived from the intensive, but vague, mode of
  10661. efficacy are precipitated upon the distinct regions illustrated in the mode
  10662. of immediacy. The integration of the two modes in supplemental feeling
  10663. makes what would have been vague to be distinct, and what would have
  10664. been shallow to be intense. This is the perception of the grey stone, in the
  10665. mixed mode of symbolic reference.
  10666.  
  10667. [274] Such perception can be erroneous, in the sense that the feeling
  10668. associates regions in the presented locus with inheritances from the past,
  10669. which in fact have not been thus transmitted into the present regions.
  10670. In the mixed mode, the perceptive determination is purely due to the
  10671. bodily organs, and thus there is a gap in the perceptive logic— so to speak.
  10672. This gap is not due to any conceptual freedom on the part of the ultimate
  10673. subject. It is not a mistake due to consciousness. It is due to the fact that
  10674. the body, as an instrument for synthesizing and enhancing feelings, is
  10675. faulty, in the sense that it produces feelings which have but slight reference
  10676. to the real state of the presented duration.
  10677.  
  10678. SECTION VI
  10679.  
  10680. Symbolic reference between the two perceptive modes affords the main
  10681. example of the principles which govern all symbolism. The requisites for
  10682. symbolism are that there be two species of percepta; and that a perceptum
  10683. of one species has some 'ground' in common with a perceptum of another
  10684. species, so that a correlation between the pair of percepta is established.
  10685.  
  10686.  
  10687.  
  10688. Symbolic Reference 181
  10689.  
  10690. The feelings, and emotions, and genera characteristics associated with the
  10691. members of one species are in some ways markedly diverse from those as-
  10692. sociated with the other species. Then there is 'symbolic reference' between
  10693. the two species when the perception of a member of one species evokes
  10694. its correlate in the other species, and precipitates upon this correlate the
  10695. fusion of feelings, emotions, and derivate actions, which belong to either
  10696. of the pair of correlates, and which are also enhanced by this correlation.
  10697. The species from which the symbolic reference starts is called the 'species
  10698. of symbols/ and the species withf which it ends is called the 'species of
  10699. meanings/ In this way there can be symbolic reference between two species
  10700. in the same perceptive mode: but the chief example of symbolism, upon
  10701. which is based a great portion of the lives [275] of all high-grade animals,
  10702. is that between the two perceptive modes.
  10703.  
  10704. Symbolism can be justified, or unjustified. The test of justification must
  10705. always be pragmatic. In so far ast symbolism has led to a route of inheri-
  10706. tance, along the percipient occasions forming the percipient 'person/
  10707. which constitutes a fortunate evolution, the symbolism is justified; and,
  10708. in so far as the symbolism has led to an unfortunate evolution, it is un-
  10709. justified. In a slightly narrower sense the symbolism can be right or wrong;
  10710. and Tightness or wrongness is also tested pragmatically. Along the 'historic
  10711. route' there is the inheritance of feelings derived from symbolic reference:
  10712. now, if feelings respecting some definite element in experience be clue
  10713. to two sources, one source being this inheritance, and the other source
  10714. being direct perception in one of the pure modes, then, if the feelings
  10715. from the two sources enhance each other by synthesis, the symbolic ref-
  10716. erence is right; but, if they are at variance so as to depress each other, the
  10717. symbolic reference is wrong. The Tightness, or wrongness, of symbolism is
  10718. an instance of the symbolism being fortunate or unfortunate; but mere
  10719. 'rectitude/ in the sense defined above, does' not cover all that can be in-
  10720. cluded in the more general concept of 'fortune/ So much of human ex-
  10721. perience is bound up with symbolic reference, that it is hardly an exag-
  10722. geration to say that the very meaning of truth is pragmatic. But though
  10723. this statement is hardly an exaggeration, still it is an exaggeration, for the
  10724. pragmatic test can never work, unless on some occasion— in the future,
  10725. or in the present— there is a definite determination of what is true on that
  10726. occasion. Otherwise the poor pragmatist remains an intellectual Hamlet,
  10727. perpetually adjourning decision of judgment to some later date. According
  10728. to the doctrines here stated, the day of judgment arrives when the 'mean-
  10729. ing' is sufficiently distinct and relevant, as a perceptum in its proper pure
  10730. mode, to afford comparison with the precipitate of feeling derived
  10731. [276] from symbolic reference. There is no inherent distinction between
  10732. the sort of percepta which are symbols f and the sort of percepta which
  10733. are meanings. When two species are correlated by a 'ground' of relatedness,
  10734. it depends upon the experiential process, constituting the percipient!
  10735.  
  10736.  
  10737.  
  10738. 182 Discussions and Applications
  10739.  
  10740. subject, as to which species is the group of symbols, and which is the group
  10741. of meanings. Also it equally depends upon the percipient as to whether
  10742. there is any symbolic reference at all.
  10743.  
  10744. Language is the example of symbolism which most naturally presents
  10745. itself for consideration of the uses of symbolism. Its somewhat artificial
  10746. character makes the various constitutive elements in symbolism to be the
  10747. more evident. For the sake of simplicity, only spoken language will be con-
  10748. sidered here.
  10749.  
  10750. A single word is not one definite sound. Every instance of its utterance
  10751. differs in some respect from every other instance: the pitch of the voice,
  10752. the intonation, the accent, the quality of sound, the rhythmic relations
  10753. of the component sounds, the intensity of sound, all vary. Thus a word is
  10754. a species of sounds, with specific identity and individual differences. When
  10755. we recognize the species, we have heard the word. But what we have heard
  10756. is merely the sound— euphonious or harsh, concordant with or discordant
  10757. with other accompanying sounds. The word is heard in the pure perceptive
  10758. mode of immediacy, and primarily elicits merely the contrasts and iden-
  10759. tities with other percepta in that mode. So far there is no symbolic
  10760. interplay.
  10761.  
  10762. If the meaning of the word be an event, then either that event is directly
  10763. known, as a remembered perceptum in an earlier occasion of the percip-
  10764. ient's life, or that event is only vaguely known by its dated spatio-temporal
  10765. nexus with events which are directly known. Anyhow there is a chain of
  10766. symbolic references (inherited along the historic route of the percipient's
  10767. life, and reinforced by the production of novel and symbolic references
  10768. at various occasions along that route) whereby in the datum [277] for the
  10769. percipient occasion there is a faintly relevant nexus between the word in
  10770. that occasion of utterance and the event. The sound of the word,! in
  10771. presentational immediacy, by symbolic references elicits this nexus into
  10772. important relevance, and thence precipitates feelings, and thoughts, upon
  10773. the enhanced objectification of the event. Such enhanced relevance of the
  10774. event may be unfortunate, or even unjustified; but it is the function of
  10775. words to produce it. The discussion of mentality is reserved for Part III:
  10776. it is a mistake to think of words as primarily the vehicle of thoughts.
  10777.  
  10778. Language also illustrates the doctrine that, in regard to a couple of prop-
  10779. erly correlated species of things, it depends upon the constitution of the
  10780. percipient subject to assign which species is acting as 'symbol' and which
  10781. as 'meaning.' The word 'forest' may suggest! memories of forests; but
  10782. equally the sight of a forest, or memories of forests, may suggest the word
  10783. 'forest.' Sometimes we are bothered because the immediate experience has
  10784. not elicited the word we want. In such a case the word with the right sort
  10785. of correlation with the experience has failed to become importantly rele-
  10786. vant in the constitution of our experience.
  10787.  
  10788. But we do not usually think of the things as symbolizing the words cor-
  10789. related to them. This failure to invert our ideas arises from the most useful
  10790.  
  10791.  
  10792.  
  10793. Symbolic Reference 183
  10794.  
  10795. aspect of symbolism. In general the symbols are more handy elements in
  10796. our experience than are the meanings. We can say the word 'forest' when-
  10797. ever we like; but only under certain conditions can we directly experience
  10798. an existent forest. To procure such an experience usually involves a prob-
  10799. lem of transportation only possible on our holidays. Also it is not so easy
  10800. even to remember forest scenes with any vividness; and we usually find that
  10801. the immediate experience of the word 'forest' helps to elicit such recollec-
  10802. tions. In such ways language is handy as an instrument of communication
  10803. along the successive occasions of the historic route forming the life of one
  10804. individual. By an [278] extension of these same principles of behaviour, it
  10805. communicates from the occasions of one individual to the succeeding oc-
  10806. casions of another individual. The same means which are handy for pro-
  10807. curing the immediate presentation of a word to oneself are equally effec-
  10808. tive for presenting it to another person. Thus we may have a two-way
  10809. system of symbolic reference involving two persons, A and B. The forest,
  10810. recollected by A, symbolizes the word 'forest' for A; then A, for his own
  10811. sake and for B's sake, pronounces the word 'forest'*; then by the efficacy
  10812. of the environment and of B'$ bodily parts, and by the supplemental en-
  10813. hancement due to B's experiential process, the word 'forest' is perceived
  10814. by B in the mode of immediacy; and, finally by symbolic reference, B
  10815. recollects vaguely various forest scenes. In this use of language for com-
  10816. munication between two persons, there is in principle nothing which differs
  10817. from its use by one person for communication along the route of his own
  10818. actual occasions.
  10819.  
  10820. This discussion shows that one essential purpose of symbols arises from
  10821. their handiness. For this reason the Egyptian papyrus made ink-written
  10822. language a more useful symbolism than the Babylonian language im-
  10823. pressed on brick. It is easier to smell incense than to produce certain
  10824. religious emotions; so, if the two can be correlated, incense is a suitable
  10825. symbol for such emotions. Indeed, for many purposes, certain aesthetic
  10826. experiences which are easy to produce make better symbols than do words,
  10827. written or spoken. Quarrels over symbolism constitute one of the many
  10828. causes of religious discord. One difficulty in symbolism is that the unhandy
  10829. meanings are often vague. For instance, this is the case with the percepta
  10830. in the mode of efficacy which are symbolized by percepta in the mode of
  10831. immediacy: also, as another instance, the incense is definite, but the re-
  10832. ligious emotions are apt to be indefinite. The result is that the meanings
  10833. are often shifting and indeterminate. This happens even in the case of
  10834. words: other people misun- [279] derstand their import. Also, in the case
  10835. of incense the exact religious emotions finally reached are very uncertain:
  10836. perhaps we would prefer that some of them were never elicited.
  10837.  
  10838. Symbolism is essential for the higher grades of life; and the errors of
  10839. symbolism can never be wholly avoided.
  10840.  
  10841.  
  10842.  
  10843. CHAPTER IX
  10844. THE PROPOSITIONS
  10845.  
  10846. SECTION I
  10847.  
  10848. [280] A living occasion is characterized by a flash of novelty among the
  10849. appetitions of its mental pole. Such 'appetitions/ i.e., 'conceptual prehen-
  10850. sions/ can be 'pure' or 'impure/ An 'impure' prehension arises from the
  10851. integration of a 'pure 7 conceptual prehension with a physical prehension
  10852. originating in the physical pole. The datum of a pure conceptual prehen-
  10853. sion is an eternal object; the datum of an impure prehension is a proposi-
  10854. tion, otherwise termed a 'theory/
  10855.  
  10856. The integration of a conceptual and physical prehension need not issue
  10857. in an impure prehension: the eternal object as a mere potentiality, un-
  10858. determined as to its physical realization, may lose its indetermination, i.e.,
  10859. its universality, by integration with itself as an element in the realized
  10860. definiteness of the physical datum of the physical prehension. In this case
  10861. we obtain what in Part III is termed a 'physical purpose/ In a physical
  10862. purpose the subjective form has acquired a special appetition— adversion
  10863. or aversion— in respect to that eternal object as a realized element of
  10864. definiteness in that physical datum. This acquisition is derived from the
  10865. conceptual prehension. The 'abruptness* of mental operations is here il-
  10866. lustrated. The physical datum in itself illustrates an indefinite number
  10867. of eternal objects. The 'physical purpose 7 has focussed appetition upon an
  10868. abruptly selected eternal object.
  10869.  
  10870. But with the growth of intensity in the mental pole, evidenced by the
  10871. flash of novelty in appetition, the appetition takes the form of a 'preposi-
  10872. tional prehension/ [281] These prehensions will be studied more partic-
  10873. ularly in Part III. They are the prehensions of 'theories/ It is evident, how-
  10874. ever, that the primary function of theories is as a lure for feeling, thereby
  10875. providing immediacy of enjoyment and purpose. Unfortunately theories,
  10876. under their name of 'propositions/ have been handed over to logicians,
  10877. who have countenanced the doctrine that their one function is to be
  10878. judged as to their truth or falsehood. Indeed Bradley does not mention
  10879. 'propositions' in his Logic. t He writes only of 'judgments/ Other authors
  10880. define propositions as a component in judgment. The doctrine here laid
  10881. clown is that, in the realization of propositions, 'judgment 7 is at very rare
  10882. component, and so is 'consciousness/ The existence of imaginative litera-
  10883.  
  10884. 184
  10885.  
  10886.  
  10887.  
  10888. The Propositions 185
  10889.  
  10890. ture should have warned logicians that their narrow doctrine is absurd.
  10891. It is difficult to believe that all logicians as they read Hamlet's speech,
  10892. "To be, or not to be: . . ." commence by judging whether the initial
  10893. proposition be true or false, and keep up the task of judgment through-
  10894. out the whole thirty-five lines. Surely, at some point in the reading, judg-
  10895. ment is eclipsed by aesthetic delight. The speech, for the theatre audience,
  10896. is purely theoretical, a mere lure for feeling.
  10897.  
  10898. Again, consider strong religious emotion— consider a Christian medi-
  10899. tating on the sayings in the Gospels. He is not judging 'true or false'; he
  10900. is eliciting their value as elements in feeling. In fact, he may ground his
  10901. judgment of truth upon his realization of value. But such a procedure is
  10902. impossible, if the primary function of propositions is to be elements in
  10903. judgments.
  10904.  
  10905. The 'lure for feeling' is the final cause guiding the concrescence of
  10906. feelings. By this concrescence the multifold datum of the primary phase
  10907. is gathered into the unity of the final satisfaction of feeling. The 'objective
  10908. lure' is that discrimination among eternal objects introduced into the
  10909. universe by the real internal constitutions of the actual occasions forming
  10910. the datum of the concrescence under review. This discrimination also
  10911. in- \282] volves eternal objects excluded from value in the temporal occa-
  10912. sions of that datum, in addition to involving the eternal objects included
  10913. for such occasions.
  10914.  
  10915. For example, consider the Battle of Waterloo. This battle resulted in
  10916. the defeat of Napoleon, and in a constitution of our actual world grounded
  10917. upon that defeat. But the abstract notions, expressing the possibilities of
  10918. another course of history which would' have followed upon his victory,
  10919. are relevant to the facts which actually happened. We may not think it
  10920. of practical importance that imaginative historians should dwell upon
  10921. such hypothetical alternatives. But we confess their relevance in thinking
  10922. about them at all, even to the extent of dismissing them. But some imag-
  10923. inative writers do not dismiss such ideas. Thus, in our actual world of
  10924. today, there is a penumbra of eternal objects, constituted by relevance to
  10925. the Battle of Waterloo. Some people do admit elements from this pen-
  10926. umbral complex into effective feeling, and others wholly exclude them.
  10927. Some are conscious of this internal decision of admission or rejection; for
  10928. others the ideas float into their minds as day-dreams without consciousness
  10929. of deliberate decision; for others, their emotional tone, of gratification
  10930. or regret, of friendliness or hatred, is obscurely influenced by this pen-
  10931. umbra of alternatives, without any conscious analysis of its content. The
  10932. elements of this penumbra are prepositional prehensions, and not pure
  10933. conceptual prehensions; for their implication of the particular nexus which
  10934. ist the Battle of Waterloo is an essential factor.
  10935.  
  10936. Thus an element in this penumbral complex is what is termed a 'propo-
  10937. sition/ A proposition is at new kind of entity. It is a hybrid between pure
  10938.  
  10939.  
  10940.  
  10941. 186 Discussions and Applications
  10942.  
  10943. potentialities and actualities. A 'singular' proposition is the potentiality
  10944. of an actual world including a definite set of actual entities in a nexus of
  10945. reactions involving the hypothetical ingression of a definite set of eternal
  10946. objects.
  10947.  
  10948. A 'general' proposition only differs from a 'singular' proposition by the
  10949. generalization of 'one definite set of [283] actual entities' into "any set
  10950. belonging to a certain sort of sets.' If the sort of sets includes all sets with
  10951. potentiality for that nexus of reactions, the proposition is called 'universal.'
  10952.  
  10953. For the sake of simplicity, we will confine attention to singular propo-
  10954. sitions; although a slight elaboration of explanation will easily extend the
  10955. discussion to include general and universal propositions.
  10956.  
  10957. The definite set of actual entities involved are called the 'logical sub-
  10958. jects of the proposition'; and the definite set of eternal objects involved
  10959. are called the 'predicates of the proposition.' The predicates define a
  10960. potentiality of relatedness for the subjects. The predicates form one com-
  10961. plex eternal object: this is 'the complex predicate.' The 'singular' propo-
  10962. sition is the potentiality of this complex predicate finding realization in
  10963. the nexus of reactions between the logical subjects, with assigned stations
  10964. in the pattern for the various logical subjects.
  10965.  
  10966. In a proposition the various logical subjects involved are impartially
  10967. concerned. The proposition is no more about one logical subject than an-
  10968. other logical subject. But according to the ontological principle, every
  10969. proposition must be somewhere. The 'locus' of a proposition consists of
  10970. those actual occasions whose actual worlds include the logical subjects
  10971. of the proposition. When an actual entity belongs to the locus of a propo-
  10972. sition, then conversely the proposition is an element in the lure for feeling
  10973. of that actual entity. If by the decision of the concrescence, the proposi-
  10974. tion has been admitted into feeling, then the proposition constitutes what
  10975. the feeling has felt. The proposition constitutes a lure for a member of
  10976. its locus by reason of the germaneness of the complex predicate to the
  10977. logical subjects, having regard to forms of definiteness in the actual world
  10978. of that member, and to its antecedent phases of feeling.
  10979.  
  10980. The interest in logic, dominating overintellectualized philosophers, has
  10981. obscured the main function of propositions in the nature of things. They
  10982. are not primarily [284] for belief, but for feeling at the physical level of
  10983. unconsciousness. They constitute a source for the origination of feeling
  10984. which is not tied down to mere datum. A proposition is 'realized' by a
  10985. member of its locus, when it is admitted into feeling.
  10986.  
  10987. There are two types of relationship between a proposition and the actual
  10988. world of a member of its locus. The proposition may be conformal or
  10989. non-con formal to the actual world, true or false.
  10990.  
  10991. When a conformal proposition is admitted into feeling, the reaction
  10992. to the datum has simply resulted in the conformation of feeling to fact,
  10993. with some emotional accession or diminution, by which the feelings in-
  10994.  
  10995.  
  10996.  
  10997. The Propositions 187
  10998.  
  10999. herent in alien fact are synthesized in a new individual valuation. The
  11000. prehension of the proposition has abruptly emphasized one form of defi-
  11001. niteness illustrated in fact.
  11002.  
  11003. When a non-conformal proposition is admitted into feeling, the re-
  11004. action to the datum has resulted in the synthesis of fact with the alterna-
  11005. tive potentiality of the complex predicate. A novelty has emerged into
  11006. creation. The novelty may promote or destroy order; it may be good or
  11007. bad. But it is new, a new type of individual, and not merely a new inten-
  11008. sity of individual feeling. That member of the locus has introduced a new
  11009. form into the actual world; or,t at least, an old form in a new function.
  11010.  
  11011. The conception of propositions as merely material for judgments is fatal
  11012. to any understanding of their role in the universe. In that purely logical
  11013. aspect, non-conformal propositions aret merely wrong, and therefore worse
  11014. than useless. But in their primary role, they pave the way along which
  11015. the world advances into novelty. Error is the price which we pay for
  11016. progress.
  11017.  
  11018. The term 'proposition' suits these hybrid entities, t provided that we
  11019. substitute the broad notion of 'feeling' for the narrower notions of 'judg-
  11020. ment' and 'belief/ A proposition is an element in the objective lure pro-
  11021. posed for feeling, and when admitted into feeling it constitutes [2851 what
  11022. is felt. The 'imaginative' feeling (cf. Part III) of a proposition is one of
  11023. the ways of feeling it; and intellectual belief is another way oft feeling the
  11024. proposition, a way which presupposes imaginative feeling. Judgment is
  11025. the decision admitting a proposition into intellectual belief.
  11026.  
  11027. Anyone who at bedtime consciously reviews the events of the day is
  11028. subconsciously projecting them against the penumbral welter of alterna-
  11029. tives. He is also unconsciously deciding feelings so as to maximize his pri-
  11030. mary feeling, and to secure its propagation beyond his immediate present
  11031. occasion. In considering the life-history of occasions, forming the historic
  11032. route of an enduring physical object, there are three possibilities as to the
  11033. subjective aims which dominate the internal concrescence of the separate
  11034. occasions. Either (i), the satisfactions f of the antecedent occasions may
  11035. be uniform with each other, and each internally without discord or incite-
  11036. ment to novelty. In such a case, apart from novel discordance introduced
  11037. by the environment, there is the mere conformal transformation of the
  11038. feeling belonging to the datum into the identical feeling belonging to the
  11039. immediate subject. Such pure conformation involves the exclusion of all
  11040. the contraries involved in the lure, with their various grades of proximity
  11041. and remoteness. This is an absolute extreme of undifferentiated endurance,
  11042. of which we have no direct evidence. In every instance for which we can
  11043. analyse, however imperfectly, the formal constitutions of successive oc-
  11044. casions, these constitutions are characterized by contraries supervening
  11045. upon the aboriginal data, butt with a regularity of alternation which pro-
  11046. cures stability in the life-history. Contrast is thus gained. Tn physical sci-
  11047.  
  11048.  
  11049.  
  11050. 188 Discussions and Applications
  11051.  
  11052. ence, this is vibration/ This is the main character of the life-histories of
  11053. an inorganic physical object, stabilized in type.
  11054.  
  11055. Or (ii), there is a zest for the enhancement of some dominant element
  11056. of feeling, received from the data, enhanced by decision admitting non-
  11057. conformation of [286] conceptual feeling to other elements in the data,
  11058. and culminating in a satisfaction transmitting enhancement of the dom-
  11059. inant element by reason of novel contrasts and inhibitions. Such a life-history
  11060. involves growth dominated by a single final end. This is the main character
  11061. of a physical object in process of growth. Such physical objects are mainly
  11062. 'organic/ so far as concerns our present knowledge of the world.
  11063.  
  11064. Or (iii), there is a zest for the elimination of all dominant elements of
  11065. feeling, received from the data. In such a case, the route soon loses its
  11066. historic individuality. It is the case of decay.
  11067.  
  11068. The first point to be noticed is that the admission of the selected ele-
  11069. ments in the lure, as felt contraries, primarily generates purpose; it then
  11070. issues in satisfaction; and satisfaction qualifies the efficient causation. But
  11071. a felt 'contrary' is consciousness in germ. When the contrasts and identi-
  11072. ties of such feelings are themselves felt, we have consciousness. It is the
  11073. knowledge of ideas, in Locke's sense of that term. Consciousness requires
  11074. more than the mere entertainment of theory. It is the feeling of the con-
  11075. trast of theory, as mere theory, with fact, as mere fact. This contrast holds
  11076. whether or no the theory be correct.
  11077.  
  11078. A proposition, in abstraction from any particular actual entity which
  11079. may be realizing it in feeling, is a manner of germaneness of a certain
  11080. set of eternal objects to a certain set of actual entities. Every proposition
  11081. presupposes those actual entities which are its logical subjects. It also pre-
  11082. supposes certain definite actual entities, or a certain type of actual entities,!
  11083. within a wide systematic nexus. In an extreme case, this nexus may com-
  11084. prise any actual entity whatsoever.
  11085.  
  11086. The presupposed logical subjects may not be in the actual world of
  11087. some actual entity. In this case, the proposition does not exist for that
  11088. actual entity. The pure concept of such a proposition refers in the hypo-
  11089. thetical future beyond that actual entity. The propo- [287] sition itself awaits
  11090. its logical subjects. Thus propositions grow with the creative advance of the
  11091. world. They are neither pure potentials, nor pure actualities; they are a
  11092. manner of potential nexus involving pure potentials and pure actualities.
  11093. They are a new type of entities. Entities of this impure type presuppose
  11094. the two pure types of entities.
  11095.  
  11096. The primary mode of realization of a proposition in an actual entityt
  11097. is not by judgment, but by entertainment. A proposition is entertained
  11098. when it is admitted into feeling. Horror, relief, purpose, are primarily
  11099. feelings involving the entertainment of propositions.
  11100.  
  11101. In conclusion, there are four main types of entities in the universe, of
  11102. which two are primary types and two are hybrid types. The primary types
  11103. are actual entities and pure potentials (eternal objects); the hybrid types
  11104.  
  11105.  
  11106.  
  11107. The Propositions 189
  11108.  
  11109. are feelings and propositions (theories). Feelings are the 'real' components
  11110. of actual entities. Propositions are only realizable as one sort of 'objective'
  11111. datum for feelings.
  11112.  
  11113. The primary element in the 'lure for feeling' is the subject's prehension
  11114. of the primordial nature of God. Conceptual feelings are generated, and
  11115. by integration with physical feelings a subsequent phase of prepositional
  11116. feelings supervenes. The lure for feeling develops with the concrescent
  11117. phases of the subject in question. I have spoken of it elsewhere (cf. Science
  11118. and the\ Modern World, Ch. XI).
  11119.  
  11120. It is this realized extension of eternal relatedness beyond the mutual
  11121. relatedness of the actual occasions which prehends into each occasion
  11122. the full sweep of eternal relatedness. I term this abrupt* realization
  11123. the 'graded envisagement' which each occasion prehends into its syn-
  11124. thesis. This gradedt envisagement is how the actual includes what
  11125. (in one sense) is 'not-being' as a positive factor in its own achieve-
  11126. ment. It is the source of error, of truth, of art, of ethics, and of re-
  11127. ligion. By it, fact is confronted with alternatives. [288]
  11128.  
  11129. SECTION lit
  11130.  
  11131. All metaphysical theories which admit a disjunction between the
  11132. component elements of individual experience on the one hand.t and on the
  11133. other hand the component elements of the external world, must inevitably
  11134. run into difficulties over the truth and falsehood of propositions, and
  11135. over the grounds for judgment. The former difficulty is metaphysical, the
  11136. latter epistemological. But all difficulties as to first principles are only
  11137. camouflaged metaphysical difficulties. Thus also the epistemological dif-
  11138. ficulty is only solvable by an appeal to ontology. The first difficulty poses
  11139. the question as to the account of truth and falsehood, and the second
  11140. difficulty poses the question as to the account of the intuitive perception
  11141. of truth and falsehood. The former concerns propositions, the latter con-
  11142. cerns judgments. There is a togetherness of the component elements in
  11143. individual experience. This 'togetherness' has that special peculiar meaning
  11144. of 'togetherness in experience.' It is a togetherness of its own kind, ex-
  11145. plicable by reference to nothing else. For the purpose of this discussion
  11146. it is indifferent whether we speak of a 'stream' of experience, or of an
  11147. 'occasion' of experience. With the former alternative there is togetherness
  11148. in the stream, and with the latter alternative there is togetherness in the
  11149. occasion. In either case, there is the unique 'experiential togetherness.'
  11150.  
  11151. The consideration of experiential togetherness raises the final metaphysi-
  11152. cal question: whether there is any other meaning of 'togetherness.' The
  11153. denial of any alternative meaning, that is to say, of any meaning not
  11154. abstracted from the experiential meaning, is the 'subjectivist' doctrine.
  11155. This reformed version of the subjecfivist doctrine is the doctrine of the
  11156. philosophy of organism.
  11157.  
  11158.  
  11159.  
  11160. 190 Discussions and Applications
  11161.  
  11162. The contrary doctrine, that there is a 'togetherness' not derivative from
  11163. experiential togetherness, leads to the disjunction of the components of
  11164. subjective experience from the community of the external world. This
  11165. dis- [289] junction creates the insurmountable difficulty for epistemology.
  11166. For intuitive judgment is concerned with togetherness in experience, and
  11167. there is no bridge between togetherness in experience, and togetherness
  11168. of the non-experiential sort.
  11169.  
  11170. This difficulty is the point of Kant's 'transcendental' criticism. He
  11171. adopted a subjectivist position, so that the temporal world was merely
  11172. experienced. But according to his form of the subjectivist doctrine, in the
  11173. Critique of Pure Reason, no element in the temporal world could itself
  11174. be an experient. His temporal world, as in that Critique, was in its essence
  11175. dead, phantasmal, phenomenal. Kant was a mathematical physicist, and
  11176. his cosmological solution was sufficient for the abstractions to which math-
  11177. ematical physics is confined.
  11178.  
  11179. The difficulties of the subjectivist doctrine arise when it is combined
  11180. with the 'sensationalist' doctrine concerning the analysis of the compo-
  11181. nents which are together in experience. According to that analysis in such
  11182. a component the only elements not stamped with the particularity of that
  11183. individual 'occasion'— or 'stream'— of experience are universals such as
  11184. 'redness' or 'shape,' With the sensationalist assumption, or with any gen-
  11185. eralization of that doctrine, so long as the elements in question are uni-
  11186. versals, the only alternatives are, either Bradley's doctrine of a single ex-
  11187. perient, the absolute, or Leibniz's doctrine of many windowless monads.
  11188. Kant, in his final metaphysics, must either retreat to Leibniz, or advance
  11189. to Bradley. Either alternative stamps experience with a certain air of
  11190. illusoriness.t The Leibnizian solution can mitigate the illusoriness only
  11191. by recourse to a pious dependence upon God. This principle was invoked
  11192. by Descartes and by Leibniz, in order to help out their epistemology. It is
  11193. a device very repugnant to a consistent rationality. The very possibility of
  11194. knowledge should not be an accident of God's goodness; it should depend
  11195. on the interwoven natures of things. After all, God's knowledge has equally
  11196. to be explained.
  11197.  
  11198. [290] The philosophy of organism admits the subjectivist doctrine (as
  11199. here stated), but rejects the sensationalist doctrine: hence its doctrine of
  11200. the objectification of one actual occasion in the experience of another
  11201. actual occasion. Each actual entity is a throb of experience including the
  11202. actual world within its scope. The problems of efficient causation and of
  11203. knowledge receive a common explanation by reference to the texture of
  11204. actual occasions. The theory of judgment in the philosophy of organism
  11205. can equally well be described as a 'correspondence' theory or as a 'coher-
  11206. ence' theory. It is a correspondence theory, because it describes judgment
  11207. as the subjective form of the integral prehension of the conformity, or of the
  11208. non-conformity, of at proposition and an objectified nexus. The prehen-
  11209. sion in question arises from the synthesis of two prehensions, one physical
  11210.  
  11211.  
  11212.  
  11213. The Propositions 191
  11214.  
  11215. and the other mental. The physical prehension is the prehension of the
  11216. nexus of objectified actual occasions. The mental prehension is the pre-
  11217. hension of the proposition. This latter prehension is necessarily 'impure/
  11218. and it arises from a history of antecedent synthesis whereby a pure con-
  11219. ceptual prehension transfers its datum as a predicate of hypothetical re-
  11220. latedness for the actualities in the datum of some physical prehension
  11221. (cf. Part III). But the origination of a propositional prehension does not
  11222. concern us in this description of judgment. The sole point is the synthesis
  11223. of a physical prehension and propositional prehension into an 'intellectual'
  11224. prehension (cf. Part III) whose subjective form involves judgment.
  11225.  
  11226. This judgment is concerned with a conformity of two components
  11227. within one experience. It is thus a 'coherence' theory. It is also concerned
  11228. with the conformity of a proposition, not restricted to that individual ex-
  11229. perience, with a nexus whose relatedness is derived from the various ex-
  11230. periences of its own members and not from that of the judging experient.t
  11231. In this sense there is a 'correspondence' theory. But, at this point of the
  11232. argument, a distinction must be made. We shall say that a [291] proposi-
  11233. tion can be true or false, and that a judgment can be correct, or incorrect,
  11234. or suspended. With this distinction we see that there is a 'correspondence'
  11235. theory of the truth and falsehood of propositions, and a 'coherence' theory
  11236. of the correctness, incorrectness and suspensiont of judgments.
  11237.  
  11238. In the 'organic' doctrine, a clear distinction between a judgment and
  11239. a proposition has been made. A judgment is a feeling in the 'process' of
  11240. the judging subject, and it is correct or incorrect respecting that subject.
  11241. It enters, as a value, into the satisfaction of that subject; and it can only
  11242. be criticized by the judgments of actual entities in the future. A judgment
  11243. concerns the universe in process of prehension by the judging subject. It
  11244. will primarily concern a definite selection of objectified actual entities, and
  11245. of eternal objects; and it affirms the physical objectification— for the judg-
  11246. ing subject— of those actual entities by the ingression of those eternal ob-
  11247. jects; so that there is one objectified nexus of those actual entities, judged
  11248. to be really interconnected, and qualified, by those eternal objects. This
  11249. judgment affirms, correctly or incorrectly, a real fact in the constitution of
  11250. the judging subject. Here there is no room for any qualification of the
  11251. categorical character of the judgment. The judgment is made about itself
  11252. by the judging subject, and is at feeling in the constitution of the judging
  11253. subject. The actual entities, with which the judgment is explicitly con-
  11254. cerned, comprise the 'logical' subjects of the judgment, and the selected
  11255. eternal objects form the 'qualities' and 'relations' which are affirmed of
  11256. the logical subjects.
  11257.  
  11258. This affirmation about the logical subjects is obviously 'affirmation' in a
  11259. sense derivative from the meaning of 'affirmation' about the judging sub-
  11260. ject. Identification of the two senses will lead to error. In the latter** sense
  11261. there is abstraction from the judging subject. The subjectivist principle
  11262. has been transcended, and the judgment has shifted its emphasis from
  11263.  
  11264.  
  11265.  
  11266. 192 Discussions and Applications
  11267.  
  11268. the objectified nexus [292] to the truth-value of the proposition in ques-
  11269. tion. Having regard to the fact that judgment concerns the subjective form
  11270. of an impure feeling arising from the integration of simpler feelings, we
  11271. note that judgments are divisible into two sorts. These are (i) intuitive
  11272. judgments and (ii) derivative judgments. In an intuitive judgment the
  11273. integration of the physical datum with the proposition elicits into feeling
  11274. the full complex detail of the proposition in its comparison of identity,
  11275. or diversity, in regard to the complex detail of the physical datum. The
  11276. intuitive judgment is the consciousness of this complex detailed com-
  11277. parison involving identity and diversity. Such a judgment is in its nature
  11278. correct. For it is the consciousness of what is.
  11279.  
  11280. In a derivative judgment the integration of the physical datum with
  11281. the proposition elicits into feeling the full complex detail of the proposi-
  11282. tion, but does not elicit into feeling the full comparison of this detail with
  11283. the complex detail of the physical fact. There is some comparison involv-
  11284. ing the remainder of the detail. But the subjective form embraces the
  11285. totality of the proposition, instead of assuming a complex pattern which
  11286. discriminates between the compared and the uncompared components. In
  11287. derivative judgments there can be error. Logic is the analysis of the rela-
  11288. tionships between propositions in virtue of which derivative judgments
  11289. will not introduce errors, other than those already attaching to the judg-
  11290. ments in+ the premises. Most judgments are derivative; such judgments
  11291. illustrate the doctrine that the subjective form of a feeling is affected by
  11292. the totality of the actual occasion. This has been termed the 'sensitivity' of
  11293. feelings in one occasion. In an intuitive judgment the subjective form of
  11294. assent or dissent has been restrained, so as to derive its character solely
  11295. from the contrasts in the datum. Even in this case, the emotional force of
  11296. the judgment, as it passes into purpose, is derived from the whole judging
  11297. subject
  11298.  
  11299. Further, the judging subject and the logical subjects [293] refer to a uni-
  11300. verse with the general metaphysical character which represents its 'pa-
  11301. tience' for those subjects, and also its 'patience' for those eternal objects.
  11302. In each judgment the universe is ranged in a hierarchy of wider and wider
  11303. societies, as explained above (cf. Part II, Ch. III). It follows that the
  11304. distinction between the logical subjects, with their qualities and relations,
  11305. and the universe as systematic background, is not quite so sharply defined
  11306. as the previous explanation suggests. For it is a matter of convention as
  11307. to which of the proximate societies are reckoned as logical subjects and
  11308. which as background. Another way of stating this shading off of logical
  11309. subjects into background t is to say that the patience of the universe for a
  11310. real fact in a judging subject is a hierarchical patience involving systematic
  11311. gradations of character. This discussion substantiates the statement made
  11312. above (cf. Part I, Ch. I, Sect. V), that a verbal statement is never the full
  11313. expression of a proposition.
  11314.  
  11315. We now recur to the distinction between a proposition and a judgment.
  11316.  
  11317.  
  11318.  
  11319. The Propositions 193
  11320.  
  11321. A proposition emerges in the analysis of a judgment; it is the datum of
  11322. the judgment in abstraction from the judging subject and from the sub-
  11323. jective form. A judgment x is a synthetic feeling, embracing two subordinate
  11324. feelings in one unity of feeling. Of these subordinate feelings one is propo-
  11325. sitional, merely entertaining the proposition which is its datum. The same
  11326. proposition can constitute the content of diverse judgments by diverse
  11327. judging entities respectively. The possibility of diverse judgments by di-
  11328. verse actual entities, having the same content (of 'proposition' in con-
  11329. trast with 'nexus'), requires that the same complex of logical subjects, ob-
  11330. jectified via the same eternal objects, can enter as a partial constituent
  11331. into the 'real' essences of diverse actual entities. The judgment is a de-
  11332. cision of feeling, the proposition is what is felt; but it is only part of the
  11333. datum felt.
  11334.  
  11335. But, since each actual world is relative to standpoint, [294] it is only
  11336. some actual entities which will have the standpoints so as to include,! in
  11337. their actual world, the actual entities which constitute the logical subjects
  11338. of the proposition. Thus every proposition defines the judging subjects
  11339. for which it is a proposition. Every proposition presupposes some definite
  11340. settled actual entities in the actual world of its judging subject; and thus
  11341. its possible judging subjects must have these actual entities in the actual
  11342. world of each of them. All judgment requires knowledge of the pre-
  11343. supposed actual entities. Thus in addition to the requisite composition of
  11344. the actual world presupposed by a proposition, there must be the requi-
  11345. site knowledge of that world presupposed by a judgment, whether the
  11346. judgment be correct or incorrect. For actual entities, whose actual worlds
  11347. have not the requisite composition, the proposition is non-existent; for
  11348. actual entities, without the requisite knowledge, the judgment is im-
  11349. possible. It is quite true that a more abstract proposition can be modelled
  11350. on the lines of the original proposition, so as to avoid the presupposition of
  11351. some or all of these settled actual entities which are the logical subjects
  11352. in the original proposition. This new proposition will have meaning for a
  11353. wider group of possible subjects than the original proposition. Some propo-
  11354. sitions seem to us to have meaning for all possible judging subjects. This
  11355. may be the case; but I do not dare to affirm that our metaphysical capac-
  11356. ities are sufficiently developed to warrant any certainty on this question.
  11357. Perhaps we are always presupposing some wide society beyond which our
  11358. imaginations cannot leap. But the vagueness of verbal statements is such
  11359. that the same form of words is taken to represent a whole set of allied
  11360. propositions of various grades of abstractness.
  11361.  
  11362. A judgment weakens or strengthens the decision whereby the judged
  11363. proposition, as a constituent in the lure, is admitted as an efficient element
  11364. m the concrescence, with the reinforcement of knowledge. A judgment is
  11365. the critique of a lure for feeling.
  11366.  
  11367. 1 Cf. Part III, Ch. V.f
  11368.  
  11369.  
  11370.  
  11371. 194 Discussions and Applications
  11372.  
  11373.  
  11374.  
  11375. SECTION III
  11376.  
  11377. [295] It now remains to consider the sense in which the actual world,
  11378. in some systematic aspect, enters into each proposition. This investigation
  11379. is wholly concerned with the notion of the logical subjects of the proposi-
  11380. tion. These logical subjects are, in the old sense of the term, 'particulars.'
  11381. They are not concepts in comparison with other concepts; they are par-
  11382. ticular facts in a potential pattern.
  11383.  
  11384. But particulars must be indicated; because the proposition concerns just
  11385. those particulars and no others. Thus the indication belongs to the propo-
  11386. sition; namely, 'Those particulars as thus indicated in such-and-such a
  11387. predicative pattern' constitutes the proposition. Apart from the indication
  11388. there is no proposition because there are no determinate particulars. Thus
  11389. we have to study the theory of indication.
  11390.  
  11391. Some definitions are required:
  11392.  
  11393. A 'relation' between occasions is an eternal object illustrated in the
  11394. complex of mutual prehensions by virtue of which those occasions con-
  11395. stitute a nexus.
  11396.  
  11397. A relation is called a 'dual relation' when the nexus in which it is real-
  11398. ized consists of two, and only two, actual occasions. It is a 'triple relation'
  11399. when there are three occasions, and so on.
  11400.  
  11401. There will, in general, be an indefinite number of eternal objects thus
  11402. illustrated in the mutual prehensions of the occasions of any one nexus;
  11403. that is to say, there are an indefinite number of relations realized between
  11404. the occasions of any particular nexus.
  11405.  
  11406. A 'general principle' is an eternal object which is only illustrated through
  11407. its 'instances,' which are also eternal objects. Thus the realization of an
  11408. instance is also the realization of the general principle of which that eter-
  11409. nal object is an instance. But the converse is not true; namely, the realiza-
  11410. tion of the general principle does not involve the realization of any par-
  11411. ticular instance, though [296] it does necessitate the realization of some
  11412. instance. Thus the instances each involve the general principle, but the
  11413. general principle only involves at least one instance. In general, the in-
  11414. stances of a general principle are mutually exclusive, so that the realiza-
  11415. tion of one instance involves the exclusion of the other instances. For
  11416. example, colour is a general principle and colours are the instances. So if
  11417. all sensible bodies exhibit the general principle, which is colour, each body
  11418. exhibits some definite colour. Also each body exhibiting a definite colour
  11419. is thereby 'coloured.'
  11420.  
  11421. A nexus exhibits an 'indicative system' of dual relations among its mem-
  11422. bers, when (i) one, and only one, relation of the system relates each pair
  11423. of its members; and (ii) these relations are instances of a general prin-
  11424. ciple; and (iii) the relation (in the system) between any member A and
  11425. anv other member B does not also relate A and a member of the nexus
  11426.  
  11427.  
  11428.  
  11429. The Propositions 195
  11430.  
  11431. other than B; and (iv) the relations (in the system) between A and B
  11432. and between A and C suffice to define the relation (in the system) be-
  11433. tween B and C, where A, B, and C are any three members of the nexus.
  11434.  
  11435. Thus if A and X be any two members of the nexus, and if X has knowl-
  11436. edge of A's systematic relation to it and also of A's systematic relations to
  11437. B ? C, and D, where B, C, and D are members of the nexus, then X has
  11438. knowledge of its own systematic relations to B, C, and D, and of the
  11439. mutual systematic relations between B, C, and D. Such a nexus admits of
  11440. the precise indication of its members from the standpoint of any one of
  11441. them. The relative where' presupposes a nexus exhibiting an indicative
  11442. system. More complex types of indicative systems can be defined; but the
  11443. simplest type suffices to illustrate the principle involved. We have been
  11444. defining Aristotle's category of 'position/ It will be noticed that in a nexus
  11445. with an indicative system of relations, the subjective aspect of experience
  11446. can be eliminated from propositions involved. For a knowledge of B and
  11447. C and D as from A [297] yields a proposition concerning C and D as from
  11448. B. Thus the prevalent notion, that the particular subject of experience can,
  11449. in the nature of the case, never be eliminated from the experienced fact,
  11450. is quite untrue.
  11451.  
  11452. Every proposition presupposes some general nexus with an indicative
  11453. relational system. This nexus includes its locus of judging subjects and
  11454. also its logical subjects. This presupposition is part of the proposition, and
  11455. the proposition cannot be entertained by any subject for which the pre-
  11456. supposition is not valid. Thus in a proposition certain characteristics are
  11457. presupposed for the judging subject and for the logical subjects. This pre-
  11458. supposition of character can be carried further than the mere requirements
  11459. of indication require. For example, in 'Socrates is mortal' the mere spatio-
  11460. temporal indicative system may be sufficient to indicate 'Socrates/ But
  11461. the proposition may mean 'The man Socrates is mortal/ or 'The philoso-
  11462. pher Socrates is mortal/ The superfluous indication may be part of the
  11463. proposition. Anyhow, the principle that a proposition presupposes the
  11464. actual world as exhibiting some systematic aspect has now been explained.
  11465.  
  11466. This discussion can be illustrated by the proposition, 'Caesar has crossed
  11467. the Rubicon/ This form of words symbolizes an indefinite number of di-
  11468. verse propositions. In its least abstract form 'Caesar stands for a society of
  11469. settled actual entities in the actual world from the standpoint of the judg-
  11470. ing subject, with their objectifications consciously perceived by the sub-
  11471. ject. The whole theory of perception will come up for further discussion
  11472. in a later chapter (cf. Part III); at this point it can be assumed. The word
  11473. 'Rubicon' is to be explained in the same way as the word 'Caesar/ The
  11474. only points left ambiguous respecting 'Caesar' and 'Rubicon' are that
  11475. these societies— either or both, and each with its defining characteristic-
  11476. may be conjecturally supposed to be prolonged up to the world contem-
  11477. porary with the judging subject, or, even more conjecturally, into the
  11478. future [298] world beyond the subject. The past tense of the word 'has'
  11479.  
  11480.  
  11481.  
  11482. 196 Discussions and Applications
  11483.  
  11484. shows that this point of ambiguity is irrelevant, so that the proposition can
  11485. be framed so as to ignore it. But it need not be so framed: one of Caesar's
  11486. old soldiers may in later years have sat on the bank of the river and medi-
  11487. tated on the assassination of Caesar, and on Caesar's passage over the
  11488. little river tranquilly flowing before his gaze. This would have been a
  11489. different proposition from the more direct one which I am now consider-
  11490. ing. Nothing could better illustrate the hopeless ambiguity of language;
  11491. since both propositions fit the same verbal phraseology. There is yet a
  11492. third proposition: a modern traveller sitting on the bank of the Rubicon,
  11493. and meditating on his direct perceptions of actual occasions can locate,
  11494. relatively to himself by spatio-temporal specifications, an event which
  11495. inferentially and conjecturally he believes to include a portion of the past
  11496. history of the Rubicon as directly known to him. He also, by an analogous
  11497. process of inference and conjecture, and of spatio-temporal specification,
  11498. locates relatively to himself another event which he believes to contain
  11499. the life of Caesar of whom he has no direct knowledge. The proposition
  11500. meditated on by this traveller sitting on the bank of the modern river is
  11501. evidently a different proposition to that in the mind of Caesar's old soldier.
  11502. Then there is the proposition which might have been in the mind of one
  11503. of the crowd who listened to Antony's speech, a man who had seen Caesar
  11504. and not the Rubicon.
  11505.  
  11506. It is obvious that in this way an indefinite number of highly special
  11507. propositions can be produced, differing from each other by fine gradations.
  11508. Everything depends upon the differences in direct perceptive knowledge
  11509. which these various propositions presuppose for their subjects. But there
  11510. are propositions of at more general type, for which 'Caesar' and 'Rubicon'
  11511. have more generalized, vaguer meanings. In these vaguer meanings. 'Caesar'
  11512. and 'Rubicon' indicate the entities, if any, located by any one member of
  11513. a type of routes, starting from a [299] certain type of inference and con-
  11514. jecture. Also there are some such propositions in which the fact of there
  11515. being such entities, to be thus located, is part of the content whereby the
  11516. judgment is true or false; and there are other propositions in which even
  11517. this requisite is evaded, so far as truth or falsehood is concerned. It is by
  11518. reason of these various types of more abstract propositions that we can
  11519. conceive the hypothetical existence of the more special propositions which
  11520. for some of us, as judging subjects, would be meaningless.
  11521.  
  11522. This discussion should show the futility of taking any verbal statement,
  11523. such as 'Caesar has crossed the Rubicon/ and arguing about the meaning.
  11524. Also any proposition, which satisfies the verbal form so as to be one of its
  11525. possibilities of meaning, defines its own locus of subjects; and only for
  11526. such subjects is there the possibility of a judgment whose content is that
  11527. proposition.
  11528.  
  11529. A proposition is the potentiality of the objectification of certain pre-
  11530. supposed actual entities via certain qualities and relations, the objectifi-
  11531. cation being for some unspecified subject for which the presupposition has
  11532.  
  11533.  
  11534.  
  11535. The Propositions 197
  11536.  
  11537. meaning in direct experience. The judgment is the conscious affirmation
  11538. by a particular subject— for which the presupposition holds— that this
  11539. potentiality is, or is not, realized for it. It must be noticed that 'realized'
  11540. does not mean 'realized in direct conscious experience/ but does mean
  11541. 'realized as being contributory to the datum out of which that judging
  11542. subject originates/ Since direct t conscious experience is usually absent, a
  11543. judgment can be erroneous.
  11544.  
  11545. Thus a proposition is an example of what Locke calls an 'idea deter-
  11546. mined to particular existences/ It is the potentiality of such an idea; the
  11547. realized idea, admitted to decision in a given subject, is the judgment,
  11548. which may be a true or false idea about the particular things. The discus-
  11549. sion of this question must be resumed (cf. Part III) when conceptual
  11550. activity is examined. But it is evident that a proposition is a complex
  11551. entity which [300] stands between the eternal objects and the actual oc-
  11552. casions. Compared to eternal objects a proposition shares in the concrete
  11553. particularity of actual occasions; and compared to actual occasions a propo-
  11554. sition shares in the abstract generality of eternal objects. Finally, it must
  11555. be remembered that propositions enter into experience in other ways than
  11556. through judgment-feelings. +
  11557.  
  11558.  
  11559.  
  11560. SECTION IV
  11561.  
  11562. A metaphysical proposition— in the proper, general sense of the termt
  11563. 'metaphysical— signifies a proposition which (i) has meaning for any-
  11564. actual occasion, as a subject entertaining it, and (ii) is 'general/ in the
  11565. sense that its predicate potentially relates any and every set of actual oc-
  11566. casions, providing the suitable number of logical subjects for the predi-
  11567. cative pattern, and (iii) has a 'uniform' truth-value, in the sense that, by
  11568. reason of its form and scope, its truth-value is identical with the truth-
  11569. value of each of the singular propositions to be obtained by restricting the
  11570. application of the predicate to any one set of logical subjects. It is obvious
  11571. that, if a metaphysical proposition be true, the third condition is un-
  11572. necessary. For a general proposition can only be true if this condition be
  11573. fulfilled. But if the general proposition be false, then it is only metaphysical
  11574. when in addition each of the derivate singular propositions is false. The
  11575. general proposition would be false, if any one of the derivate singular
  11576. propositions were false. But the third condition is expressed in the propo-
  11577. sition without any dependence upon the determination of the proposition's
  11578. truth or falsehood.
  11579.  
  11580. There can be no cosmic epoch for which the singular propositions de-
  11581. rived from a metaphysical proposition differ in truth-valuet from those of
  11582. any other cosmic epoch.
  11583.  
  11584. We certainly think that we entertain metaphysical propositions: but,
  11585. having regard to the mistakes of the past respecting the principles of
  11586. geometry, it is wise to [30 J] reserve some scepticism on this point The
  11587.  
  11588.  
  11589.  
  11590. 198 Discussions and Applications
  11591.  
  11592. propositions which seem to be most obviously metaphysical are the arith-
  11593. metical theorems. I will therefore illustrate the justification both for the
  11594. belief, and for the residual scepticism, by an examination of one of the
  11595. simplest of such theorems: One and one make two. 2
  11596.  
  11597. Certainly, this proposition, construed in the sense 'one entity and an-
  11598. other entity make two entities/" seems to be properly metaphysical without
  11599. any shadow of limitation upon its generality, or truth. But we must hesi-
  11600. tate even here, when we notice that it is usually asserted, with equal con-
  11601. fidence as to the generality of its metaphysical truth, in a sense which is
  11602. certainly limited, and sometimes untrue. In our reference to the actual
  11603. world, we rarely consider an individual actual entity. The objects of our
  11604. thoughts are almost always societies, or looser groups of actual entities.
  11605. Now, for the sake of simplicity, consider a society of the 'personal' type.
  11606. Such a society will be a linear succession of actual occasions forming a
  11607. historical route in which some defining characteristic is inherited by each
  11608. occasion from its predecessors. A society of this sort is an 'enduring ob-
  11609. ject/ Probably, a simple enduring object is simpler than anything which
  11610. we ordinarily perceive or think about. It is the simplest type of society;
  11611. and for any duration of its existence it requires that its environment be
  11612. largely composed of analogous simplef enduring objects. What we nor-
  11613. mally consider is the wider society in which many strands of enduring
  11614. objects are to be found, a 'corpuscular society/
  11615.  
  11616. Now consider two distinct enduring objects. They will be easier to
  11617. think about if their defining characteristics are different. We will call these
  11618. defining characteristics a and b y and also will use these letters, a and b,
  11619. as the names of the two enduring objects. Now the proposition 'one entity
  11620. and another entity make two [302] entities' is usually construed in the
  11621. sense that, given two enduring objects, any act of attention which con-
  11622. sciously comprehends an actual occasion from each of the two historic
  11623. routes will necessarily discover two actual occasions, one from each of the
  11624. two distinct routes. For example, suppose that a cup and a saucer are two
  11625. such enduring objects, which of course they are not; we always assume
  11626. that, so long as they are both in existence and are sufficiently close to be
  11627. seen in one glance, any act of attention, whereby we perceive the cup and
  11628. perceive the saucer, will thereby involve the perception of two actual en-
  11629. tities, one the cup in one occasion of its existence and the other the saucer
  11630. in one occasion of its existence. There can be no reasonable doubt as to
  11631. the truth of this assumption in this particular example. But in making
  11632. it, we are very far from the metaphysical proposition from which we
  11633. started. We are in fact stating a truth concerning the wide societies of
  11634. entities amid which our lives are placed. It is a truth concerning this
  11635. cosmos, but not a metaphysical truth.
  11636.  
  11637. Let us return to the two truly simple enduring objects, a and b. Also
  11638.  
  11639. 2 For the proof of this proposition, cf. Principia Mathematical Vol. II,
  11640. *110.643.
  11641.  
  11642.  
  11643.  
  11644. The Propositions 199
  11645.  
  11646. let us assume that their defining characteristics, a and b, are not con-
  11647. traries, so that both of them can qualify the same actual occasion. Then
  11648. there is no general metaphysical reason why the distinct routes of a and b
  11649. should not intersect in at least one actual occasion. Indeed, having regard
  11650. to the extreme generality of the notion of a simple enduring object, it is
  11651. practically certain that— with the proper choice for the defining character-
  11652. istics, a and b— intersecting historic routes for a and b must have fre-
  11653. quently come into existence. In such a contingency a being who could
  11654. consciously distinguish the two distinct enduring objects a and b, so as
  11655. to have knowledge of their distinct defining characteristics and their dis-
  11656. tinct historic routes, might find a and b exemplified in one actual entity.
  11657. It is as though the cup and the saucer were at one instant identical; and
  11658. then, later on, resumed their distinct existence.
  11659.  
  11660. [303] We hardly ever apply arithmetic in its pure metaphysical sense,
  11661. without the addition of presumptions which depend for their truth on the
  11662. character of the societies dominating the cosmic epoch in which we live.
  11663. It is hardly necessary to draw attention to the fact, that ordinary verbal
  11664. statements make no pretence of discriminating the different senses in which
  11665. an arithmetical statement can be understood.
  11666.  
  11667. There is no difficulty in imagining a world— i.e., a cosmic epoch— in
  11668. which arithmetic would be an interesting fanciful topic for dreamers, but
  11669. useless for practical people engrossed in the business of life. In fact, we
  11670. seem to have been only barely rescued from such a state of things. For
  11671. amid the actual occasions located in the wilds of so-called 'empty space/
  11672. and well removed from the enduring objects which go to form the en-
  11673. during material bodies, it is quite probable that the contemplation of
  11674. arithmetic would not direct attention to any very important relations of
  11675. things. It is, of course, a mere speculation that any actual entity, occurring
  11676. in such an environment of faintly coordinated achievement, achieves the
  11677. intricacy of constitution required for conscious mental operations.
  11678.  
  11679. SECTION V
  11680.  
  11681. We ask the metaphysical question, What is there in the nature of
  11682. things, whereby an inductive inference, or a judgment of general truth,
  11683. can be significantly termed 'correct' or Incorrect'? For example, we believe
  11684. now— July 1, 1927— that the railway time-tables for the United States,
  11685. valid for the previous months of May and June, represent the facts as to
  11686. the past running of the trains, within certain marginal limits of unpunc-
  11687. tuality, and allowing for a few individual breakdowns. Also we believe
  11688. that the current time-tables for July will be exemplified, subject to the
  11689. same qualifications. On the evidence before us our beliefs are justified,
  11690. provided that we introduce into our judgments some estimate of the
  11691. [304] high probability which is all that we mean to affirm. If we are con-
  11692. sidering astronomical events, our affirmations will include an estimate of
  11693.  
  11694.  
  11695.  
  11696. 200 Discussions and Applications
  11697.  
  11698. a higher probability. Though even here some margin of uncertainty may
  11699. exist The computers of some famous observatory may have made an un-
  11700. precedented error; or some unknown physical law may have important
  11701. relevance to the condition of the star mainly concerned, leading to its
  11702. unexpected explosion. 3
  11703.  
  11704. This astronomical contingency, and the beliefs which cluster round it,
  11705. have been stated with some detail, because— as thus expressed— they
  11706. illustrate the problem as it shapes itself in philosophy. Also the example
  11707. of the railway time-tables illustrates another point. For it is possible
  11708. momentarily, in Vermont on July 1, 1927, to forget that the unprecedented
  11709. Mississippi floods happened during that May and June; so that although
  11710. the estimate as to error in punctuality was justified by the evidence con-
  11711. sciously before us, it did not in fact allow for the considerable derange-
  11712. ment of the traffic in some states in the Union. 4 The point of this illus-
  11713. tration from railway trains is that there is a conformity to matter of fact
  11714. which these judgments exhibit, even if the events concerned have not
  11715. happened, or will not happen. These considerations introduce the funda-
  11716. mental principle concerning 'judgment/ It is that all judgment is categor-
  11717. ical; it concerns a proposition true or false in its application to the actual
  11718. occasion which is the subject making the judgment. This doctrine is not
  11719. so far from Bradley's doctrine of judgment, as explained in his Logic.
  11720. According to Bradley, the ultimate subject of every judgment is the one
  11721. ultimate substance, the absolute. Also, according to him, the judging
  11722. subject is a mode of the absolute, self-contradictory if taken to be inde-
  11723. pendently actual. For Bradley, the judging subject has only a [305] deriva-
  11724. tive actuality, which is the expression of its status as an affection of the
  11725. absolute. Thus,! in Bradley's doctrine, a judgment is an operation by which
  11726. the absolute, under the limitations of one of its affections, enjoys self-
  11727. consciousness of its enjoyment of affections. It will be noticed that in
  11728. this bald summary of Bradley's position, I am borrowing Spinoza's phrase,
  11729. 'affeciiones substantial
  11730.  
  11731. In the philosophy of organism, an actual occasion—as has been stated
  11732. above— is the whole universe in process of attainment of a particular
  11733. satisfaction. Bradley's doctrine of actuality is simply inverted. The final
  11734. actuality is the particular process with its particular attainment of satis-
  11735. faction. The actuality of the universe is merely derivative from its soli-
  11736. darity in each actual entity. It must be held that judgment concerns the
  11737. universe as objectified from the standpoint of the judging subject. It con-
  11738. cerns the universe through that subject.
  11739.  
  11740. With this doctrine in mind, we pass to the discussion of the sense in
  11741. which probability can be a positive fact in an actual entity; so that a propo-
  11742.  
  11743. 8 Since this sentence was written in July, 1927, a star has unexpectedly split
  11744. in two, in March, 1928.
  11745.  
  11746. 4 Still less, at the time of writing this sentence, were the Vermont floods of
  11747. November, 1927, foreseen.
  11748.  
  11749.  
  11750.  
  11751. The Propositions 201
  11752.  
  11753. sition expressing the probability of some other proposition can in this
  11754. respect agree or disagree with the constitution of the judging entity. The
  11755. notion of 'probability/ in the widest sense of that term, presents a puzzling
  11756. philosophical problem. The mathematical theory of probability is based
  11757. upon certain statistical assumptions. When these assumptions hold, the
  11758. meaning of probability is simple; and the only remaining difficulties are
  11759. concerned with the technical mathematical development. But it is not
  11760. easy to understand how the statistical theory can apply to all cases to
  11761. which the notion of more or less probability is habitually applied. For
  11762. example, when we consider— as we do consider— the probability of some
  11763. scientific conjecture as to the internal constitution of the stars, or as to
  11764. the future of human society after some unprecedented convulsion, we
  11765. seem to be influenced by some analogy which it is very difficult to convert
  11766. into an appeal to any definite statistical fact. We may consider that it is
  11767. probable [306] that the judgment could be justified by some statistical
  11768. appeal, if we only knew where to look. This is the belief that the statistical
  11769. probability is itself probable. But here, evidently, there is an appeal to a
  11770. wider meaning of probability in order to support the statistical probability
  11771. applicable to the present case. It is arguable that this wider probability
  11772. is itself another statistical probability as to the existence of the special
  11773. statistics relevant to such types of scientific argument. But in this explana-
  11774. tion puzzling questions are accumulating; and it is impossible to avoid the
  11775. suspicion that we are being put off with one of those make-believe ex-
  11776. planations, so useful to reasoners who are wedded to a theory. The phi-
  11777. losophy of organism provides two distinct elements in the universe from
  11778. which an intuition of probability can originate. One of them is statistical.
  11779. In this and the next two sections, + an attempt will be made to justify
  11780. the statistical theory. It is therefore the more imperative to survey care-
  11781. fully the difficulties which have to be met.
  11782.  
  11783. In the first place, probability is always relative* to evidence; so, on
  11784. the statistical theory, the numerical probability will mean the numerical
  11785. ratio of favourable to unfavourable cases in the particular class of 'cases'
  11786. selected as the 'ground 7 for statistical comparison. But alternative 'grounds'
  11787. certainly exist. Accordingly we must provide a reason,f not based upon
  11788. 'probability/ why one 'ground' is selected rather than another. We may
  11789. admit such a chain of vaguer and vaguer probabilities, in which our first
  11790. ground is selected as statistically probable in respect to its superiority to
  11791. other 'grounds' of other types. We are thus driven back to a second-order
  11792. ground' of probability. We may logically proceed to third-order 'grounds/
  11793. and so on. But if the statistical theory is to be substantiated, after a finite
  11794. number of steps we must reach a 'ground' which is not selected for any
  11795. reason of probability. It must be selected because it is the 'ground' pre-
  11796. supposed in all our reasonings. [307] Apart from some such ultimate
  11797. 'ground,' the statistical theory, viewed as an ultimate explanation for all
  11798. our uses of the notion of 'probability/ must inevitably fail. This failure
  11799.  
  11800.  
  11801.  
  11802. 202 Discussions and Applications
  11803.  
  11804. arises by reason of the complete arbitrariness of the ultimate 'ground'
  11805. upon which the whole estimate of probability finally rests.
  11806.  
  11807. Secondly, the primary requisite for a 'ground' suitable for statistical
  11808. probability seems itself to appeal to probability. The members of the
  11809. class, called the 'ground/ must themselves be 'cases of equal probability/
  11810. some favourable and some unfavourable, with the possibility of the limit-
  11811. ing types of 'ground' in which all members are favourable, or all members
  11812. are unfavourable. The proposition in question, whose probability is to be
  11813. estimated, must be known to be a member of the 'ground'; but no other
  11814. evidence, as to the set— favourable or unfavourable—to which t the propo-
  11815. sition belongs, enters into consideration. It is evident that 7 for the ulti-
  11816. mate ground, the phrase 'cases of equal probability' must be explicable
  11817. without reference to any notion of probability. The principle of such an
  11818. explanation is easily found by reference to the six faces of dice. A die is
  11819. a given fact; and its faces do not differ, qua faces, in any circumstance
  11820. relative to their fall with one face upwards or another face upwards. Also
  11821. beyond this given fact, there is ignorance. Thus again we are driven to an
  11822. ultimate fact: there must be an ultimate species, and the specific character
  11823. must be irrelevant to the 'favourableness' or 'unfavourableness' of the
  11824. members of the species in their capacity of cases. All this must be given
  11825. in direct knowledge without any appeal to probability. Also there must
  11826. be equally direct knowledge of the proportion of favourable or unfavour-
  11827. able cases within the species— at least within the limits of precision or
  11828. vagueness presupposed in the conclusion.
  11829.  
  11830. Thirdly, it is another requisite for a 'ground' that the number of in-
  11831. stances which it includes be finite. The whole theory of the ratios of car-
  11832. dinal numbers, on which [308] statistical probability depends, breaks down
  11833. when the cardinal numbers are infinite.
  11834.  
  11835. Fourthly, the method of 'sampling' professes to evade two objections.
  11836. One of them is the breakdown, mentioned above, when the number of
  11837. cases in the ground' is infinite. The other objection, thus evaded, is that
  11838. in practice the case in question is novel and does not belong to the
  11839. 'ground' which is in fact examined. According to this second objection,
  11840. unless there is some further evidence, the statistical state of the 'ground'
  11841. is bogus evidence as to the probability of the case in question. To sum
  11842. up: The method of sampling professes to overcome! (i) the difficulty
  11843. arising from the infinity of the ground; and (ii) that arising from the
  11844. novelty of the case in question, whereby it does not belong to the ground
  11845. examined. In the discussion it must be remembered that we are con-
  11846. sidering that ultimate ground which must not require any appeal to prob-
  11847. ability beyond itself. Thus the statistical facts as to the ground! must be
  11848. 'given' and not merely 'probable.'
  11849.  
  11850. (i) When we have ant infinite 'ground/ containing an infinite number
  11851. of favourable cases and an infinite number of unfavourable cases, 'random'
  11852. sampling can give no help towards the establishment of statistical proba-
  11853.  
  11854.  
  11855.  
  11856. The Propositions 203
  11857.  
  11858. bility; for one reason because no such notion of ratios can apply to these
  11859. infinities; and for another reason, no sample is 'random'; it has only fol-
  11860. lowed a complex method. A finite number of samples each following some
  11861. method of its own, however complex each method may be, will give a
  11862. statistical result entirely dependent upon those methods. In so far as
  11863. repetitions of so-called random samplings give concordant results, the only
  11864. conclusion to be drawn is that there is a relevant, though concealed, anal-
  11865. ogy between the 'random' methods. Thus a finite 'ground' is essential for
  11866. statistical probability. It must be understood that this argument implies
  11867. no criticism on a properly interpreted method of sampling applied to a
  11868. finite 'ground/
  11869.  
  11870. [309] (ii) When the 'case' in question does not belong to the ground
  11871. examined, theret can, apart from further information, be no rational in-
  11872. ference from the 'ground' to the novel case. If probability be in truth
  11873. purely statistical, and if there be no additional information, there can be
  11874. no escape from this conclusion. But we certainly do unhesitatingly argue
  11875. from a 'ground'' which does not include the case in question, to a probable
  11876. conclusion concerning the case in question. Thus either such an inference
  11877. is irrational, futile, useless; or, when there is justification, there is additional
  11878. information. This is the famous dilemma which perplexes the theories of
  11879. induction t and of probability.
  11880.  
  11881. SECTION VI
  11882.  
  11883. It is evident that the ultimate 'ground' to which all probable judgments
  11884. must refer can be nothing else than the actual world as objectified in judg-
  11885. ing subjects. A judging subject is always passing a judgment upon its own
  11886. data. Thus, if the statistical theory is to hold, the relations between the
  11887. judging subject and its data must be such as to evade the difficulties which
  11888. beset that theory.
  11889.  
  11890. Every actual entity is in its nature essentially social; and this in two
  11891. ways. First, the outlines of its own character are determined by the data
  11892. which its environment provides for its process of feeling. Secondly, these
  11893. data are not extrinsic to the entity; they constitute that display of the
  11894. universe which is inherent in the entity. Thus the data upon which the
  11895. subject passes judgment are themselves components conditioning the
  11896. character of the judging subject. It follows that any general presupposi-
  11897. tion as to the character of the experiencing subject also implies a general
  11898. presupposition as to the social environment providing the display for that
  11899. subject. In other words, a species of subject requires a species of data as
  11900. its preliminary phase of concrescence. But such data are nothing but the
  11901. social environment under the [310] abstraction effected by objectification.
  11902. Also the character of the abstraction itself depends on the environment.
  11903. The species of data requisite for the presumed judging subject presupposes
  11904. an environment of a certain social character.
  11905.  
  11906.  
  11907.  
  11908. 204 Discussions and Applications
  11909.  
  11910. Thus, according to the philosophy of organism, inductive reasoning
  11911. gains its validity by reason of a suppressed premise. This tacit presuppo-
  11912. sition is that the particular future which is the logical subject of the
  11913. judgment, inductively justified, shall include actualities which have close
  11914. analogy to some contemporary subject enjoying assigned experience; for
  11915. example, an analogy to the judging subject in question, or to some sort
  11916. of actuality presupposed as in the actual world which is the logical subject
  11917. of the inductive judgment. It is also presumed that this future is derived
  11918. from the present by a continuity of inheritance in which this condition
  11919. is maintained. There is thus the presupposition of the maintenance of the
  11920. general social environment— -eft/ier by reference to judging subjects, or
  11921. by more direct reference to the preservation of the general type of material
  11922. world requisite for the presupposed character of one or more of the logical
  11923. subjects of the proposition.
  11924.  
  11925. In this connection, I can only repeat, as a final summary, a paragraph
  11926. from my Science and the Modern World (Ch. Ill):
  11927. You will observe that I do not hold induction to be in its essence the
  11928. divinationt of general laws. It is the derivation of some characteristics
  11929. of a particular future from the known characteristics of a particular
  11930. past. The wider assumption of general laws holding for all cognizable
  11931. occasions appears a very unsafe addendum to attach to this limited
  11932. knowledge. All we can ask of the present occasion is that it shall
  11933. determine a particular community of occasions, which are in some
  11934. respects mutually qualified by reason of their inclusion within that
  11935. same community.
  11936. It is evident that, in this discussion of induction, the philosophy of or-
  11937. ganism [311] appears as an enlargement of the premise in ethical discus-
  11938. sions: that man is a social animal. Analogously, every actual occasion is
  11939. social, so that when we have presumed the existence of any persistent type
  11940. of actual occasions, we have thereby made presumptions as to types of
  11941. societies comprised in its environment. Another way of stating this ex-
  11942. planation of the validity of induction is, that in every forecast there is a
  11943. presupposition of a certain type of actual entities, and that the question
  11944. then asked is, Under what circumstances will these entities find them-
  11945. selves? The reason that an answer can be given is that the presupposed
  11946. type of entities requires a presupposed type of data for the primary phases
  11947. of these actual entities; and that a presupposed type of data requires a
  11948. presupposed type of social environment. But the laws of nature are the
  11949. outcome of the social environment. Hence when we have presupposed a
  11950. type of actual occasions, we have already some information as to the laws
  11951. of nature in operation throughout the environment.
  11952.  
  11953. In every inductive judgment, there is therefore contained a presupposi-
  11954. tion of the maintenance of the general order of the immediate environ-
  11955. ment, so far as concerns actual entities within the scope of the induction.
  11956. The inductive judgment has regard to the statistical probabilities inherent
  11957. in this given order. The anticipations are devoid of meaning apart from
  11958.  
  11959.  
  11960.  
  11961. The Propositions 205
  11962.  
  11963. the definite cosmic order which they presuppose. Also survival requires
  11964. order, and to presuppose survival, apart from the type of order which that
  11965. type of survival requires, is a contradiction. It is at this point that the
  11966. organic philosophy differs from any form of Cartesian 'substance-philoso-
  11967. phy/ For if a substance requires nothing but itself in order to exist, its
  11968. survival can tell no tale as to the survival of order in its environment. Thus
  11969. no conclusion can be drawn respecting the external relationships of the
  11970. surviving substance to its future environment. For [312] the organic phi-
  11971. losophy, anticipations as to the future of a piece of rock presuppose an
  11972. environment with the type of order which that piece of rock requires.
  11973. Thus the completely unknown environment never enters into an inductive
  11974. judgment. The induction is about the statistical probabilities of this en-
  11975. vironment, or about the graded relevance to it of eternal objects.
  11976.  
  11977. Thus the appeal to the mere unknown is automatically ruled out. The
  11978. question, as to what will happen to an unspecified entity in an unspecified
  11979. environment, has no answer. Induction always cocerns societies of actual
  11980. entities which are important for the stability of the immediate en-
  11981. vironment.
  11982.  
  11983.  
  11984.  
  11985. SECTION VII
  11986.  
  11987. In the preceding section there has been a covert appeal to probability.
  11988. It is the purpose of this section to explain how the probability, thus in-
  11989. voked, can be explained according to the statistical theory. First, we have
  11990. to note exactly where this appeal to probability enters into the notion of
  11991. induction. An inductive argument always includes a hypothesis, namely,
  11992. that the environment which is the subject-matter considered contains a
  11993. society of actual occasions analogous to a society in the present. But
  11994. analogous societies require analogous data for their several occasions; and
  11995. analogous data can be provided only by the objectifications provided by
  11996. analogous environments. But the laws of nature are derived from the
  11997. characters of the societies dominating the environment. Thus the laws of
  11998. nature dominating the environment in question have some analogy to
  11999. the laws of nature dominating the immediate environment.
  12000.  
  12001. Now the notions of 'analogy' and of 'dominance 7 both leave a margin
  12002. of uncertainty. We can ask, How far analogous? and How far dominant?
  12003. If there were exact analogy, and complete dominance, there would be a
  12004. mixture of certainty as to general conditions and of complete ignorance
  12005. as to specific details. But such a descrip- [313] tion does not apply either
  12006. to our knowledge of the immediate present, or of the past, or to our in-
  12007. ductive knowledge of the future. Our conscious experience involves a
  12008. baffling mixture of certainty, ignorance, and probability.
  12009.  
  12010. Now it is evident that the theory of cosmic epochs, due to the domi-
  12011. nance of societies of actual occasions, provides the basis for a statistical
  12012. explanation of probability. In any one epoch there are a definite set of
  12013.  
  12014.  
  12015.  
  12016. 206 Discussions and Applications
  12017.  
  12018. dominant societies in certain ordered interconnections. There is also an
  12019. admixture of chaotic occasions which cannot be classified as belonging to
  12020. any society. But, having regard to the enornious extension of any cosmic
  12021. epoch, we are practically dealing with infinities, so that some method of
  12022. sampling is required, rooted in the nature of the case and not arbitrarily
  12023. adopted.
  12024.  
  12025. This natural method of sampling is provided by the data which form
  12026. the primary phase of any one actual occasion. Each actual occasion ob-
  12027. jectifies the other actual occasions in its environment. This environment
  12028. can be limited to the relevant portion of the cosmic epoch. It is a finite
  12029. region of the extensive continuum, so far as adequate importance is con-
  12030. cerned in respect to individual differences among actual occasions. Also,
  12031. in respect to the importance of individual differences, we may assume
  12032. that there is a lower limit to the extension of each relevant occasion within
  12033. this region. With these two presumptions, it follows that the relevant
  12034. objectifications, forming the relevant data for any one occasion, refer to
  12035. a finite sample of actual occasions in the environment. Accordingly our
  12036. knowledge of the external world, and of the conditions upon which its
  12037. laws depend, t is, through and through, of that numerical character which
  12038. a statistical theory of probability requires. Such a theory does not require
  12039. that exact statistical calculations bet made. All that is meant by such a
  12040. theory is that our probability judgments are ultimately derivable from
  12041. vague estimates of 'more or less' in a numerical sense. [314] We have an
  12042. unprecise intuition of the statistical basis of the sort of way in which
  12043. things happen.
  12044.  
  12045. Note. — By far the best discussion of the philosophical theory of probability
  12046. is to be found in Mr. }. Maynard Keynes' book, A Treatise on Probability. This
  12047. treatise must long remain the standard work on the subject. My conclusions in
  12048. this chapter do not seem to me to differ fundamentally from those of Mr.
  12049. Keynes as set out towards the conclusion of his Chapter XXI. But Mr. Keynes
  12050. here seems to revert to a view of probability very analogous to that form of the
  12051. 'frequency theory' which, as suggested by me,f he criticized acutely (and rightly,
  12052. so far as concerned that special form) in his Chapter VIII.
  12053.  
  12054. SECTION VIII
  12055.  
  12056. So far the argument of the three! preceding sections has been devoted
  12057. to the explanation of the statistical ground for a probability judgment. But
  12058. the same discussion also discloses an alternative non-statistical ground for
  12059. such a judgment.
  12060.  
  12061. The main line of thought has been (i) that each actual occasion has at
  12062. the base of its own constitution the environment from which it springs;
  12063. (ii) that in this function of the environment abstraction has been made
  12064. from its indefinite multiplicity of forms of definiteness, so as to obtain a
  12065. concordant experience of the elements retained; (in) that any actual oc-
  12066. casion belonging to an assigned species requires an environment adapted
  12067.  
  12068.  
  12069.  
  12070. The Propositions 207
  12071.  
  12072. to that species, so that the presupposition of a species involves a pre-
  12073. supposition concerning the environment; (iv) that in every inductive judg-
  12074. ment, and in every judgment of probability, there is a presupposition, im-
  12075. plicit or explicit, of one, or more, species of actual occasions implicated in
  12076. the situation considered, so that, by (iii),t there is a presupposition of
  12077. some general type of environment.
  12078.  
  12079. Thus the basis of all probability and induction is the fact of analogy
  12080. between an environment presupposed and an environment directly ex-
  12081. perienced.
  12082.  
  12083. The argument, as to the statistical basis of probability, then recurred to
  12084. the doctrine of social order. According to this doctrine, all social order
  12085. depends on the statistical dominance in the environment of occasions be-
  12086. longing [315] to the requisite societies. The laws of nature are statistical
  12087. laws derived from this fact. Thus the judgment of probability can be
  12088. derived from an intuition— in general vague and imprecise— as to the sta-
  12089. tistical basis of the presupposed environment. This judgment can be de-
  12090. rived from the analogy with the experienced environment. There will be
  12091. such factors in experience adequate to justify a judgment of the inductive
  12092. type.
  12093.  
  12094. But there is another factor from which, in combination with the four
  12095. premises, a non-statistical judgment of probability can be derived. The
  12096. principle of the graduated 'intensive relevance' of eternal objects to the
  12097. primary physical data of experience expresses a real fact as to the pref-
  12098. erential adaptation of selected eternal objects to novel occasions originat-
  12099. ing from an assigned environment.
  12100.  
  12101. This principle expresses the prehension by every creature of the grad-
  12102. uated order of appetitions constituting the primordial nature of God.
  12103. There can thus be an intuition of an intrinsic suitability of some definite
  12104. outcome from a presupposed situation. There will be nothing statistical in
  12105. this suitability. It depends upon the fundamental graduation of appeti-
  12106. tions which lies at the base of things, and which solves all indeterminations
  12107. of transition.
  12108.  
  12109. In this way, there can be an intuition of probability respecting the origi-
  12110. nation of some novelty. It is evident that the statistical theory entirely
  12111. fails to provide any basis for such judgments.
  12112.  
  12113. It must not be thought that these non-statistical judgments are in any
  12114. sense religious. They lie at a far lower level of experience than do the
  12115. religious emotions. The secularization of the concept of God's functions
  12116. in the world is at least as urgent a requisite of thought as is the seculariza-
  12117. tion of other elements in experience. The concept of God is certainly one
  12118. essential element in religious feeling. But the converse is not true; the
  12119. concept of religious feeling is not an essential element in the con- [316] cept
  12120. of God's function in the universe. In this respect religious literature has
  12121. been sadly misleading to philosophic theory, partly by attraction and partly
  12122. by repulsion.
  12123.  
  12124.  
  12125.  
  12126. CHAPTER X
  12127. PROCESS
  12128.  
  12129. SECTION I
  12130.  
  12131. [317] That all things flow' is the first vague generalization which the
  12132. unsystematized, barely analysed, intuition of men has produced. It is the
  12133. theme of some of the best Hebrew poetry in the Psalms; it appears as one
  12134. of the first generalizations of Greek philosophy in the form of the saying
  12135. of Heraclitus; amid the later barbarism of Anglo-Saxon thought it reappears
  12136. in the story of the sparrow flitting through the banqueting? hall of the
  12137. Northumbrian king; and in all stages of civilization its recollection lends
  12138. its pathos to poetry. Without doubt, if we are to go back to that ultimate,
  12139. integral experience, unwarped by the sophistications of theory, that ex-
  12140. perience whose elucidation is the final aim of philosophy, the flux of things
  12141. is one ultimate generalization around which we must weave our philo-
  12142. sophical system.
  12143.  
  12144. At this point we have transformed the phrase, 'all things flow/ into the
  12145. alternative phrase, 'the flux of things.' In so doing, the notion of the 'flux'
  12146. has been held up before our thoughts as one primary notion for further
  12147. analysis. But in the sentence 'all things flow,' there are three words— and
  12148. we have started by isolating the last word of the three. We move back-
  12149. ward to the next word 'things' and ask. What sort of things flow? Finally
  12150. we reach the first word 'all' and ask, What is the meaning of the 'many'
  12151. things engaged in this common flux, and in what sense, if any, can the
  12152. word 'all' refer to a definitely indicated set of these many things?
  12153.  
  12154. The elucidation of meaning involved in the phrase 'all things flow't is
  12155. one chief task of metaphysics.
  12156.  
  12157. [318] But there is a rival notion, antithetical to the former. I cannot
  12158. at the moment recall one immortal phrase which expresses it with the
  12159. same completeness as that with which! the alternative notion has been
  12160. rendered by Heraclitus. This other notion dwells on permanences of
  12161. things— the solid earth, the mountains, the stones, the Egyptian Pyramids,
  12162. the spirit of man, God,
  12163.  
  12164. The best rendering of integral experience, expressing its general form
  12165. divested of irrelevant details, is often to be found in the utterances of
  12166. religious aspiration. One of the reasons of the thinness of so much modern
  12167. metaphysics is its neglect of this wealth of expression of ultimate feeling.
  12168.  
  12169. 208
  12170.  
  12171.  
  12172.  
  12173. Process 209
  12174.  
  12175. Accordingly we find in the first two lines of a famous hymn a full ex-
  12176. pression of the union of the two notions in one integral experience:
  12177.  
  12178. Abide with me;
  12179.  
  12180. Fast falls the eventide.
  12181.  
  12182. Here the first line expresses the permanences, 'abide/ 'me' and the 'Being'
  12183. addressed; and the second line sets these permanences amid the inescapable
  12184. flux. Here at length we find formulated the complete problem of meta-
  12185. physics. Those philosophers who start with the first line have given us the
  12186. metaphysics of 'substance 7 ; and those who start with the second line have
  12187. developed the metaphysics of 'flux/ But, in truth, the two lines cannot be
  12188. torn apart in this way; and we find that a wavering balance between the
  12189. two is a characteristic of the greater number of philosophers. Plato found
  12190. his permanences in a static, spiritual heaven, and his flux in the entangle-
  12191. ment of his forms amid the fluent imperfections of the physical world.
  12192. Here I draw attention to the word 'imperfection/ In any assertion as to
  12193. Plato I speak under correction; but I believe that Plato's authority can be
  12194. claimed for the doctrine that the things that flow are imperfect in the
  12195. sense of 'limited' and of 'definitely exclusive of much that they might be
  12196. and are not/ The lines quoted from the hymn are an almost perfect
  12197. expres- [3 J 9] sion of the direct intuition from which the main position of
  12198. the Platonic philosophy is derived. Aristotle corrected his Platonism into
  12199. a somewhat different! balance. He was the apostle of 'substance and at-
  12200. tribute/ and of the classifies tory logic which this notion suggests. But, on
  12201. the other side, he makes a masterly analysis of the notion of 'generation/
  12202. Aristotle in his own person expressed a useful protest against the Platonic
  12203. tendency to separate a static spiritual world from a fluent world of super-
  12204. ficial experience. The later Platonic schools stressed this tendency: just as
  12205. the mediaeval Aristotelian thought allowed the static notions of Aristotle's
  12206. logic to formulate some of the main metaphysical problems in terms which
  12207. have lasted till today.
  12208.  
  12209. On the whole, the history of philosophy supports Bergson's charge that
  12210. the human intellect 'spatializes the universe'; that is to say, that it tends
  12211. to ignore the fluency, and to analyse the world in terms of static categories.
  12212. Indeed Bergson went further and conceived this tendency as an inherent
  12213. necessity of the intellect. I do not believe this accusation; but I do hold
  12214. that 'spatialization' is the shortest route to a clear-cut philosophy expressed
  12215. in reasonably familiar language. Descartes gave an almost perfect example
  12216. of such a system of thought. The difficulties of Cartesianism with its
  12217. three clear-cut substances, and with its 'duration' and 'measured time'
  12218. well in the background, illustrate the result of the subordination of fluency.
  12219. This subordination is to be found in the unanalysed longing of the hymn,
  12220. in Plato's vision of heavenly perfection, in Aristotle's logical concepts,
  12221. and in Descartes' mathematical mentality. Newton, that Napoleon of the
  12222. world of thought, brusquely ordered fluency back into the world, regi-
  12223.  
  12224.  
  12225.  
  12226. 210 Discussions and Applications
  12227.  
  12228. merited into his 'absolute mathematical time, flowing equably without
  12229. regard to anything external/ He also gave it a mathematical uniform in
  12230. the shape of his Theory of Fluxions.
  12231.  
  12232. At this point the group of seventeenth- and eighteenth- [320] century
  12233. philosophers practically made a discovery, which, although it lies on the
  12234. surface of their writings, they only half-realized. The discovery is that
  12235. there are two kinds of fluency. One kind is the concrescence\ which, in
  12236. Locke's language, is 'the real internal constitution of a particular existent/
  12237. The other kind is the transition from particular existent to particular
  12238. existent. This transition, again in Locke's language, is the 'perpetually
  12239. perishing' which is one aspect of the notion of time; and in another aspect
  12240. the transition is the origination of the present in conformity with the
  12241. 'power' of the past.
  12242.  
  12243. The phrase 'the real internal constitution of a particular existent/ the
  12244. description of the human understanding as a process of reflection upon
  12245. data, the phrase 'perpetually perishing/ and the word 'power' together
  12246. with its elucidation are all to be found in Locke's Essay. Yet owing to the
  12247. limited scope of his investigation Locke did not generalize or put his
  12248. scattered ideas together. This implicit notion of the two kinds of flux finds
  12249. further unconscious illustration in Hume, It is all but explicit in Kant,
  12250. though— as I think— misdescribed. Finally, it is lost in the evolutionary
  12251. monism of Hegel and of his derivative schools. With all his inconsistencies,
  12252. Locke is the philosopher to whom it is most useful to recur, when we de-
  12253. sire to make explicit the discovery of the two kinds of fluency, required for
  12254. the description of the fluent world. One kind is the fluency inherent in the
  12255. constitution of the particular existent. This kind I have called 'concres-
  12256. cence.' The other kind is the fluency whereby the perishing of the process,
  12257. on the completion of the particular existent, constitutes that existent as
  12258. an original element in the constitutions of other particular existents
  12259. elicited by repetitions of process. This kind I have called 'transition/ Con-
  12260. crescence moves towards its final cause, which is its subjective aim; transi-
  12261. tion is the vehicle of the efficient cause, which is the immortal past.
  12262.  
  12263. The discussion of how the actual particular occasions become original
  12264. elements for a new creation is termed [32 1] the theory of objectifi cation.
  12265. The objectified particular occasions together have the unity of a datum for
  12266. the creative concrescence. But in acquiring this measure of connection,
  12267. their inherent presuppositions of each other eliminate certain elements
  12268. in their constitutions, and elicit into relevance other elements. Thus ob-
  12269. jectification is an operation of mutually adjusted abstraction, or elimina-
  12270. tion, whereby the many occasions of the actual world become one complex
  12271. datum. This fact of the elimination by reason of synthesis is sometimes
  12272. termed the perspective of the actual world from the standpoint of
  12273. that concrescence. Each actual occasion defines its own actual world
  12274. from which it originates. No two occasions can have identical actual
  12275. worlds.
  12276.  
  12277.  
  12278.  
  12279. Process 211
  12280.  
  12281.  
  12282.  
  12283. SECTION II
  12284.  
  12285. 'Concrescence' is the name for the process in which the universe of
  12286. many things acquires an individual unity in a determinate relegation of
  12287. each item of the 'many' to its subordination in the constitution of the
  12288. novel 'one/
  12289.  
  12290. The most general term 'thing'— or, equivalently, 'entity'— means nothing
  12291. else than to be one of the 'many' which find their niches in each instance
  12292. of concrescence. Each instance of concrescence is itself the novel indi-
  12293. vidual 'thing' in question. There are not 'the concrescence' and 'the! novel
  12294. thing': when we analyse the novel thing we find nothing but the concres-
  12295. cence. 'Actuality' means nothing else than this ultimate entry into the
  12296. concrete, in abstraction from which there is mere nonentity. In other
  12297. words, abstraction from the notion of 'entry into the concrete' is a self-
  12298. contradictory notion, since it asks us to conceive a thing as not a thing.
  12299.  
  12300. An instance of concrescence is termed an 'actual entity'— or, equiva-
  12301. lently, an 'actual occasion.' There is not one completed set of things which
  12302. are actual occasions. For the fundamental inescapable fact is the creativity
  12303. [322] in virtue of which there can be no 'many things' which are not sub-
  12304. ordinated in a concrete unity. Thus a set of all actual occasions is by the
  12305. nature of things a standpoint for another concrescence which elicits a con-
  12306. crete unity from those many actual occasions. Thus we can never survey
  12307. the actual world except from the standpoint of an immediate concrescence
  12308. which is falsifying the presupposed completion. The creativity in virtue of
  12309. which any relative** complete actual world is, by the nature of things, the
  12310. datum for a new concrescencet is termed 'transition.' Thus, by reason of
  12311. transition, 'the actual world' is always a relative term, and refers to that
  12312. basis of presupposed actual occasions which is a datum for the novel
  12313. concrescence.
  12314.  
  12315. An actual occasion is analysable. The analysis discloses operations trans-
  12316. forming entities which are individually alien t into components of a com-
  12317. plex which is concretely one. The term 'feeling' will be used as the generic
  12318. description of such operations. We thus say that an actual occasion is a
  12319. concrescence effected by a process of feelings.
  12320.  
  12321. A feeling can be considered in respect to (i) the actual occasions felt,
  12322. (ii) the eternal objects felt, (hi) the feelings felt, and (iv) its own sub-
  12323. jective forms of intensity. In the process of concrescence the diverse feel-
  12324. ings pass on to wider generalities of integral feeling.
  12325.  
  12326. Such a wider generality is a feeling of a complex of feelings, including
  12327. their specific elements of identity and contrast. This process of the integra-
  12328. tion of feeling proceeds until the concrete unity of feeling is obtained. In
  12329. this concrete unity all indetermination as to the realization of possibilities
  12330. has been eliminated. The many entities of the universe, including those
  12331. originating in the concrescence itself, find their respective roles in this
  12332.  
  12333.  
  12334.  
  12335. 212 Discussions and Applications
  12336.  
  12337. final unity. This final unity is termed the 'satisfaction.' The 'satisfaction'
  12338. is the culmination of the concrescence into a completely determinate
  12339. matter of fact. In any of its antecedent stages the concrescence exhibits
  12340. sheer inde- [323] termination as to the nexus between its many components.
  12341.  
  12342. SECTION III
  12343.  
  12344. An actual occasion is nothing but the unity to be ascribed to a particular
  12345. instance of concrescence. This concrescence is thus nothing else than the
  12346. 'real internal constitution' of the actual occasion in question. The analysis
  12347. of the formal constitution of an actual entity has given three stages in the
  12348. process of feeling: (i) the responsive phase, (ii) the supplemental stage,
  12349. and (hi) the satisfaction.
  12350.  
  12351. The satisfaction is merely the culmination marking the evaporation of
  12352. all indetermination; so that, in respect to all modes of feeling and to all
  12353. entities in the universe, the satisfied actual entity embodies a determinate
  12354. attitude of 'yes' or 'no/ Thus the satisfaction is the attainment of the
  12355. private ideal which is the final cause of the concrescence. But the process
  12356. itself lies in the two former phases. The first phase is the phase of pure
  12357. reception of the actual world in its guise of objective datum for aesthetic
  12358. synthesis. In this phase there is the mere reception of the actual world as
  12359. a multiplicity of private centres of feeling, implicated in a nexus of mutual
  12360. presupposition. The feelings are felt as belonging to the external centres,
  12361. and are not absorbed into the private immediacy. The second stage is
  12362. governed by the private ideal, gradually shaped in the process itself;
  12363. whereby the many feelings, derivatively felt as alien, are transformed into
  12364. a unity of aesthetic appreciation immediately felt as private. This is the
  12365. incoming of 'appetition/ which in its higher exemplifications we term
  12366. 'vision.' In the language of physical science, the 'scalar' form overwhelms
  12367. the original 'vector' form: the origins become subordinate to the individual
  12368. experience. The vector form is not lost, but is submerged as the founda-
  12369. tion of the scalar superstructure.
  12370.  
  12371. In this second stage the feelings assume an emotional [324] character
  12372. by reason of this influx of conceptual feelings. But the reason why the
  12373. origins are not lost in the private emotion is that there is no element in
  12374. the universe capable of pure privacy. If we could obtain a complete analy-
  12375. sis of meaning, the notion of pure privacy would be seen to be self-
  12376. contradictory. Emotional feeling is still subject to the third metaphysical
  12377. principle,** that to be 'something' is 'to have the potentiality for acquiring
  12378. real unity with other entities.' Hence, 'to be a real component of an actual
  12379. entity' is in some way 'to realize this potentiality.' Thus 'emotion' is 'emo-
  12380. tional feeling ; and Vhat is felt' is the presupposed vector situation. In
  12381. physical science this principle takes the form which should never be lost
  12382. sight of in fundamental speculation, that scalar quantities are constructs
  12383. derivative from vector quantities. In more familiar language, this prin-
  12384.  
  12385.  
  12386.  
  12387. Process 213
  12388.  
  12389. ciple can be expressed by the statement that the notion of 'passing on' is
  12390. more fundamental than that of a private individual fact. In the abstract
  12391. language here adopted for metaphysical statement, 'passing on 7 becomes
  12392. 'creativity/ in the dictionary sense of the verb create, 'to bring forth, beget,
  12393. produce/ Thus, according to the third principle, no entity can be divorced
  12394. from the notion of creativity. An entity is at least a particular form
  12395. capable of infusing its own particularity into creativity. An actual entity,
  12396. or a phase of an actual entity, is more than that; but, at least, it is that.
  12397.  
  12398. Locke's 'particular ideas' are merely the antecedent actual entities exer-
  12399. cising their function of infusing with their own particularity the 'passing
  12400. on/t which is the primary phase of the 'real internal constitution' of the
  12401. actual entity in question. In obedience to a prevalent misconception,
  12402. 'Locke termed this latter entity the 'mind'; and discussed its 'furniture/
  12403. when he should have discussed 'mental operations' in their capacity of
  12404. later phases in the constitutions of actual entities. Locke himself flittingly
  12405. expresses this fundamental vector function of his 'ideas/ In a paragraph,
  12406. forming a portion of a quotation already [325] made, he writes: "I confess
  12407. power includes in it some kind of relation,— a relation to action or change;
  12408. as, indeed, which of our ideas, of what kind soever, when attentively con-
  12409. sidered, does not?" x
  12410.  
  12411. SECTION IV
  12412.  
  12413. The second phase, that of supplementation, divides itself into two
  12414. subordinate phases. Both of these phases may be trivial; also they are not
  12415. truly separable, since they interfere with each other by intensification or
  12416. inhibition. If both phases are trivial, the whole second phase is merely the
  12417. definite negation of individual origination; and the process passes passively
  12418. to its satisfaction. The actual entity is then the mere vehicle for the trans-
  12419. ference of inherited constitutions of feeling. Its private immediacy passes
  12420. out of the picture. Of these two sub-phases, the former— so far as there is
  12421. an order— is that of aesthetic supplement, and the latter is that of intel-
  12422. lectual supplement.
  12423.  
  12424. In the aesthetic supplement there is an emotional appreciation of the
  12425. contrasts and rhythms inherent in the unification of the objective content
  12426. in the concrescence of one actual occasion. In this phase perception is
  12427. heightened by its assumption of pain and pleasure, beauty and distaste.
  12428. It is the phase of inhibitions and intensifications. It is the phase in which
  12429. blue becomes more intense by reason of its contrasts, and shape acquires
  12430. dominance by reason of its loveliness. What was received as alien, has
  12431. been recreated as private. This is the phase of perceptivity, including
  12432. emotional reactions to perceptivity. In this phase, private immediacy has
  12433. welded the data into a new fact of blind feeling. Pure aesthetic supple-
  12434.  
  12435. 1 Essay, II, XXI, 3.t
  12436.  
  12437.  
  12438.  
  12439. 214 Discussions and Applications
  12440.  
  12441. ment has solved its problem. This phase requires an influx of conceptual
  12442. feelings and their integration with the pure physical feelings .
  12443.  
  12444. But 'blindness' of the process, so far, retains an indetermination. There
  12445. must be either a determinate nega- [326] tion of intellectual 'sight/ or an
  12446. admittance of intellectual 'sight/ The negationt of intellectual sight is
  12447. the dismissal into irrelevancet of eternal objects in their abstract status of
  12448. pure potentials. 'What might be' has the capability of relevant contrast
  12449. with 'what is/ If the pure potentials, in this abstract capacity, are dis-
  12450. missed from relevance, the second sub-phase is trivial. The process then
  12451. constitutes a blind actual occasion, 'blind' in the sense that no intellectual
  12452. operations are involved; though conceptual operations are always involved.
  12453. Thus there is always mentality in the form of 'vision/ but not always
  12454. mentality in the form of conscious 'intellectuality/
  12455.  
  12456. But if some eternal objects, in their abstract capacity, are realized as
  12457. relevant to actual fact, there is an actual occasion with intellectual opera-
  12458. tions. The complex of such intellectual operations is sometimes termed the
  12459. 'mind' of the actual occasion; and the actual occasion is also termed
  12460. 'conscious/ But the term 'mind' conveys the suggestion of independent
  12461. substance. This is not meant here: a better term is the 'consciousness'
  12462. belonging to the actual occasion.
  12463.  
  12464. An eternal object realized in respect to its pure potentiality as related
  12465. to determinate logical subjects is termed a 'prepositional feeling' in the
  12466. mentality of the actual occasion in question. The consciousness belonging
  12467. to an actual occasion is its sub-phase of intellectual supplementation, when
  12468. that sub-phase is not purely trivial. This sub-phase is the eliciting, into
  12469. feeling, oft the full contrast between mere propositional potentiality and
  12470. realized fact.
  12471.  
  12472. SECTION V
  12473.  
  12474. To sum up: There are two species of process, macroscopic! process, and
  12475. microscopic process. The macroscopic process is the transition from at-
  12476. tained actuality to actuality in attainment; while the microscopic process
  12477. is the conversion of conditions which are merely real into determinate
  12478. actuality. The former process effects the [327] transition from the 'actual'
  12479. to the 'merely real'; and the latter process effects the growth from the real
  12480. to the actual. The former process is efficient; the latter process ist teleo-
  12481. logical. The future is merely real, without being actual; whereas the past
  12482. is a nexus of actualities. The actualities are constituted by their real genetic
  12483. phases. The present is the immediacy of teleological process whereby
  12484. reality becomes actual. The former process provides the conditions which
  12485. really govern attainment; whereas the latter process provides the ends
  12486. actually attained. The notion of 'organism' is combined with that of
  12487. 'process' in a twofold manner. The community of actual things is an
  12488. organism; but it is not a static organism. It is an incompletion in process
  12489.  
  12490.  
  12491.  
  12492. Process 215
  12493.  
  12494. of production. Thus the expansion of the universe in respect to actual
  12495. things is the first meaning of 'process'; and the universe in any stage of
  12496. its expansion is the first meaning of 'organism/ In this sense, an organism
  12497. is a nexus.
  12498.  
  12499. Secondly, each actual entity is itself only describable as an organic pro-
  12500. cess. It repeats in microcosm what the universe is in macrocosm. It is a
  12501. process proceeding from phase to phase, each phase being the real basis
  12502. from which its successor proceeds towards the completion of the thing
  12503. in question. Each actual entity bears in its constitution the 'reasons' why
  12504. its conditions are what they are. These 'reasons' are the other actual en-
  12505. tities objectified for it.
  12506.  
  12507. An 'object' is a transcendent element characterizing that definiteness
  12508. to which our 'experience' has to conform. In this sense, the future has
  12509. objective reality in the present, but no formal actuality. For it is inherent
  12510. in the constitution of the immediate, present actuality that a future will
  12511. supersede it. Also conditions to which that future must conform, includ-
  12512. ing real relationships to the present, are really objective in the immediate
  12513. actuality.
  12514.  
  12515. Thus each actual entity, although complete so far as concerns its micro-
  12516. scopic process, is yet incomplete by reason of its objective inclusion of
  12517. the macroscopicf [328] process. It really experiences a future which must
  12518. be actual, although the completed actualities of that future are undeter-
  12519. mined. In this sense, each actual occasion experiences its own objective
  12520. immortality.
  12521.  
  12522. Note. — The function here ascribed to an 'object' is in general agreement with
  12523. a paragraph (p. 249, 2nd! edition) in Professor Kemp Smith's Commentary on
  12524. Kant's Critique, where he is considering Kant's 'Objective Deduction' as in the
  12525. first edition of the Critique: "When we examine the objective, we find that the
  12526. primary characteristic distinguishing it from the subjective is that it lays a com-
  12527. pulsion upon our minds, constraining us to think about it in a certain way. By
  12528. an object is meant something which will not allow us to think at haphazard."
  12529.  
  12530. There is of course the vital difference, among others, that where Kemp Smith,
  12531. expounding Kant, writes 'thinking/ the philosophy of organism substitutes
  12532. 'experiencing.'
  12533.  
  12534.  
  12535.  
  12536. PART III
  12537. THE THEORY OF PREHENSIONS
  12538.  
  12539.  
  12540.  
  12541. CHAPTER I
  12542. THE THEORY OF FEELINGS
  12543.  
  12544. SECTION I
  12545.  
  12546. [334] The philosophy of organism is a cell-theory of actuality. Each ul-
  12547. timate unit of fact is a cell-complex, not analysable into components with
  12548. equivalent completeness of actuality.
  12549.  
  12550. The cell can be considered genetically and morphologically. The ge-
  12551. netic theoryt is considered in this part; [335] the morphological theory is
  12552. considered in Part IV, under the title of the 'extensive analysis' of an
  12553. actual entity.
  12554.  
  12555. In the genetic theory, the cell is exhibited as appropriating for the
  12556. foundation of its own existence, the various elements of the universe out
  12557. of which it arises. Each process of appropriation of a particular element
  12558. is termed a prehension. The ultimate elements of the universe, thus ap-
  12559. propriated, are the already constituted! actual entities, and the eternal
  12560. objects. All the actual entities are positively prehended, but only a selec-
  12561. tion of the eternal objects. In the course of the integrations of these
  12562. various prehensions, entities of other categoreal types become relevant;
  12563. and some new entities of these types, such as novel propositions and
  12564. generic contrasts, come into existence. These relevant entities of these
  12565. other types are also prehended into the constitution of the concrescent
  12566. cell. This genetic process has now to be traced in its main outlines.
  12567.  
  12568. An actual entity is a process in the course of which many operations
  12569. with incomplete subjective unity terminate in a completed unity of opera-
  12570. tion, termed the 'satisfaction/ The 'satisfaction' is the contentment of
  12571. the creative urge by the fulfilment of its categoreal demands. The analysis
  12572. of these categories is one aim of metaphysics.
  12573.  
  12574. The process itself is the constitution of the actual entity; in Locke's
  12575. phrase, it is the 'real internal constitution' of the actual entity. In the
  12576. older phraseology employed by Descartes, the process is what the actual
  12577. entity is in itself, Jormaliter. 7 The terms 'formal' and 'formally' are here
  12578. used in this sense.
  12579.  
  12580. The terminal unity of operation, here called the 'satisfaction/ embodies
  12581. what the actual entity is beyond itself. In Locke's phraseology, the 'powers'
  12582. of the actual entity are discovered in the analysis of the satisfaction. In
  12583. Descartes' phraseology, the satisfaction is the actual entity considered as
  12584. analysable in respect to its existence [336] 'objective,'* It is the actual
  12585. entity as a definite, determinate, settled fact, stubborn and with unavoid-
  12586.  
  12587. 219
  12588.  
  12589.  
  12590.  
  12591. 220 The Theory of Prehensions
  12592.  
  12593. able consequences. The actual entity as described by the morphology of
  12594. its satisfaction is the actual entity 'spatialized/ to use Bergson's term. The
  12595. actual entity, thus spatialized, is at given individual fact actuated by its
  12596. own 'substantial form/ Its own process, which is its own internal existence,
  12597. has evaporated, worn out and satisfied; but its effects are all to be described
  12598. in terms of its "satisfaction/ The 'effects' of an actual entity are its in-
  12599. terventions in concrescent processes other than its own. Any entity, thus
  12600. intervening in processes transcending itself, is said to be functioning as an
  12601. 'object/ According to the fourth Category of Explanation it is the one
  12602. general metaphysical character of all entities of all sorts, that they function
  12603. as objects. It is this metaphysical character which constitutes the solidarity
  12604. of the universe. The peculiarity of an actual entity is that it can be con-
  12605. sidered both 'objectively' and 'formally/ The 'objective' aspect is mor-
  12606. phological so far as that actual entity is concerned: by this it is meant
  12607. that the process involved is transcendent relatively to it, so that the esse
  12608. of its satisfaction is sentiri. The 'formal' aspect is functional so far as that
  12609. actual entity is concerned: by this it is meant that the process involved is
  12610. immanent in it. But the objective consideration is pragmatic. It is the
  12611. consideration of the actual entity in respect to its consequences. In the
  12612. present chapter the emphasis is laid upon the formal consideration of an
  12613. actual entity. But this formal consideration of one actual entity requires
  12614. reference to the objective intervention of other actual entities. This ob-
  12615. jective intervention of other entities constitutes the creative character
  12616. which conditions the concrescence in question. The satisfaction of each
  12617. actual entity is an element in the givenness of the universe: it limits bound-
  12618. less, abstract possibility into the particular real potentiality from which
  12619. each novel concrescence originates. The 'boundless, abstract possibility'
  12620. means the creativity [337] considered solely in reference to the possibilities
  12621. of the intervention of eternal objects, and in abstraction from the ob-
  12622. jective intervention of actual entities belonging to any definite actual
  12623. world, including God among the actualities abstracted from.
  12624.  
  12625. SECTION II
  12626.  
  12627. The possibility of finite truths depends on the fact that the satisfaction
  12628. of an actual entity is divisible into a variety of determinate operations.
  12629. The operations are 'prehensions/ But the negative prehensions which con-
  12630. sist of exclusions from contribution to the concrescence can be treated
  12631. in their subordination to the positive prehensions. These positive prehen-
  12632. sions are termed 'feelings/ The process of concrescence is divisible into
  12633. an initial stage of many feelings, and a succession of subsequent phases
  12634. of more complex feelings integrating the earlier simpler feelings, up to
  12635. the satisfaction which is one complex unity of feeling. This is the genetic'
  12636. analysis of the satisfaction. Its 'coordinate' analysis will be given later,
  12637. in Part IV.
  12638.  
  12639.  
  12640.  
  12641. The Theory of Feelings 221
  12642.  
  12643. Thus a component feeling in the satisfaction is to be assigned, for its
  12644. origination, to an earlier phase of the concrescence.
  12645.  
  12646. This is the general description of the divisible character of the satis-
  12647. faction, from the genetic standpoint. The extensiveness which underlies
  12648. the spatio-temporal relations of the universe is another outcome of this
  12649. divisible character. Also the abstraction from its own full formal consti-
  12650. tution involved in objectifications of one actual entity in the constitu-
  12651. tions of other actual entities equally depends upon this same divisible
  12652. character, whereby the actual entity is conveyed in the particularity of
  12653. some one of its feelings. A feeling— i.e., a positive prehension — is essen-
  12654. tially a transition effecting a concrescence. Its complex constitution is
  12655. analysable into five factors which express what that transition consists of,
  12656. and effects. The factors are: (i) the 'subject' which feels, (ii) the 'initial
  12657. [338] data' which are to be felt, (iii) the 'elimination' in virtue of nega-
  12658. tive prehensions, (iv) the 'objective datum 7 which is felt, (v) the 'sub-
  12659. jective form* which is how that subject feels that objective datum.
  12660.  
  12661. A feeling is in all respects determinate, with a determinate subject,
  12662. determinate initial data, determinate negative prehensions, a determinate
  12663. objective datum, and a determinate subjective form. There is a transition
  12664. from the initial data to the objective datum effected by the elimination.
  12665. The initial data constitute a 'multiplicity/ or merely one 'proper' entity,
  12666. while the objective datum is a 'nexus/ a proposition, or a 'proper' entity
  12667. of some categoreal type. There is a concrescence of the initial data into the
  12668. objective datum, made possible by the elimination, and effected by the
  12669. subjective form. The objective datum is the perspective of the initial data.i
  12670. The subjective form receives its determination from the negative prehen-
  12671. sions, the objective datum, and the conceptual origination of the subject.
  12672. The negative prehensions are determined by the categoreal conditions
  12673. governing feelings, by the subjective form, and by the initial data. This
  12674. mutual determination of the elements involved in a feeling is one expres-
  12675. sion of the truth that the subject of the feeling is causa sui. The partial
  12676. nature of a feeling, other than the complete satisfaction, is manifest by the
  12677. impossibility of understanding its generation without recourse to the whole
  12678. subject. There is a mutual sensitivity of feelings in one subject, governed by
  12679. categoreal conditions. This mutual sensitivity expresses the notion of final
  12680. causation in the guise of a pre-established harmony.
  12681.  
  12682. SECTION III
  12683.  
  12684. A feeling cannot be abstracted from the actual entity entertaining it.
  12685. This actual entity is termed the 'subject' of the feeling. It is in virtue of
  12686. its subject that the feeling is one thing. If we abstract the subject from
  12687. the feeling we are left with many things. Thus a feeling is [339] a particu-
  12688. lar in the same sense in which each actual entity is a particular. It is one
  12689. aspect of its own subject.
  12690.  
  12691.  
  12692.  
  12693. 222 The Theory of Prehensions
  12694.  
  12695. The term 'subject' has been retained because in this sense it is familiar
  12696. in philosophy. But it is misleading. The term 'superject* would be better.
  12697. The subject-superject is the purpose of the process originating the feelings.
  12698. The feelings are inseparable from the end at which they aim; and this end
  12699. is the feeler. The feelings aim at the feeler, as their final cause. The feelings
  12700. are what they are in order that their subject may be what it is. Then
  12701. transcendently, since the subject is what it is in virtue of its feelings, it is
  12702. only by means of its feelings that the subject objectively conditions the
  12703. creativity transcendent beyond itself. In our own relatively high grade
  12704. of human existence, this doctrine of feelings and their subject is best il-
  12705. lustrated by our notion of moral responsibility. The subject is responsible
  12706. for being what it is in virtue of its feelings. It is also derivatively respon-
  12707. sible for the consequences of its existence because they flow from its
  12708. feelings.
  12709.  
  12710. If the subject-predicate form of statement be taken to be metaphysically
  12711. ultimate, it is then impossible to express this doctrine of feelings and their
  12712. superject. It is better to say that the feelings aim at their subject, than
  12713. to say that they are aimed at their subject. For the latter mode of expres-
  12714. sion removes the subject from the scope of the feeling and assigns it to
  12715. an external agency. Thus the feeling would be wrongly abstracted from its
  12716. own final cause. This final cause is an inherent element in the feeling,
  12717. constituting the unity of that feeling. An actual entity feels as it does
  12718. feel in order to be the actual entity which it is. In this way an actual en-
  12719. tity satisfies Spinoza's notion of substance: it is causa sui. The creativity
  12720. is not an external agency with its own ulterior purposes. All actual entities
  12721. share with God this characteristic of self-causation. For this reason every
  12722. actual entity also shares with God the characteristic of transcending all
  12723. other actual entities, including God. The [340] universe is thus a creative
  12724. advance into novelty. The alternative to this doctrine is a static morpho-
  12725. logical universe.
  12726.  
  12727. SECTION IV
  12728.  
  12729. There are three main categoreal conditions which flow from the final
  12730. nature of things. These three conditions are: (i) the Category of Subjective
  12731. Unity, (ii) the Category of Objective Identity, and (iii) the Category of
  12732. Objective Diversity. Later we shall isolate five** other categoreal conditions.
  12733. But the three conditions mentioned above have an air of ultimate meta-
  12734. physical generality.
  12735.  
  12736. The first category has to do with self-realization. Self-realization is the
  12737. ultimate fact of facts. An actuality is self-realizing, and whatever is self-
  12738. realizing is an actuality. An actual entity is at once the subject of self-
  12739. realization, and the superject which is self-realized.
  12740.  
  12741. The second and third categories have to do with objective determina-
  12742. tion. All entities, including even other actual entities, enter into the self-
  12743. realization of an actuality in the capacity of determinants of the definite-
  12744.  
  12745.  
  12746.  
  12747. The Theory of Feelings 223
  12748.  
  12749. ness of that actuality. By reason of this objective functioning of entities
  12750. there is truth and falsehood. For every actuality is devoid of a shadow of
  12751. ambiguity: it is exactly what it is, by reason of its objective definition at
  12752. the hands of other entities. In abstraction from actualization, truth and
  12753. falsehood are meaningless: we are in the region of nonsense, a limbo where
  12754. nothing has any claim to existence. But definition is the soul of actuality:
  12755. the attainment of a peculiar definiteness is the final cause which animates
  12756. a particular process; and its attainment halts its process, so that by tran-
  12757. scendence it passes into its objective immortality as a new objective con-
  12758. dition added to the riches of definiteness attainable, the 'real potentiality'
  12759. of the universe.
  12760.  
  12761. A distinction must here be made. Each task of creation is a social effort,
  12762. employing the whole universe. Each novel actuality is a new partner add-
  12763. ing a new con- [341] dition. Every new condition can be absorbed into ad-
  12764. ditional fullness of attainment. On the other hand, each condition is ex-
  12765. clusive, intolerant of diversities; except so far as it finds itself in a web
  12766. of conditions which convert its exclusions into contrasts. A new actuality
  12767. may appear in the wrong society, amid which its claims to efficacy act
  12768. mainly as inhibitions. Then a weary task is set for creative function, by an
  12769. epoch of new creations to remove the inhibition. Insistence on birth at
  12770. the wrong season is the trick of evil. In other words, the novel fact may
  12771. throw back, inhibit, and delay. But the advance, when it does arrive, will
  12772. be richer in content, more fully conditioned, and more stable. For in its
  12773. objective efficacy an actual entity can only inhibit by reason of its alterna-
  12774. tive positive contribution.
  12775.  
  12776. A chain of facts is like a barrier reef. On one side there is wreckage,
  12777. and beyond it harbourage and safety. The categories governing the deter-
  12778. mination of things are the reasons why there should be evil; and are also
  12779. the reasons why, in the advance of the world, particular evil facts are finally
  12780. transcended.
  12781.  
  12782. SECTION V
  12783.  
  12784. Category I. The many feelings which belong to an incomplete phase in
  12785. the process of an actual entity, though unintegrated by reason of the in-
  12786. completeness of the phase, are compatible for synthesis by reason of the
  12787. unity of their subject.
  12788.  
  12789. This is the Category of 'Subjective Unity/ This category is one expression
  12790. of the general principle that the one subject is the final end which condi-
  12791. tions each component feeling. Thus the superject is already present as a
  12792. condition, determining how each feeling conducts its own process. Al-
  12793. though in any incomplete phase there are many unsynthesized feelings,
  12794. yet each of these feelings is conditioned by the other feelings. The process
  12795. of each feeling is such as to render that feeling integrable with the other
  12796. feelings.
  12797.  
  12798. [342] This Category of Subjective Unity is the reason why no feeling can
  12799.  
  12800.  
  12801.  
  12802. 224 The Theory of Prehensions
  12803.  
  12804. be abstracted from its subject. For the subject is at work in the feeling, in
  12805. order that it may be the subject with that feeling. The feeling is an epi-
  12806. sode in self-production, and is referent to its aim. This aim is a certain
  12807. definite unity with its companion feelings.
  12808.  
  12809. This doctrine of the inherence of the subject in the process of its pro-
  12810. duction requires that in the primary phase of the subjective process there
  12811. be a conceptual feeling of subjective aim: the physical and other feelings
  12812. originate as steps towards realizing this conceptual aim through their
  12813. treatment of initial data. This basic conceptual feeling suffers simplifica-
  12814. tion in the successive phases of the concrescence. It starts with conditioned
  12815. alternatives, and by successive decisions is reduced to coherence. The doc-
  12816. trine of responsibility is entirely concerned with this modification. In each
  12817. phase the corresponding conceptual feeling is the 'subjective end* charac-
  12818. teristic of that phase. The many feelings, in any incomplete phase, are
  12819. necessarily compatible with each other by reason of their individual con-
  12820. formity to the subjective end evolved for that phase.
  12821.  
  12822. This Category of Subjective Unity is a doctrine of pre-established har-
  12823. mony, applied to the many feelings in an incomplete phase. If we recur
  12824. therefore to the seven kinds of 'proper' entities, and ask how to classify
  12825. an incomplete phase, we find that it has the unity of a proposition. In ab-
  12826. straction from the creative urge by which each such phase is merely an
  12827. incident in a process, this phase is merely a proposition about its com-
  12828. ponent feelings and their ultimate superject. The pre-established harmony
  12829. is the self-consistency of this proposition, that is to say, its capacity for
  12830. realization. But such abstraction from the process does violence to its
  12831. nature; for the phase is an incident in the process. When we try to do
  12832. justice to this aspect of the phase, we must say that it is a proposition
  12833. seeking truth. It is a lure to the supervention of those integrating feel-
  12834. ings by which the mere [343] potentiality of the proposition, with its out-
  12835. standing indeterminations as to its setting amid the details of the universe,
  12836. is converted intof the fully determinate actuality.
  12837.  
  12838. The ground, or origin, of the concrescent process! is the multiplicity
  12839. of data in the universe, actual entities and eternal objects and propositions
  12840. and nexus. Each new phase in the concrescence means the retreat of mere
  12841. propositional unity before the growing grasp of real unity of feeling. Each
  12842. successive propositional phase is a lure to the creation of feelings which
  12843. promote its realization. Each temporal entity, in one sense, originates from
  12844. its mental pole, analogously to God himself. It derives from God its basic
  12845. conceptual aim, relevant to its actual world, yet with indeterminations
  12846. awaiting its own decisions. This subjective aim, in its successive modifi-
  12847. cations, remains the unifying factor governing the successive phases of
  12848. interplay between physical and conceptual feelings. These decisions are
  12849. impossible for the nascent creature antecedently to the novelties in the
  12850. phases of its concrescence. But this statement in its turn requires amplifi-
  12851.  
  12852.  
  12853.  
  12854. The Theory of Feelings 225
  12855.  
  12856. cation. With this amplification the doctrine, that the primary phase of a
  12857. temporal actual entity is physical, is recovered. A 'physical feeling' is here
  12858. defined to be the feeling of another actuality. If the other actuality be
  12859. objectified by its conceptual feelings, the physical feeling of the subject
  12860. in question is termed 'hybrid/ Thus the primary phase is a hybrid physical
  12861. feeling of God, in respect to God's conceptual feeling which is immedi-
  12862. ately relevant to the universe 'given' for that concrescence. There is then,
  12863. according to the Category of Conceptual Valuation, i.e., Categoreal Obliga-
  12864. tion IV, a derived conceptual feeling which reproduces for the subject the
  12865. data and valuation of God's conceptual feeling. This conceptual feeling
  12866. is the initial conceptual aim referred to in the preceding statement. In this
  12867. sense, God can be termed the creator of each temporal actual entity. But
  12868. the phrase is apt to be misleading by [344] its suggestion that the ultimate
  12869. creativity of the universe is to be ascribed to God's volition. The true
  12870. metaphysical position is that God is the aboriginal instance of this creativ-
  12871. ity, and is therefore the aboriginal condition which qualifies its action. It
  12872. is the function of actuality to characterize the creativity, and God is the
  12873. eternal primordial character. But,t of course, there is no meaning to
  12874. 'creativity' apart from its 'creatures,' and no meaning to 'God' apart from
  12875. the 'creativity' and the 'temporal creatures,' and no meaning to the 'tem-
  12876. poral creatures' t apart from 'creativity' and 'God.'
  12877.  
  12878. Category II. There can be no duplication of any element in the ob-
  12879. jective datum of the satisfaction of an actual entity, so far as concerns the
  12880. function of that element in that satisfaction.
  12881.  
  12882. This is the 'Category of Objective Identity.' This category asserts the es-
  12883. sential self-identity of any entity as regards its status in each individuali-
  12884. zation of the universe. In such a concrescence one thing has one rdle,
  12885. and cannot assume any duplicity. This is the very meaning of self-identity,
  12886. that, in any actual confrontation of thing with thing, one thing cannot
  12887. confront itself in alien rdles. Any one thing remains obstinately itself
  12888. playing a part with self-consistent unity. This category is one ground of
  12889. incompatibility.
  12890.  
  12891. Category III. There can be no 'coalescence' of diverse elements in the
  12892. objective datum of an actual entity, so far as concerns the functions of
  12893. those elements in that satisfaction.
  12894.  
  12895. This is the 'Category of Objective Diversity.' Here* the term 'coalescence'
  12896. means the self-contradictory notion of diverse elements exercising an ab-
  12897. solute identity of function, devoid of the contrasts inherent in their di-
  12898. versities. In other words, in a real complex unity each particular component
  12899. imposes its own particularity on its status. No entity can have an abstract
  12900. status in a real unity. Its status must be such that only it can fill and only
  12901. that actuality can supply.
  12902.  
  12903. [345] The neglect of this category is a prevalent error in metaphysical
  12904. reasoning. This category is another ground of incompatibility.
  12905.  
  12906.  
  12907.  
  12908. 226 The Theory of Prehensions
  12909.  
  12910.  
  12911.  
  12912. SECTION VI
  12913.  
  12914. The importance of these categories can only be understood by consider-
  12915. ing each actual world in the light of a 'medium' leading up to the con-
  12916. crescence of the actual entity in question. It will be remembered that the
  12917. phrase actual world' has always reference to some one concrescence.
  12918.  
  12919. Any actual entity, which we will name A, feels other actual entities, f
  12920. which we will name B, C, and D. Thus B, C, and D all lie in the actual
  12921. world of A. But C and D may lie in the actual world of B, and are then
  12922. felt by it; also D may lie in the actual world of C and be felt by it. This
  12923. example might be simplified, or might be changed to one of any degree of
  12924. complication. Now B, as an initial datum for A's feeling, also presents C
  12925. and D for A to feel through its mediation. Also C, as an initial datum for
  12926. A ? s feeling, also presents D for A to feel through its mediation. Thus, in
  12927. this artificially simplified example, A has D presented for feeling through
  12928. three distinct sources: (i) directly as a crude datum, (ii) by the mediation
  12929. of B, and (iii) by the mediation of C. This threefold presentation is D, in
  12930. its function of an initial datum for A's feeling of it, so far as concerns the
  12931. mediation of B and C. But, of course, the artificial simplification of the
  12932. medium to two intermediaries is very far from any real case. The medium
  12933. between D and A consists of all those actual entities which lie in the
  12934. actual world of A and not in the actual world of D. For the sake of sim-
  12935. plicity the explanation will continue in terms of this threefold presen-
  12936. tation.
  12937.  
  12938. There are thus three sources of feeling, D direct, D in its nexus with
  12939. C, and D in its nexus with B. Thus in the basic phase of A's concresence
  12940. there arise three prehensions of the datum D. According to the first cate-
  12941. gory [346] these prehensions are not independent. This subjective unity
  12942. of the concrescence introduces negative prehensions, so that D in the di-
  12943. rect feeling is not felt in its formal completeness, but objectified with the
  12944. elimination of such of its prehensions as are inconsistent with D felt
  12945. through the mediation of B, and through the mediation of C. Thus the
  12946. three component feelings of the first phasef are consistent, so as to pass
  12947. into the integration of the second phase in which there is A's one feeling
  12948. of a coherent objectification of D. Since D is necessarily self-consistent,
  12949. the inconsistencies must arise from the subjective forms of the prehen-
  12950. sions of D by B directly, by C directly, and by A directly. These incon-
  12951. sistencies lead to the eliminations in A's total prehension of D.
  12952.  
  12953. In this process, the negative prehensions which effect the elimination are
  12954. not merely negligible. The process through which a feeling passes in con-
  12955. stituting itself! also records itself in the subjective form of the integral
  12956. feeling. The negative prehensions have their own subjective forms which
  12957. they contribute to the process. A feeling bears on itself the scars of its
  12958. birth; it recollects as a subjective emotion its struggle for existence; it re-
  12959.  
  12960.  
  12961.  
  12962. The Theory of Feelings 227
  12963.  
  12964. tains the impress of what it might have been, but is not. It is for this
  12965. reason that what an actual entity has avoided as a datum for feeling may
  12966. yet be an important part of its equipment. The actual cannot be reduced
  12967. to mere matter of fact in divorce from the potential.
  12968.  
  12969. The same principle of explanation also holds in the case of a con-
  12970. ceptual prehension, in which the datum is an eternal object. In the first
  12971. phase of this conceptual prehension, there is this eternal object to be
  12972. felt as a mere abstract capacity for giving definiteness to a physical feeling.
  12973. But also there are the feelings of the objectifications of innumerable actual
  12974. entities. Some of these physical feelings illustrate this same eternal object
  12975. as an element providing their definiteness. There are in this way diverse
  12976. prehensions of the same eternal object; and by the first category these
  12977. various prehensions must be [347] consistent, so as to pass into the inte-
  12978. gration of the subsequent phase in which there is one coherent complex
  12979. feeling, namely, a conceptual feeling of that eternal object. This sub-
  12980. jective insistence on consistency may, from the beginning, replace the
  12981. positive feelings by negative prehensions.
  12982.  
  12983. SECTION VII
  12984.  
  12985. In the explanations of the preceding section, only the first category
  12986. has been explicitly alluded to. It must now be pointed out how the other
  12987. categories have been tacitly presupposed.
  12988.  
  12989. The fact that there is integration at all arises from the condition ex-
  12990. pressed by the Category of Objective Identity. The same entity, be it actual
  12991. entity or be it eternal object, cannot be felt twice in the formal constitu-
  12992. tion of one concrescence. The incomplete phases with their many feelings
  12993. of one object are only to be interpreted in terms of the final satisfaction
  12994. with its one feeling of that one object Thus objective identity requires
  12995. integration of the many feelings of one object into the one feeling of
  12996. that object. The analysis of an actual entity is only intellectual, or, to speak
  12997. with a wider scope, only objective. Each actual entity is a cell with atomic
  12998. unity. But in analysis it can only be understood as a process; it can only
  12999. be felt as a process, that is to say, as in passage. The actual entity is divis-
  13000. ible; but is in fact undivided. The divisibility can thus only refer to its
  13001. objectifications in which it transcends itself. But such transcendence is
  13002. self-revelation.
  13003.  
  13004. [348] +The third category is concerned with the antithesis to oneness,
  13005. namely, diversity. An actual entity is not merely one; it is also definitely
  13006. complex. But, to be definitely complex is to include definite diverse ele-
  13007. ments in definite ways. The category of objective deversity expresses the
  13008. inexorable condition— that a complex unity must provide for each of its
  13009. components a real diversity of status, with a reality which bears the same
  13010. sense as its own reality and is peculiar to itself. In other words, a real unity
  13011. cannot provide sham diversities of status for its diverse components.
  13012.  
  13013.  
  13014.  
  13015. 228 The Theory of Prehensions
  13016.  
  13017. This category is in truth only a particular application of the second
  13018. category. For a 'status' is after all something; and, according to the Cate-
  13019. gory of Objective Identity, it cannot duplicate its r61e. Thus if the 'status 7
  13020. be the status of this, it cannot in the same sense be the status of that. The
  13021. prohibition of sham diversities of status sweeps away the 'class-theory' t of
  13022. particular substances, which was waveringly suggested by Locke (II,
  13023. XXIII, 1), was more emphatically endorsed by Hume (Treatise, Bk. I,t
  13024. Part I, Sect. 6), and has been adopted by Hume's followers. For the es-
  13025. sence of a class is that it assigns no diversity of function to the members
  13026. of its extension. The members of a class are diverse members in virtue
  13027. of mere logical disjunction. The 'class/ thus appealed to, is a mere mul-
  13028. tiplicity. But in the prevalent discussion of classes, there are illegitimate
  13029. transitions to the notions of a 'nexus' and of a 'proposition.' The appeal to
  13030. a class to perform the services of a proper entity is exactly analogous to
  13031. an appeal to an imaginary terrier to kill a real rat.
  13032.  
  13033. +Thus the process of integration, which lies at the very heart of the
  13034. concrescence, is the urge imposed on the concrescent unity of that uni-
  13035. verse by the three Categories of Subjective Unity, of Objective Identity, and
  13036. of Objective Diversity. The oneness of the universe, and the oneness of
  13037. each element in the universe, repeat themselves to the crack of doom in
  13038. the creative advance from creature to creature, each creature including in
  13039. itself the whole of history and exemplifying the self-identity of things and
  13040. their mutual diversities.
  13041.  
  13042. SECTION VIII
  13043.  
  13044. This diversity of status, combined with the real unity of the components,
  13045. means that the real synthesis of two component elements in the objective
  13046. datum of a feeling [349] must be infected with the individual particulari-
  13047. ties of each of the relata. Thus the synthesis in its completeness expresses
  13048. the joint particularities of that pair of relata, and can relate no others. A
  13049. complex entity with this individual definiteness, arising out of determinate-
  13050. ness of eternal objects, will be termed a 'contrast/ A contrast cannot be
  13051. abstracted from the contrasted relata.
  13052.  
  13053. The most obvious examples of a contrast are to be found by confining
  13054. attention purely to eternal objects. The contrast between blue and red
  13055. cannot be repeated as that contrast between any other pair of colours,
  13056. or any pair of sounds, or between a colour and a sound. It is just the con-
  13057. trast between blue and red, that and nothing else. Certain abstractions from
  13058. that contrast, certain values inherent in it, can also be got from other
  13059. contrasts. But they are other contrasts, and not that contrast; and the
  13060. abstractions are not 'contrasts' of the same categoreal type.
  13061.  
  13062. In another sense, a 'nexus' falls under the meaning of the term 'con-
  13063. trast'; though we shall avoid this application of the term. What are or-
  13064. dinarily termed 'relations' are abstractions from contrasts. A relation can
  13065.  
  13066.  
  13067.  
  13068. The Theory of Feelings 229
  13069.  
  13070. be found in many contrasts; and when it is so found, it is said to relate
  13071. the things contrasted. The term 'multiple contrast 7 will be used when
  13072. there are or may be more than two elements jointly contrasted, and it is
  13073. desired to draw attention to that fact. A multiple contrast is analysable
  13074. into component dual contrasts. But a multiple contrast is not a mere ag-
  13075. gregation of dual contrasts. It is one contrast, over and above its com-
  13076. ponent contrasts. This doctrine that a multiple contrast cannot be con-
  13077. ceived as a mere disjunction of dual contrasts is the basis of the doctrine
  13078. of emergent evolution. It is the doctrine of real unities being more than
  13079. a mere collective disjunction of component elements. This doctrine has
  13080. the same ground as the objection to the class-theory of particular sub-
  13081. stances. The doctrine is a commonplace of art.
  13082.  
  13083. Bradley's discussions of relations are confused by his [350] failure to
  13084. distinguish between relations and contrasts. A relation is a genus of con-
  13085. trasts. He is then distressed— or would have been distressed if he had not
  13086. been consoled by the notion of 'mereness' as in 'mere appearance'— to
  13087. find that a relation will not do the work of a contrast. It fails to contrast.
  13088. Thus Bradley's argument proves that relations, among other things, are
  13089. 'mere'; that is to say, are indiscretions of the absolute, apings of reality
  13090. without self-consistency.
  13091.  
  13092. SECTION IX
  13093.  
  13094. One use of the term 'contrast' is to mean that particularity of conjoint
  13095. unity which arises from the realized togetherness of eternal objects. But
  13096. there is another, and more usual, sense of 'particularity/ This is the sense
  13097. in which the term 'particular' is applied to an actual entity.
  13098.  
  13099. One actual entity has a status among other actual entities, not expres-
  13100. sible wholly in terms of contrasts between eternal objects. For example,
  13101. the complex nexus of ancient imperial Rome to European history is not
  13102. wholly expressible in universals. It is not merely the contrast of a sort of
  13103. city, imperial, Roman, ancient, with a sort of history of a sort of con-
  13104. tinent, sea-indented, river-diversified, with alpine divisions, begirt by larger
  13105. continental masses and oceanic wastes, civilized, barbarized, christianized,
  13106. commercialized, industrialized. The nexus in question does involve such
  13107. a complex contrast of universals. But it involves more. For it is the nexus
  13108. of that Rome with that Europe. We cannot be conscious of this nexus
  13109. purely by the aid of conceptual feelings. This nexus is implicit, below con-
  13110. sciousness, in our physical feelings. In part we are conscious of such
  13111. physical feelings, and of that particularity of the nexus between particular
  13112. actual entities. This consciousness takes the form of our consciousness of
  13113. particular spatial and temporal relations between things directly perceived.
  13114. But, as in the case of Rome and Europe, so far as con- \3S1] cerns the mass
  13115. of our far-reaching knowledge, the particular nexus between the partic-
  13116. ular actualities in question ist only indicated by constructive reference
  13117. to the physical feelings of which we are conscious.
  13118.  
  13119.  
  13120.  
  13121. 230 The Theory of Prehensions
  13122.  
  13123. This peculiar particularity of the nexus between actual entities can be
  13124. put in another way. Owing to the disastrous confusion, more especially
  13125. by Hume, of conceptual feelings with perceptual feelings, the truism
  13126. that we can only conceive in terms of universals has been stretched to
  13127. mean that we can only feel in terms of universals. This is untrue. Our
  13128. perceptual feelings feel particular existents; that is to say, a physical
  13129. feeling, belonging to the percipient, feels the nexus between two other
  13130. actualities, A and B. It feels feelings of A which feel B, and feels feelings
  13131. of B which feel A. It integrates these feelings, so as to unify their identity
  13132. of elements. These identical elements form the factor defining the nexus
  13133. between A and B, a nexus also retaining the particular diversity of A and
  13134. B in its uniting force.
  13135.  
  13136. Also the more complex multiple nexus between many actual entities in
  13137. the actual world of a percipient is felt by that percipient. But this nexus,
  13138. as thus felt, can be abstracted from that particular percipient. It is the
  13139. same nexus for all percipients which include those actual entities in their
  13140. actual worlds. The multiple nexus is how those actual entities are really
  13141. together in all subsequent unifications of the universe, by reason of the
  13142. objective immortality of their real mutual prehensions of each other.
  13143.  
  13144. We thus arrive at the notion of the actual world of any actual entity,
  13145. as a nexus whose objectification constitutes the complete unity of ob-
  13146. jective datum for the physical feeling of that actual entity. This actual
  13147. entity is the original percipient of that nexus. But any other actual entity
  13148. which includes in its own actual world that original percipientf also in-
  13149. cludes that previous nexus as a portion of its own actual world. Thus each
  13150. actual world is a nexus which in this sense is independent of its original
  13151. [352] percipient. It enjoys an objective immortality in the future beyond
  13152. itself.
  13153.  
  13154. Every nexus is a component nexus, first accomplished in some later phase
  13155. of concrescence of an actual entity, and ever afterwards having its status
  13156. in actual worlds as an unalterable fact, dated and located among the
  13157. actual entities connected in itself. If in a nexus there be a realized con-
  13158. trast of universals, this contrast is located in that actual entity to which
  13159. it belongs as first originated in one of its integrative feelings. Thus every
  13160. realized contrast has a location, which is particular with the particularity
  13161. of actual entities. It is a particular complex matter of fact, realized; and,
  13162. because of its reality, a standing condition in every subsequent actual
  13163. world from which creative advance must originate.
  13164.  
  13165. It is this complete individual particularity of each actuality, and of each
  13166. nexus, and of each realized contrast, which is the reason for the three
  13167. Categoreal Conditions—of Subjective Unity, of Objective Identity, and of
  13168. Objective Diversity. The word 'event* is used sometimes in the sense of a
  13169. nexus of actual entities, and sometimes in the sense of a nexus as objecti-
  13170. fied by universals. In either sense, it is a definite fact with a date.
  13171.  
  13172. The initial data of a complex feeling, as mere data, are many; though
  13173.  
  13174.  
  13175.  
  13176. The Theory of Feelings 231
  13177.  
  13178. as felt they are one in the objective unity of a pattern. Thus a nexus is a
  13179. realized pattern of the initial data: though this pattern is merely relative to
  13180. the feeling, expressive of those factors in the many data by reason of which
  13181. they can acquire their unity in the feeling. This is the second use of the
  13182. term nexus, mentioned above.
  13183.  
  13184. Thus, just as the 'feeling as one' cannot bear the abstraction from it of
  13185. the subject, so the 'data as one' cannot bear the abstraction from it of
  13186. every feeling which feels it as such. According to the ontological principle,
  13187. the impartial nexus is an objective datum in the consequent nature of God;
  13188. since it is somewhere and yet not by any necessity of its own nature im-
  13189. plicated in the [353] feelings of any determined actual entity of the actual
  13190. world. The nexus involves realization somewhere. This is the first use of
  13191. the term nexus.
  13192.  
  13193. In two extreme cases the initial data of a feeling have a unity of their
  13194. own. In one case, the data reduce to a single actual entity, other than the
  13195. subject of the feeling; and in the other case the data reduce to a single
  13196. eternal object. These are called 'primary feelings/ A particular feeling
  13197. divorced from its subject is nonsense.
  13198.  
  13199. There are thus two laws respecting the feelings constituting the com-
  13200. plex satisfaction of an actual entity: (i) An entity can only be felt once,
  13201. and (ii) the diverse feelings, in the same subject, of the same entity as
  13202. datum which are to be unified into one feeling, must be compatible in their
  13203. treatment of the entity felt. In conformity with this pre-established har-
  13204. mony, 'incompatibility' would have dictated from the beginning that some
  13205. 'feeling' be replaced by a negative prehension.
  13206.  
  13207. SECTION X
  13208.  
  13209. The subjective forms of feelings are best discussed in connection with
  13210. the different types of feelings which can arise. This classification into types
  13211. has regard to the differences among feelings in respect to their initial data,
  13212. their objective data, and their subjective forms. But these sources of dif-
  13213. ference cannot wholly be kept separate.
  13214.  
  13215. A feeling is the appropriation of some elements in the universe to be
  13216. components in the real internal constitution of its subject. The elements
  13217. are the initial data; they are what the feeling feels. But they are felt under
  13218. an abstraction. The process of the feeling involves negative prehensions
  13219. which effect elimination. Thus the initial data are felt under a 'perspective'
  13220. which is the objective datum of the feeling.
  13221.  
  13222. In virtue of this elimination the components of the complex objective
  13223. datum have become 'objects' intervening in the constitution t of the sub-
  13224. ject of the feeling. In the phraseology of mathematical physics a feeling
  13225. has a [354] 'vector' character. A feeling is the agency by which other things
  13226. are built into the constitution of its one subject in process of concrescence.
  13227. Feelings are constitutive of the nexus by reason of which the universe finds
  13228. its unification ever renewed by novel concrescence. The universe is always
  13229.  
  13230.  
  13231.  
  13232. 232 The Theory of Prehensions
  13233.  
  13234. one, since there is no surveying it except from an actual entity which uni-
  13235. fies it. Also the universe is always new, since the immediate actual entity is
  13236. the superject of feelings which are essentially novelties.
  13237.  
  13238. The essential novelty of a feeling attaches to its subjective form. The
  13239. initial data, and even the nexus which is the objective datum, may have
  13240. served other feelings with other subjects. But the subjective form is the
  13241. immediate novelty; it is how that subject is feeling that objective datum.
  13242. There is no tearing this subjective form from the novelty of this con-
  13243. crescence. It is enveloped in the immediacy of its immediate present. The
  13244. fundamental example of the notion 'quality inhering inf particular sub-
  13245. stance' is afforded by 'subjective form inhering in feeling/ If we abstract
  13246. the form from the feeling, we are left with an eternal object as the rem-
  13247. nant of subjective form.
  13248.  
  13249. A feeling can be genetically described in terms of its process of origina-
  13250. tion, with its negative prehensions whereby its many initial data become
  13251. its complex objective datum. In this process the subjective form originates,
  13252. and carries into the feeling its own history transformed into the way in
  13253. which the feeling feels. The way in which the feeling feels expresses how
  13254. the feeling came into being. It expresses the purpose which urged it for-
  13255. ward, and the obstacles which it encountered, and the indeterminations
  13256. which were dissolved by the originative decisions of the subject.
  13257.  
  13258. There are an indefinite number of types of feeling according to the
  13259. complexity of the initial data which the feeling integrates, and according
  13260. to the complexity of the objective datum which it finally feels. But there
  13261. are three primary types of feeling which enter into the forma- [355] tion of
  13262. all the more complex feelings. These types are: (i) that of simple physical
  13263. feelings, (ii) that of conceptual feelings, and (iii) that of transmuted
  13264. feelings. In a simple physical feeling, the initial datum is a single actual
  13265. entity; in a conceptual feeling, the objective datum is an eternal object;!
  13266. in a transmuted feeling, the objective datum is a nexus of actual entities.
  13267. Simple physical feelings and transmuted feelings make up the class of
  13268. physical feelings.
  13269.  
  13270. In none of these feelings, taken in their original purity devoid of ac-
  13271. cretions from later integrations, does the subjective form involve conscious-
  13272. ness. Although in a propositional feeling the subjective form may involve
  13273. judgment, this element in the subjective form is not necessarily present.
  13274.  
  13275. One final remark must be added to the general description of a feeling.
  13276. A feeling is a component in the concrescence of a novel actual entity. The
  13277. feeling is always novel in reference to its data; since its subjective form,
  13278. though it must always have reproductive reference to the data, is not
  13279. wholly determined by them. The process of the concrescence is a progres-
  13280. sive integration of feelings controlled by their subjective forms. In this
  13281. synthesis, feelings of an earlier phase sink into the components of some
  13282. more complex feeling of a later phase. Thus each phase adds its element
  13283. of novelty, until the final phase in which the one complex 'satisfaction' is
  13284.  
  13285.  
  13286.  
  13287. The Theory of Feelings 233
  13288.  
  13289. reached. Thus the actual entity, as viewed morphologically through its
  13290. 'satisfaction/ is novel in reference to any one of its component feelings. It
  13291. presupposes those feelings. But conversely, no feeling can be abstracted
  13292. either from its data, or its subject. It is essentially a feeling aiming at that
  13293. subject, and motivated by that aim. Thus the subjective form embodies
  13294. the pragmatic aspect of the feeling; for the datum is felt with that subjec-
  13295. tive form in order that the subject may be the superject which it is.
  13296.  
  13297. In the analysis of a feeling, whatever presents itself as also ante rem is a
  13298. datum, whatever presents itself as \}S6] exclusively in re is subjective form,
  13299. whatever presents itself in re and post rem is 'subject-superject/ This doc-
  13300. trine of 'feeling' is the central doctrine respecting the becoming of an
  13301. actual entity. In a feeling the actual world, selectively appropriated, is the
  13302. presupposed datum, not formless but with its own realized form selectively
  13303. germane, in other words 'objectified/ The subjective form is the ingression
  13304. of novel form peculiar to the new particular fact, and with its peculiar
  13305. mode of fusion with the objective datum. The subjective form in abstrac-
  13306. tion from the feeling is merely a complex eternal object. In the becoming,
  13307. it meets the 'data' which are selected from the actual world. In other
  13308. words, the data are already 'in being/ There the term 'in being' is for the
  13309. moment used as equivalent to the term 'in realization/
  13310.  
  13311. SECTION XI
  13312.  
  13313. **A subjective form has two factors, its qualitative pattern and its pattern
  13314. of intensive quantity. But these two factors of pattern cannot wholly be
  13315. considered in abstraction from each other. For the relative intensities of
  13316. the qualitative elements in the qualitative pattern are among the relational
  13317. factors which constitute that qualitative pattern. Also conversely, there are
  13318. qualitative relations among the qualitative elements and they constitute an
  13319. abstract qualitative pattern for the qualitative relations. The pattern of
  13320. intensities is not only the variety of qualitative elements with such-and-
  13321. such intensities; but it is also the variety of qualitative elements, as in
  13322. such-and-such an abstract qualitative pattern, with such-and-such inten-
  13323. sities. Thus the two patterns are not really separable. It is true that there
  13324. is an abstract qualitative pattern, and an abstract intensive pattern; but in
  13325. the fused pattern the abstract qualitative pattern lends itself t to the in-
  13326. tensities, and the abstract intensive pattern lends itself to the qualities.
  13327.  
  13328. Further, the subjective form cannot be absolutely dis- [357] joined from
  13329. the pattern of the objective datum. Some elements of the subjective form
  13330. can be thus disjoined; and they form the subjective form as in abstraction
  13331. from the patterns of the objective datum. But the full subjective form can-
  13332. not be abstracted from the pattern of the objective datum. The intel-
  13333. lectual disjunction is not a real separation. Also the subjective form, amid
  13334. its own original elements, always involves reproduction of the pattern of
  13335. the objective datum.
  13336.  
  13337. As a simple example of this description of a feeling, consider the audi-
  13338.  
  13339.  
  13340.  
  13341. 234 The Theory of Prehensions
  13342.  
  13343. tion of sound. In order to avoid unnecessary complexity, let the sound be
  13344. one definite note. The audition of this note is a feeling. This feeling has
  13345. first an auditor, who is the subject of the feeling. But the auditor would not
  13346. be the auditor that he is apart from this feeling of his.
  13347.  
  13348. Secondly, there is the complex ordered environment composed of certain
  13349. other actual entities which, however vaguely, is felt by reason of this audi-
  13350. tion. This environment is the datum of this feeling. It is the external
  13351. world, as grasped systematically in this feeling. In this audition it is felt
  13352. under the objectification of vague spatial relations, and as exhibiting musi-
  13353. cal qualities. But the analytic discrimination of this datum of the feeling
  13354. is in part vague and conjectural, so far as consciousness is concerned: there
  13355. is the antecedent physiological functioning of the human body, and the
  13356. presentational immediacy of the presented locus.
  13357.  
  13358. There is also an emotional sensory pattern, the subjective form, which is
  13359. more definite and more easily analysable. The note, in its capacity of a
  13360. private sensation, has pitch, quality, and intensity. It is analysable into its
  13361. fundamental tone, and a selection of its overtones. This analysis reveals an
  13362. abstract qualitative pattern which is the complex relatedness of the funda-
  13363. mental tone-quality* with the tone-qualities of its select overtones. This
  13364. qualitative pattern may, or may not, include relations of a spatial type, if
  13365. some of the overtones come [358] from instruments spatially separate— f for
  13366. example, from a spatial pattern of tuning forks.
  13367.  
  13368. The fundamental tone, and its overtones, have, each of them, their own
  13369. intensities. This pattern of intensities can be analysed into the relative
  13370. intensities of the various tones and the absolute intensity which is the
  13371. total loudness. The scale of relative intensities enters into the final quality
  13372. of the note, with some independence of its absolute loudness.
  13373.  
  13374. Also the spatial pattern of the tuning forks and the resonance of the mu-
  13375. sic chamber enter into this quality. But these also concern the datum of the
  13376. feeling. Also in this integration of feeling we must include the qualitative
  13377. and quantitative auditory contributions derived from various nerve-routes of
  13378. the body. In this way the animal body, as part of the external world, takes
  13379. a particularly prominent place in the pattern of the datum of the feeling.
  13380. Also in the subjective form we must reckon qualities of joy and distaste, of
  13381. adversion and of aversion, which attach integrally to the audition, and also
  13382. differentially to various elements of the audition. In an earlier phase of the
  13383. auditor, there is audition divested of such joy and distaste. This earlier,
  13384. bare audition does not in its own nature determine this additional qualifi-
  13385. cation. It originates as the audition becomes an element in a higher syn-
  13386. thesis, and yet it is an element in the final component feeling. Thus the
  13387. audition gains complexity of subjective form by its integration with other
  13388. feelings. Also, though we can discern three patterns, namely, the pattern of
  13389. the datum, the pattern of emotional quality, and the pattern of emotional
  13390. intensity, we cannot analyse either of the latter patterns in complete
  13391. separation either from the pattern of the datum, or from each other.
  13392.  
  13393.  
  13394.  
  13395. The Theory of Feelings 235
  13396.  
  13397. The final concrete component in the satisfaction is the audition with its
  13398. subject, its datum, and its emotional pattern as finally completed. It is a
  13399. particular fact not to be torn away from any of its elements.
  13400.  
  13401. SECTION XII
  13402.  
  13403. [359] Prehensions are not atomic; they can be divided into other pre-
  13404. hensions and combined into other prehensions. Also prehensions are not
  13405. independent of each other. The relation between their subjective forms is
  13406. constituted by the one subjective aim which guides their formation. This
  13407. correlation of subjective forms is termed 'the mutual sensitivity' of prehen-
  13408. sions (cf. Part I, Ch. II, Sect. HI, Categoreal Obligation VII, The Cate-
  13409. gory of Subjective Harmony 7 ).
  13410.  
  13411. The prehensions in disjunction are abstractions; each of them is its sub-
  13412. ject viewed in that abstract objectification. The actuality is the totality of
  13413. prehensions with subjective unity in process of concrescence into concrete
  13414. unity.
  13415.  
  13416. There are an indefinite number of prehensions, overlapping, subdividing,
  13417. and supplementary to each other. The principle, according to which a pre-
  13418. hension can be discovered, is to take any component in the objective
  13419. datum of the satisfaction; in the complex pattern of the subjective form
  13420. of the satisfaction there will be a component with direct relevance to this
  13421. element in the datum. Then in the satisfaction, there is a prehension of
  13422. this component of the objective datum with that component of the total
  13423. subjective form as its subjective form.
  13424.  
  13425. The genetic growth of this prehension can then be traced by considering
  13426. the transmission of the various elements of the datum from the actual
  13427. world, and— in the case of eternal objects— their origination in the con-
  13428. ceptual prehensions. There is then a growth of prehensions, with integra-
  13429. tions, eliminations, and determination of subjective forms. But the deter-
  13430. mination f of successive phases of subjective forms, whereby the integra-
  13431. tions have the characters that they do have, depends on the unity of the
  13432. subject imposing a mutual sensitivity upon the prehensions. Thus a pre-
  13433. hension, considered genetically, can never free itself from the incurable
  13434. atomicity [360] of the actual entity to which it belongs. The selection of a
  13435. subordinate prehension from the satisfaction— as described above— involves
  13436. a hypothetical, propositional point of view. The fact is the satisfaction as
  13437. one. There is some arbitrariness in taking a component from the datum
  13438. with a component from the subjective form, and in considering them, on
  13439. the ground of congruity, as forming a subordinate prehension. The justifi-
  13440. cation is that the genetic process can be thereby analysed. If no such
  13441. analysis of the growth of that subordinate prehension can be given, then
  13442. there has been a faulty analysis of the satisfaction. This relation between
  13443. the satisfaction and the genetic process is expressed in the eighth and ninth
  13444. categories of explanation (cf. Part I, Ch. II, Sect. II).
  13445.  
  13446.  
  13447.  
  13448. CHAPTER II
  13449. THE PRIMARY FEELINGS
  13450.  
  13451. SECTION I
  13452.  
  13453. [361] A 'simple physical feeling' entertained in one subject is a feeling
  13454. for which the initial datum is another single actual entity, and the ob-
  13455. jective datum is another feeling entertained by the latter actual entity.
  13456.  
  13457. Thus in a simple physical feeling there are two actual entities con-
  13458. cerned. One of them is the subject of that feeling, and the other is the
  13459. initial datum of the feeling. A second feeling is also concerned, namely,
  13460. the objective datum of the simple physical feeling. This second feeling is
  13461. the 'objectification' of its subject for the subject of the simple physical
  13462. feeling. The initial datum is objectified as being the subject of the feeling
  13463. which is the objective datum: the objectification is the 'perspective' of the
  13464. initial datum.
  13465.  
  13466. A simple physical feeling is an act of causation. The actual entity which
  13467. is the initial datum is the 'cause/ the simple physical feeling is the 'effect/
  13468. and the subject entertaining the simple physical feeling is the actual entity
  13469. 'conditioned' by the effect. This 'conditioned' actual entity will also be
  13470. called the 'effect.' All complex causal action can be reduced to a complex
  13471. of such primary components. Therefore simple physical feelings will also
  13472. be called 'causal' feelings.
  13473.  
  13474. But it is equally true to say that a simple physical feeling is the most
  13475. primitive type of an act of perception, devoid of consciousness. The actual
  13476. entity which is the initial datum is the actual entity perceived, the ob-
  13477. jective datum is the 'perspective' under which that actual entity is per-
  13478. ceived, and the subject of the simple physical feeling [362] is the perceiver.
  13479. This is not an example of conscious perception. For the subjective form
  13480. of a simple physical feeling does not involve consciousness, unless acquired
  13481. in subsequent phases of integration. It seems as though in practice, for
  13482. human beings at least, only transmuted feelings acquire consciousness,
  13483. never simple physical feelings. Consciousness originates in the higher
  13484. phases of integration and illuminates those phases with the greater clarity
  13485. and distinctness.
  13486.  
  13487. Thus a simple physical feeling is one feeling which feels another feeling.
  13488. But the feeling felt has a subject diverse from the subject of the feeling
  13489. which feels it. A multiplicity of simple physical feelings entering into the
  13490. propositional unity of a phase constitutes the first phase in the concres-
  13491. cence of the actual entity which is the common subject of all these feel-
  13492.  
  13493.  
  13494.  
  13495. The Primary Feelings 237
  13496.  
  13497. ings. The limitation, whereby the actual entities felt are severally reduced
  13498. to the perspective of one of their own feelings, is imposed by the Gate-
  13499. goreal Condition of Subjective Unity, requiring a harmonious compatibility
  13500. in the feelings of each incomplete phase. Thus the negative prehensions,
  13501. involved in the production of any one feeling, are not independent of the
  13502. other feelings. The subjective forms of feelings depend in part on the
  13503. negative prehensions. This primary phase of simple physical feelings con-
  13504. stitutes the machinery by reason of which the creativity transcends the
  13505. world already actual, and yet remains conditioned by that actual world in
  13506. its new impersonation.
  13507.  
  13508. Owing to the vagueness of our conscious analysis of complex feelings,
  13509. perhaps we never consciously discriminate one simple physical feeling in
  13510. isolation. But all our physical relationships arc made up of such simple
  13511. physical feelings, as their atomic bricks. Apart from inhibitions or additions,
  13512. weakenings or intensifications, due to the history of its production, the
  13513. subjective form of a physical feeling is re-enaction of the subjective form
  13514. of the feeling felt. Thus the cause passes on its feeling to be reproduced
  13515. by the new subject as its own, and yet [363] as inseparable from the cause.
  13516. There is a flow of feeling. But the re-enaction is not perfect. The cate-
  13517. goreal demands of the concrescence require adjustments of the pattern of
  13518. emotional intensities. The cause is objectively in the constitution of the
  13519. effect, in virtue of being the feeler of the feeling reproduced in the effect
  13520. with partial equivalence of subjective form. Also the cause's feeling has its
  13521. own objective datum, and its own initial datum. Thus this antecedent
  13522. initial datum has now entered into the datum of the effect's feeling at
  13523. second-hand through the mediation of the cause.
  13524.  
  13525. The reason why the cause is objectively in the effectt is that the cause's
  13526. feeling cannot, as a feeling, be abstracted from its subject which is the
  13527. cause. This passage of the cause into the effect is the cumulative character
  13528. of time. The irreversibility of time depends on this character.
  13529.  
  13530. Note that in the 'satisfaction' there is an integration of simple physical
  13531. feelings. No simple physical feeling need be distinguished in consciousness.
  13532. Physical feelings may be merged with feelings of any type, and of whatever
  13533. complexity. A simple physical feeling has the dual character of being the
  13534. cause's feeling re-enacted for the effect as subject. But this transference of
  13535. feeling effects a partial identification of cause with effect, and not a mere
  13536. representation of the cause. It is the cumulation of the universe and not a
  13537. stage-play about it. In a simple feeling there is a double particularity in
  13538. reference to the actual world, the particular cause and the particular ef-
  13539. fect. In Locke's language (III, III, 6), and with his limitation of thought,
  13540. a simple feeling is an idea in one mind 'determined to this or that particu-
  13541. lar existent.' Locke is here expressing what only metaphysicians can doubt.
  13542.  
  13543. By reason of this duplicity in a simple feeling there is a vector character
  13544. which transfers the cause into the effect. It is a feeling from the cause
  13545. which acquires the subjectivity of the new effect without loss of its original
  13546.  
  13547.  
  13548.  
  13549. 238 The Theory of Prehensions
  13550.  
  13551. [364] subjectivity in the cause. Simple physical feelings embody the re-
  13552. productive character of nature, and also the objective immortality of the
  13553. past. In virtue of these feelings time is the conformation of the immediate
  13554. present to the past. Such feelings are 'conformar feelings.
  13555.  
  13556. The novel actual entity, which is the effect, is the reproduction of the
  13557. many actual entities of the past. But in this reproduction there is abstrac-
  13558. tion from their various totalities of feeling. This abstraction is required by
  13559. the categoreal conditions for compatible synthesis in the novel unity. This
  13560. abstractive 'objectification' is rendered possible by reason of the 'divisible'
  13561. character of the satisfactions of actual entities. By reason of this 'divisible'
  13562. character causation is the transfer of a feeling, and not of a total satisfac-
  13563. tion. The other feelings are dismissed by negative prehensions, owing to
  13564. their lack of compliance with categoreal demands.
  13565.  
  13566. A simple physical feeling enjoys a characteristic which has been variously
  13567. described as 're-enaction/ 'reproduction/ and 'conformation/ This charac-
  13568. teristic can be more accurately explained in terms of the eternal objects
  13569. involved. There are eternal objects determinant of the definiteness of the
  13570. objective datum which is the 'cause/ and eternal objects determinant of
  13571. the definiteness of the subjective form belonging to the 'effect/ When
  13572. there is re-enaction there is one eternal object with two-way functioning,
  13573. namely, as partial determinant of the objective datum, and as partial de-
  13574. terminant of the subjective form. In this two-way role, the eternal object
  13575. is functioning relationally between the initial data on the one hand and
  13576. the concrescent subject on the other. It is playing one self-consistent role in
  13577. obedience to the Category of Objective Identity.
  13578.  
  13579. Physical science is the science investigating spatio-temporal and quan-
  13580. titative characteristics of simple physical feelings. The actual entities of the
  13581. actual world are bound together in a nexus of these feelings. Also in the
  13582. creative advance, the nexus proper to an antecedent [365] actual world is
  13583. not destroyed. It is reproduced and added to, by the new bonds of feeling
  13584. with the novel actualities which transcend it and include it. But these
  13585. bonds have always their vector character. Accordingly the ultimate physical
  13586. entities for physical science are always vectors indicating transference. In
  13587. the world there is nothing static. But there is reproduction; and hence the
  13588. permanence which is the result of order, and the cause of it. And yet there
  13589. is always change; for time is cumulative as well as reproductive, and the
  13590. cumulation of the many is not their reproduction as many.
  13591.  
  13592. This section on simple physical feelings lays the foundation of the treat-
  13593. ment of cosmology in the philosophy of organism. It contains the discus-
  13594. sion of the ultimate elements from which a more complete philosophical
  13595. discussion of the physical world— that is to say, of nature— must be derived.
  13596. In the first place an endeavour has been made to do justice alike to the
  13597. aspect of the world emphasized by Descartes and to the atomism of the
  13598. modern quantum theory. Descartes saw the natural world as an extensive
  13599. spatial plenum, enduring through time. Modern physicists see energy
  13600.  
  13601.  
  13602.  
  13603. The Primary Feelings 239
  13604.  
  13605. transferred in definite quanta. This quantum theory also has analogues in
  13606. recent neurology. Again fatigue is the expression of cumulation- it is phys-
  13607. ical memory. Further,! causation and physical memory spring from the
  13608. same root: both of them are physical perception. Cosmology must do
  13609. equal justice to atomism, to continuity, to causation, to memory, to percep-
  13610. tion, to qualitative and quantitative forms of energy, and to extension.
  13611. But so far there has been no reference to the ultimate vibratory characters
  13612. of organisms and to the 'potential' element in nature.
  13613.  
  13614. SECTION II
  13615.  
  13616. Conceptual feelings and simple causal feelings constitute the two main
  13617. species of 'primary' feelings. All other feelings of whatever complexity
  13618. arise out of a process of integration which starts with a phase of these
  13619. [366] primary feelings. There is, however, a difference between the species.
  13620. An actual entity in the actual world of a subject must enter into the con-
  13621. crescence of that subject by some simple causal feeling, however vague,
  13622. trivial, and submerged. Negative prehensions may eliminate its distinctive
  13623. importance. But in some way, by some trace of causal feeling, the remote
  13624. actual entity is prehended positively. In the case of an eternal object,
  13625. there is no such necessity. In any given concrescence, it may be included
  13626. positively by means of a conceptual feeling; but it may be excluded by a
  13627. negative prehension. The actualities have to be felt, while the pure po-
  13628. tentials can be dismissed. So far as concerns their functionings as objects,
  13629. this is the great distinction between an actual entity and an eternal object.
  13630. The one is stubborn matter of fact; and the other never loses its 'accent 7 of
  13631. potentiality.
  13632.  
  13633. In each concrescence there is a twofold aspect of the creative urge. In
  13634. one aspect there is the origination of simple causal feelings; and in the
  13635. other aspect there is the origination of conceptual feelings. These con-
  13636. trasted aspects will be called the physical and the mental poles of an ac-
  13637. tual entity. No actual entity is devoid of either pole; though their relative
  13638. importance differs in different actual entities. Also conceptual feelings do
  13639. not necessarily involve consciousness; though there can be no conscious
  13640. feelings which do not involve conceptual feelings as elements in the
  13641. synthesis.
  13642.  
  13643. Thus an actual entity is essentially dipolar, with its physical and mental
  13644. poles; and even the physical world cannot be properly understood without
  13645. reference to its other side, which is the complex of mental operations. The
  13646. primary mental operations are conceptual feelings.
  13647.  
  13648. A conceptual feeling is feeling an eternal object in the primary meta-
  13649. physical character of being an 'object/ that is to say, feeling its capacity
  13650. for being a realized determinant of process. Immanence and transcendence
  13651. are the characteristics of an object: as a realized determinant it [367] is
  13652. immanent; as a capacity for determination it is transcendent; in both roles
  13653.  
  13654.  
  13655.  
  13656. 240 The Theory of Prehensions
  13657.  
  13658. it is relevant to something not itself. There is no character belonging to
  13659. the actual apart from its exclusive determination by selected eternal ob-
  13660. jects. The definiteness of the actual arises from the exclusiveness of eternal
  13661. objects in their function as determinants. If the actual entity be this, then
  13662. by the nature of the case it is not that or that. The fact of incompatible
  13663. alternatives is the ultimate fact in virtue of which there is definite charac-
  13664. ter. A conceptual feeling is the feeling of an eternal object in respect to its
  13665. general capacity as a determinant of character, including thereby its ca-
  13666. pacity of exclusiveness. In the technical phraseology of these lectures, a
  13667. conceptual feeling is a feeling whose 'datum' is an eternal object. Anal-
  13668. ogously a negative prehension is termed 'conceptual'! when its datum is
  13669. an eternal object. In a conceptual feeling there is no necessary progress
  13670. from the 'initial data' to the 'objective datum/ The two may be identical,
  13671. except in so far as conceptual feelings with diverse sources of origination
  13672. acquire integration.
  13673.  
  13674. Conceptual prehensions, positive or negative, constitute the primary
  13675. operations among those belonging to the mental pole of an, actual entity.
  13676.  
  13677. SECTION III
  13678.  
  13679. The subjective form of a conceptual feeling has the character of a Val-
  13680. uation/ and this notion must now be explained.
  13681.  
  13682. A conceptual feeling arises in some incomplete phase of its subject and
  13683. passes into a supervening phase in which it has found integration with
  13684. other feelings. In this supervening phase, the eternal object, which is the
  13685. datum of the conceptual feeling, is an ingredient in some sort of datum in
  13686. which the other components are the objective data of other feelings in the
  13687. earlier phase. This new datum is the integrated datum; it will be some sort
  13688. of 'contrast/ By the first categoreal condition the feelings [368] of the
  13689. earlier phase are compatible for integration. Thus the supervention of the
  13690. later phase does not involve elimination by negative prehensions; such
  13691. eliminations of positive prehensions in the concrescent subject would
  13692. divide that subject into many subjects, and would divide these many sub-
  13693. jects from the superject. But, though there can be no elimination from the
  13694. supervening phase as a whole, there may be elimination from some new
  13695. integral feeling which is merely one component of that phase.
  13696.  
  13697. But in the formation of this integrated datum there must be determina-
  13698. tion of exactly how this eternal object has ingress into that datum con-
  13699. jointly with the remaining eternal objects and actual entities derived from
  13700. the other feelings. This determination is effected by the subjective forms
  13701. of the component conceptual feelings. Again it is to be remembered that,
  13702. by the first categoreal condition, this subjective form is not independent of
  13703. the other feelings in the earlier phase, and thus is such as to effect this
  13704. determination. Also the integral feeling has its subjective form with its
  13705. pattern of intensiveness. This patterned intensiveness regulates the dis-
  13706.  
  13707.  
  13708.  
  13709. The Primary Feelings 241
  13710.  
  13711. tinctive lelative importance of each element of the datum as felt in that
  13712. feeling. This intensive regulation of that eternal object f as felt in the in-
  13713. tegrated datum, is determined by the subjective form of the conceptual
  13714. feeling. Yet again, by reference to the first, and seventh, categoreal condi-
  13715. tions, this intensive form of the conceptual feeling has dependence also in
  13716. this respect on the other feelings of the earlier phase. Thus, according as
  13717. the valuation of the conceptual feeling is a Valuation up' or a Valuation
  13718. down/ the importance of the eternal object as felt in the integrated feel-
  13719. ing is enhanced, or attenuated. Thus the valuation is both qualitative, de-
  13720. termining how the eternal object is to be utilized, and is also intensive,
  13721. determining what importance that utilization is to assume.
  13722.  
  13723. Thus a valuation has three characteristics:
  13724.  
  13725. (i) According to the Categories of Subjective Unity, and [369] of Sub-
  13726. jective Harmony, the valuation is dependent on the other feelings in its
  13727. phase of origination.
  13728.  
  13729. (ii) The valuation determines in what status the eternal object has in-
  13730. gression into the integrated nexus physically felt.
  13731.  
  13732. (iii) The valuation values up, or down, so as to determine the intensive
  13733. importance accorded to the eternal object by the subjective form of the
  13734. integral feeling.
  13735.  
  13736. These three characteristics of an integral feeling, derived from its con-
  13737. ceptual components, are summed up in the term 'valuation/
  13738.  
  13739. But though these three characteristics are included in a valuation, they
  13740. are merely the outcome of the subjective aim of the subject, determining
  13741. what it is itself integrally to be, in its own character of the superject of its
  13742. own process.
  13743.  
  13744. SECTION IV
  13745.  
  13746. Consciousness concerns the subjective form of a feeling. But such a sub-
  13747. jective form requires a certain type of objective datum. A subjective form
  13748. in abstraction loses its reality, and sinks into an eternal object capable of
  13749. determining a feeling into that distinctive type of definiteness. But when
  13750. the eternal object 'informs' a feeling it can only so operate in virtue of its
  13751. conformation to the other components which jointly constitute the defi-
  13752. niteness of the feeling. The moral of this slight discussion must now be
  13753. applied to the notion of 'consciousness/ Consciousness is an element in
  13754. feeling which belongs to its subjective form. But there can only be that
  13755. sort of subjective form when the objective datum has an adequate charac-
  13756. ter. Further, the objective datum can only assume this character when it is
  13757. derivate from initial data which carry in their individual selves the re-
  13758. ciprocal possibilities of this objective synthesis.
  13759.  
  13760. A pure conceptual feeling in its first mode of origination never involves
  13761. consciousness. In this respect a pure mental feeling, conceptual or proposi-
  13762. tional, is analogous [370] to a pure physical feeling. A primary feeling of
  13763.  
  13764.  
  13765.  
  13766. 242 The Theory of Prehensions
  13767.  
  13768. either type, or a propositional feeling, can enrich its subjective form with
  13769. consciousness only hy means of its alliances.
  13770.  
  13771. Whenever there is consciousness there is some element of recollection.
  13772. It recalls earlier phases from the dim recesses of the unconscious. Long ago
  13773. this truth was asserted in Plato's doctrine of reminiscence. No doubt Plato
  13774. was directly thinking of glimpses of eternal truths lingering in a soul
  13775. derivate from a timeless heaven of pure form. Be that as it may, then in a
  13776. wider sense consciousness enlightens experience which precedes it, and
  13777. could be without it if considered as a mere datum.
  13778.  
  13779. Hume, with opposite limitations to his meaning, asserts the same doc-
  13780. trine. He maintains that we can never conceptually entertain what we have
  13781. never antecedently experienced through impressions of sensation. The
  13782. philosophy of organism generalizes the notion of 'impressions of sensation'
  13783. into that of 'pure physical feeling/ Even then Hume's assertion is too un-
  13784. guarded according to Hume's own showing. But the immediate point is
  13785. the deep-seated alliance of consciousness with recollection both for Plato
  13786. and for Hume.
  13787.  
  13788. Here we maintain the doctrine that, in the analysis of the origination of
  13789. any conscious feeling, some component physical feelings are to be found;
  13790. and conversely, whenever there is consciousness, there is some component
  13791. of conceptual functioning. For the abstract element in the concrete fact is
  13792. exactly what provokes our consciousness. The consciousness is what arises
  13793. in some process of synthesis of physical and mental operations. In hist
  13794. doctrine of ideas, Locke goes further than Hume and is, as I think, more
  13795. accurate in expressing the facts; though Hume adds something which
  13796. Locke omits.
  13797.  
  13798. Locke upholds the direct conscious apprehension of 'things without'
  13799. (e.g.,t Essay, II, XXI, 1), otherwise termed 'exterior things' (II, XXIII, 1),
  13800. or 'this or that particular existence' (III, III, 6), and illustrated by an in-
  13801. dividual nurse and an individual mother (III, III, 7). [371] In the philos-
  13802. ophy of organism the nexus, which is the basis for such direct apprehen-
  13803. sion, is provided by the physical feelings. The philosophy of organism
  13804. here takes the opposite road to that taken alike by Descartes and by Kant.
  13805. Both of these philosophers accepted (Descartes with hesitations, and Kant
  13806. without question) the traditional subjectivist sensationalism, and assigned
  13807. the intuition of 'things without' peculiarly to the intelligence.
  13808.  
  13809. Hume's addition consists in expressing and discussing, with the utmost
  13810. clarity, the traditional sensationalist dogma. Thus for Hume, as for Locke
  13811. when he remembers to speak in terms of this doctrine, an 'impression' is
  13812. the conscious apprehension of a universal. For example, he writes {Trea-
  13813. tise, Bk. I,t Part I, Ch. I), "That idea of red, which we form in the dark,
  13814. and that impression which strikes our eyes in sunshine, differ only in de-
  13815. gree, not in nature." t This means that a consistent sensationalism cannot
  13816. distinguish between a percept and a concept. Hume had not in his mind
  13817. (at least when philosophizing, though he admits it for other sorts of 'prac-
  13818.  
  13819.  
  13820.  
  13821. The Primary Feelings 243
  13822.  
  13823. tice') the fourth category of explanation, that no entity can be abstracted
  13824. from its capacity to function as an object in the process of the actual world.
  13825. To function as an object' is 'to be a determinant of the definiteness of an
  13826. actual occurrence/ According to the philosophy of organism, a pure con-
  13827. cept does not involve consciousness, at least in our human experience.
  13828. Consciousness arises when a synthetic feeling integrates physical and con-
  13829. ceptual feelings. Traditional philosophy in its account of conscious per-
  13830. ception has exclusively fixed attention on its pure conceptual side; and
  13831. thereby has made difficulties for itself in the theory of knowledge. Locke,
  13832. with his naive good sense, assumes that perception involves more than this
  13833. conceptual side; though he fails to grasp the inconsistency of this assump-
  13834. tion with the extreme subjectivist sensational doctrine. Physical feelings
  13835. form the non-conceptual element in our awareness of [372] nature. 1 Also,
  13836. all awareness, even awareness of concepts, requires at least the synthesis of
  13837. physical feelings with conceptual feeling. In awareness actuality, as a
  13838. process in fact, is integrated with the potentialities which illustrate either
  13839. what it is and might not be, or what it is not and might be. In other
  13840. words, there is no consciousness without reference to definiteness, affirma-
  13841. tion, and negation. Also affirmation involves its contrast with negation,
  13842. and negation involves its contrast with affirmation. Further, affirmation
  13843. and negation are alike meaningless apart from reference to the definiteness
  13844. of particular actualities. Consciousness is how we feel the affirmation-
  13845. negation contrast. Conceptual feeling is the feeling of an unqualified nega-
  13846. tion; that is to say, it is the feeling of a definite eternal object with the
  13847. definite extrusion of any particular realization. Consciousness requires that
  13848. the objective datum should involve (as one side of a contrast) a qualified
  13849. negative determined to some definite situation. It will be found later (cf.
  13850. Ch. IV) that this doctrine implies that there is no consciousness apart
  13851. from propositions as one element in the objective datum.
  13852.  
  13853. 1 Cf. The Concept of Nature, Ch. I.
  13854.  
  13855.  
  13856.  
  13857. CHAPTER III
  13858. THE TRANSMISSION OF FEELINGS
  13859.  
  13860. SECTION I
  13861.  
  13862. [373] According to the ontological principle there is nothing which
  13863. floats into the world from nowhere. Everything in the actual world is re-
  13864. ferable to some actual entity. It is either transmitted from an actual entity
  13865. in the past, or belongs to the subjective aim of the actual entity to whose
  13866. concrescence it belongs. This subjective aim is both an example and a limi-
  13867. tation of the ontological principle. It is an example, in that the principle is
  13868. here applied to the immediacy of concrescent fact. The subject completes
  13869. itself during the process of concrescence by a self-criticism of its own
  13870. incomplete phases. In another sense the subjective aim limits the on-
  13871. tological principle by its own autonomy. But the initial stage of its aim is
  13872. an endowment which the subject inherits from the inevitable ordering of
  13873. things, conceptually realized in the nature of God. The immediacy of the
  13874. concrescent subject is constituted by its living aim at its own self-constitu-
  13875. tion. Thus the initial stage of the aim is rooted in the nature of God, and
  13876. its completion depends on the self-causation of the subject-superject. This
  13877. function of God is analogous to the remorseless working of things in
  13878. Greek and in Buddhist thought. The initial aim is the best for that im-
  13879. passe. But if the best be bad, then the ruthlessness of God can be personi-
  13880. fied as Ate, the goddess of mischief. The chaff is burnt. What is inexorable
  13881. in God, is valuation as an aim towards 'order'; and 'order' means 'society
  13882. permissive of actualities with patterned intensity of feeling arising from
  13883. adjusted con- [374] trasts/t In this sense God is the principle of concretion;
  13884. namely, he is that actual entity from which each temporal concrescence
  13885. receives that initial aim from which its self-causation starts. That aim
  13886. determines the initial gradations of relevance of eternal objects for con-
  13887. ceptual feeling; and constitutes the autonomous subject in its primary
  13888. phase of feelings with its initial conceptual valuations, and with its initial
  13889. physical purposes. Thus the transition of the creativity from an actual
  13890. world to the correlate novel concrescence is conditioned by the relevance
  13891. of God's all-embracing conceptual valuations to the particular possibilities
  13892. of transmission from the actual world, and by its relevance to the various
  13893. possibilities of initial subjective form available for the initial feelings. In
  13894. this way there is constituted the concrescent subject in its primary phase
  13895. with its dipolar constitution, physical and mental, indissoluble.
  13896.  
  13897. 244
  13898.  
  13899.  
  13900.  
  13901. The Transmission of Feelings 245
  13902.  
  13903. If we prefer the phraseology, we can say that God and the actual world
  13904. jointly constitute the character of the creativity for the initial phase of the
  13905. novel concrescence. The subject, thus constituted, is the autonomous mas-
  13906. ter of its own concrescence into subject-superject. It passes from a sub-
  13907. jective aim in concrescence into a superject with objective immortality. At
  13908. any stage it is subject-superject. According to this explanation, self-deter-
  13909. mination is always imaginative in its origin. The deterministic efficient
  13910. causation is the inflow of the actual world in its own proper character of
  13911. its own feelings, with their own intensive strength, felt and re-enacted by
  13912. the novel concrescent subject. But this re-enaction has a mere character of
  13913. conformation to pattern. The subjective valuation is the work of novel
  13914. conceptual feeling; and in proportion to its importance, acquired in com-
  13915. plex processes of integration and reintegration, this autonomous concep-
  13916. tual element modifies the subjective forms throughout the whole range of
  13917. feeling in that concrescence and thereby guides the integrations.
  13918.  
  13919. In so far as there is negligible autonomous energy, the [375] subject
  13920. merely receives the physical feelings, confirms their valuations according to
  13921. the 'order' of that epoch, and transmits by reason of its own objective im-
  13922. mortality. Its own flash of autonomous individual experience is negligible
  13923. for the science which is tracing transmissions up to the conscious ex-
  13924. perience of a final observer. But as soon as individual experience is not
  13925. negligible, the autonomy of the subject in the modification of its initial
  13926. subjective aim must be taken into account. Each creative act is the uni-
  13927. verse incarnating itself as one, and there is nothing above it by way of final
  13928. condition.
  13929.  
  13930.  
  13931.  
  13932. SECTION II
  13933.  
  13934. The general doctrine of the previous section requires an examination of
  13935. principles regulating the transmission of feelings into data for novel feel-
  13936. ings in a new concrescence. Since no feeling can be abstracted from its sub-
  13937. ject, this transmission is merely another way of considering the objectifica-
  13938. tion of actual entities. A feeling will be called 'physical' when its datum
  13939. involves objectifications of other actual entities. In the previous chapter
  13940. the special case of 'simple physical feelings' was discussed. A feeling be-
  13941. longing to this special case has as its datum only one actual entity, and
  13942. this actual entity is objectified by one of its feelings. All the more com-
  13943. plex kinds of physical feelings arise in subsequent phases of concrescence,
  13944. in virtue of integrations of simple t physical feelings with each other and
  13945. with conceptual feelings. But before proceeding to these more complex
  13946. physical feelings, a subdivision of simple physical feelings must be con-
  13947. sidered. Such feelings are subdivided into 'pure physical feelings' and 'hy-
  13948. brid physical feelings/ In a 'pure physical feeling' the actual entity which
  13949. is the datum is objectified by one of its own physical feelings. Thus having
  13950. regard to the 're-enaction' which is characteristic of the subjective form of
  13951.  
  13952.  
  13953.  
  13954. 246 The Theory of Prehensions
  13955.  
  13956. a simple physical feeling, we have— in the case of the simpler actual en-
  13957. tities—an example of the transference of energy in the physical [376]
  13958. world. When the datum is an actual entity of a highly complex grade, the
  13959. physical feeling by which it is objectified as a datum may be of a highly
  13960. complex character, and the simple notion of a transference of some form
  13961. of energy to the new subject may entirely fail to exhaust the important
  13962. aspects of the pure physical feeling in question.
  13963.  
  13964. In a 'hybrid physical feeling' the actual entity forming the datum is
  13965. objectified by one of its own conceptual feelings. Thus having regard to
  13966. the element of autonomy which is characteristic of the subjective form of
  13967. a conceptual feeling, we have— in the case of the more complex actual
  13968. entities— an example of the origination and direction of energy in the
  13969. physical world. In general, this simplified aspect of a hybrid physical feel-
  13970. ing does not exhaust its role in the concrescence of its subject.
  13971.  
  13972. The disastrous separation of body and mind, characteristic of philo-
  13973. sophical systems which are in any important respect derived from Car-
  13974. tesianism, is avoided in the philosophy of organism by the doctrines of
  13975. hybrid physical feelings and of the transmuted feelings. In these ways
  13976. conceptual feelings pass into the category of physical feelings. Also con-
  13977. versely, physical feelings give rise to conceptual feelings, and conceptual
  13978. feelings give rise to other conceptual feelings— according to the doctrines
  13979. of the Categories of Conceptual Valuation (Category IV), and of Con-
  13980. ceptual Reversion (Category V), to be discussed in the subsequent sec-
  13981. tions of this chapter.
  13982.  
  13983. One important characteristic of a hybrid feeling is the intensity of the
  13984. conceptual feeling which originates from it, according to the Category of
  13985. Subjective Valuation. In the next section, this Categoreal Condition of
  13986. 'Conceptual Valuation' is considered in relation to all physical feelings,
  13987. 'pure' and 'hybrid' alike. The present section will only anticipate that dis-
  13988. cussion so far as hybrid feelings are concerned. Thus the part of the general
  13989. category now relevant can be formulated:
  13990.  
  13991. [377] A hybrid physical feeling originates for its subject a conceptual
  13992. feeling with the same datum as that of the conceptual feeling of the ante-
  13993. cedent subject. But the two conceptual feelings in the two subjects re-
  13994. spectively may have different subjective forms.
  13995.  
  13996. There is an autonomy in the formation of the subjective forms of con-
  13997. ceptual feelings, conditioned only by the unity of the subject as expressed
  13998. in categoreal conditions I, VII, and VIII. These conditions for unity cor-
  13999. relate the sympathetic subjective form of the hybrid feeling with the
  14000. autonomous subjective form of the derivative conceptual feeling with the
  14001. same subject.
  14002.  
  14003. There are evidently two sub-species of hybrid feelings: (i) those which
  14004. feel the conceptual feelings of temporal actual entities, and (ii) those
  14005. which feel the conceptual feelings of God.
  14006.  
  14007. The objectification of God in a temporal subject is effected by the hy-
  14008.  
  14009.  
  14010.  
  14011. The Transmission of Feelings 247
  14012.  
  14013. brid feelings with God's conceptual feelings as data. Those of God's feel-
  14014. ings which are positively prehended are those with some compatibility of
  14015. contrast, or of identity, with physical feelings transmitted from the tem-
  14016. poral world. But when we take God into account, then we can assert with-
  14017. out any qualification Hume's principle, that all conceptual feelings are
  14018. derived from physical feelings. The limitation of Hume's principle intro-
  14019. duced by the consideration of the Category of Conceptual Reversion
  14020. (cf. Sect. Ill of this chapter) is to be construed as referring merely to the
  14021. transmission from the temporal world, leaving God out of account. Apart
  14022. from the intervention of God, there could be nothing new in the world,
  14023. and no order in the world. The course of creation would be a dead level
  14024. of ineffectiveness, with all balance and intensity progressively excluded by
  14025. the cross currents of incompatibility. The novel hybrid feelings derived
  14026. from God, with the derivative sympathetic conceptual valuations, are the
  14027. foundations of progress. [378]
  14028.  
  14029. SECTION III
  14030.  
  14031. Conceptual feelings are primarily derivate from physical feelings, and
  14032. secondarily from each other. In this statement, the consideration of God's
  14033. intervention is excluded. When this intervention is taken into account,
  14034. all conceptual feelings must be derived from physical feelings. Unfettered
  14035. conceptual valuation, 'infinite' in Spinoza's sense of that term, is only
  14036. possible once in the universe; since that creative act is objectively immortal
  14037. as an inescapable condition characterizing creative action.
  14038.  
  14039. But, unless otherwise stated, only the temporal entities of the actual
  14040. world will be considered. We have to discuss the categoreal conditions for
  14041. such derivation of conceptual feelings from the physical feelings relating
  14042. to the temporal world. By the Categoreal Condition of Subjective Unity-
  14043. Category I— the initial phase of physical feelings has the propositional
  14044. unity of feelings compatible for integration into one feeling of the actual
  14045. world. But the completed determination of the subjective form of this
  14046. final ''satisfaction' awaits the origination of conceptual feelings whose
  14047. subjective forms introduce the factor of Valuation/ that is, Valuation up'
  14048. or Valuation down/
  14049.  
  14050. Thus a supplementary phase succeeds to the initial purely physical
  14051. phase. This supplementary phase starts with two subordinate phases of
  14052. conceptual origination, and then passes into phases of integration, and of
  14053. reintegration, in which propositional feelings, and intellectual feelings, may
  14054. emerge. In the present chapter we are concerned with the first two phases
  14055. of merely conceptual origination. These are not phases of conceptual
  14056. analysis, but of conceptual valuation. The subsequent analytic phases in-
  14057. volve propositional feelings, and in certain circumstances issue in con-
  14058. sciousness. But in this chaptert we are merely concerned with blind con-
  14059. ceptual valuation, and with the effect of such valuation upon physical
  14060.  
  14061.  
  14062.  
  14063. 248 The Theory of Prehensioiis
  14064.  
  14065. feel- [379] ings which lie in the future beyond the actual entities in which
  14066. such valuations occur.
  14067.  
  14068. The initial problem is to discover the principles according to which
  14069. some eternal objects are prehended positively and others are prehended
  14070. negatively. Some are felt and others are eliminated.
  14071.  
  14072. In the solution of this problem five* additional categoreal conditions
  14073. must be added to the three such conditions which have already been ex-
  14074. plained. The conditions have regard to the origination, and coordination,
  14075. of conceptual feelings. They govern the general process of 'conceptual
  14076. imagination/ so far as concerns its origination from physical experience.
  14077.  
  14078. Category IV. The Category of Conceptual Valuation. From each physi-
  14079. cal feeling there is the derivation of a purely conceptual feeling whose
  14080. datum is the eternal object exemplified in the definiteness of the actual
  14081. entity, or oft the nexus, physically felt.
  14082.  
  14083. This category maintains the old principle that mentality originates from
  14084. sensitive experience. It lays down the principle that all sensitive experience
  14085. originates mental operations. It does not, however, mean that there is no
  14086. origination of other mental operations derivative from these primary men-
  14087. tal operations. Nor does it mean that these mental operations involve
  14088. consciousness, which is the product of intricate integration.
  14089.  
  14090. The mental pole originates as the conceptual counterpart of operations
  14091. in the physical pole. The two poles are inseparable in their origination.
  14092. The mental pole starts with the conceptual registration of the physical
  14093. pole. This conceptual registration constitutes the sole datum of experience
  14094. according to the sensationalist school. Writers of this school entirely
  14095. neglect physical feelings, originating in the physical pole. Hume's 'im-
  14096. pressions of sensation' and Kant's sensational data are considered in terms
  14097. only applicable to conceptual registration. Hence Kant's notion of the
  14098. chaos of such ulti- [380] mate data. Also Hume— at least, in his Treatise-
  14099. can only find differences of 'force and vivacity/
  14100.  
  14101. The subjective form of a conceptual feeling is valuation. These valua-
  14102. tions are subject to the Category of Subjective Unity. Thus the conceptual
  14103. registration is conceptual valuation; and conceptual valuation introduces
  14104. creative purpose. The mental pole introduces the subject as a determinant
  14105. of its own concrescence. The mental pole is the subject determining its
  14106. own ideal of itself by reference to eternal principles of valuation autono-
  14107. mously modified in their application to its own physical objective datum.
  14108. Every actual entity is 'in time' so far as its physical pole is concerned, and
  14109. is 'out of time' so far as its mental pole is concerned. It is the union of
  14110. two worlds, namely, the temporal world, and the world of autonomous
  14111. valuation. The integration of each simple physical feeling with its con-
  14112. ceptual counterpart produces in a subsequent phase a physical feeling
  14113. whose subjective form of re-enaction has gained or lost subjective intensity
  14114. according to the valuation up, or the valuation down, in the conceptual
  14115. feeling. So far there is merely subjective readjustment of the subjective
  14116.  
  14117.  
  14118.  
  14119. The Transmission of Feelings 249
  14120.  
  14121. forms. This is the phase of physical purpose. The effect of the conceptual
  14122. feeling is thus, so far, merely to provide that the modified subjective form
  14123. is not merely derived from the re-enaction of the objectified actual entity.
  14124. Also, in the complex subsequent integrations, we find that the conceptual
  14125. counterpart has a role in detachment from the physical feeling out of
  14126. which it originates.
  14127.  
  14128. Category V. The Category of Conceptual Reversion. There is sec-
  14129. ondary origination of conceptual feelings with data which are partially
  14130. identical with, and partially diverse from, the eternal objects forming the
  14131. data in the primary phase of the mental pole; the determination of iden-
  14132. tity and diversity depending on the subjective aim at attaining depth of
  14133. intensity by reason of contrast.
  14134.  
  14135. Thus the first phase of the mental pole is conceptual [381] reproduction,
  14136. and the second phase is a phase of conceptual reversion. In this second
  14137. phase the proximate novelties are conceptually felt. This is the process by
  14138. which the subsequent enrichment of subjective forms, both in qualitative
  14139. pattern, and in intensity through contrast, is made possible by the positive
  14140. conceptual prehension of relevant alternatives. 1 There is a conceptual con-
  14141. trast of physical incompatibles. This is the category which, as thus stated,
  14142. seems to limit the strict application of Plato's principle of reminiscence,
  14143. and of Hume's principle of recollection. Probably it does not contradict
  14144. anything that Plato meant by his principle. But it does limit the rigid
  14145. application of Hume's principle. Indeed Hume himself admitted excep-
  14146. tions. It is the category by which novelty enters the world; so that even
  14147. amid stability there is never undifferentiated endurance. But, as the cate-
  14148. gory states, reversion is always limited by the necessary inclusion of ele-
  14149. ments identical with elements in feelings of the antecedent phase. By the
  14150. Category of Subjective Unity, and by the seventh Category of Subjective
  14151. Harmony, to be explained later, all origination of feelings is governed
  14152. by the subjective imposition of aptitude for final synthesis. Also by the
  14153. Category of Objective Identity this aptitude always has its ground in the
  14154. two-way functionings of self-identical elements. Then in synthesis there
  14155. must always be a ground of identity and an aim at contrast. The aim at
  14156. contrast arises from the depth of intensity promoted by contrast. The
  14157. joint necessity of this ground of identity, and this aim at contrast, is
  14158. partially expressed in this Category of Conceptual Reversion, This 'aim
  14159. at contrast' is the expression of the ultimate creative purpose that each
  14160. unification shall achieve some maximum depth of intensity of feeling,
  14161. subject to the conditions of its concrescence. This ultimate purpose is
  14162. formulated in Category VIII.
  14163.  
  14164. The question, how, and in what sense, one unrealized [382] eternal ob-
  14165. ject can be more, or less, proximate to an eternal object in realized ingres-
  14166. sion— that is to say, in comparison with any other unfelt eternal object—
  14167.  
  14168. 1 For another discussion of this topic, cf. my Religion in the Making, Ch. Ill,
  14169. Sect. VII.
  14170.  
  14171.  
  14172.  
  14173. 250 The Theory of Prehensions
  14174.  
  14175. is left unanswered by this Category of Reversion. In conformity with the
  14176. ontological principle, this question can be answered only by reference to
  14177. some actual entity. Every eternal object has entered into the conceptual
  14178. feelings of God. Thus, a more fundamental account must ascribe the re-
  14179. verted conceptual feeling in a temporal subject to its conceptual feeling de-
  14180. rived, according to Category IV, from the hybrid physical feeling of the
  14181. relevancies conceptually ordered in God's experience. In this way, by the
  14182. recognition of God's characterization of the creative act, a more complete
  14183. rational explanation is attained. The Category of Reversion is then abol-
  14184. ished;* and Hume's principle of the derivation of conceptual experience
  14185. from physical experience remains without any exception.
  14186.  
  14187. SECTION IV
  14188.  
  14189. The two categories of the preceding section concerned the efficacy of
  14190. physical feelings, pure or hybrid, for the origination of conceptual feelings
  14191. in a later phase of their own subject. The present section considers analo-
  14192. gous feelings with diverse subjects 'scattered' throughout members of a
  14193. nexus. It considers a single subject, subsequent to the nexus, prehending
  14194. this multiplicity of scattered feelings as the data for a corresponding mul-
  14195. tiplicity of its own simple physical feelings, some pure and some hybrid.
  14196. It then formulates the process by which in that subject an analogy between
  14197. these various feelings— constituted by one eternal object, of whatever com-
  14198. plexity, implicated in the various analogous data of these feelings— is, by
  14199. a supervening process of integration, converted into one feeling having
  14200. for its datum the specific contrast between the nexus as one entity and
  14201. that eternal object. This contrast is what is familiarly known as the quali-
  14202. fication of the nexus by that eternal object. An inter- [383] mediate stage
  14203. in this process of integration is the formation in the final subject of one
  14204. conceptual feeling with that eternal object as its datum. This conceptual
  14205. feeling has an impartial relevance to the above-mentioned various simple
  14206. physical feelings of the various members of the nexus. It is this impartiality
  14207. of the conceptual feeling which leads to the integration in which the many
  14208. members of the nexus are collected into the one nexus which they form,
  14209. and in which that nexus is set in contrast to the one eternal object which
  14210. has emerged from their analogies.
  14211.  
  14212. Thus pure, and hybrid, physical feelings, issuing into a single concep-
  14213. tual feeling, constitute the preliminary phase of this transmutation in the
  14214. prehending subject. The integration of these feelings in that subject leads
  14215. to the transmuted physical feeling of a nexus as qualified by that eternal
  14216. object which is the datum of the single conceptual feeling. In this way the
  14217. world is physically felt as a unity, and is felt as divisible into parts which
  14218. are unities, namely, nexus. Each such unity has its own characteristics
  14219. arising from the undiscriminated actual entities which are members of
  14220. that nexus. In some cases objectification of the nexus has only indirect
  14221.  
  14222.  
  14223.  
  14224. The Transmission of Feelings 251
  14225.  
  14226. reference to the characteristics of its individual atomic actualities. In such
  14227. a case the objectification may introduce new elements into the world, for-
  14228. tunate or unfortunate. Usually the objectification gives direct informa-
  14229. tion, so that the prehending subject shapes itself as the direct outcome of
  14230. the order prevalent in the prehended nexus. Transmutation is the way
  14231. in which the actual world is felt as a community, and is so felt in virtue
  14232. of its prevalent order. For it arises by reason of the analogies between the
  14233. various members of the prehended nexus, and eliminates their differences.
  14234. Apart from transmutation our feeble intellectual operations would fail to
  14235. penetrate into the dominant characteristics of things. We can only under-
  14236. stand by discarding. Transmutation depends upon a categoreal condition.
  14237.  
  14238. [384] Category VI. The Category of Transmutation. When (in accord-
  14239. ance with Category IV, or with Categories IV and V) one and the samet
  14240. conceptual feeling is derived impartially by a prehending subject from
  14241. its analogous simple physical feelings of various actual entities, then in
  14242. a subsequent phase of integration—of these simple physical feelings to-
  14243. gether with the derivate conceptual feeling— the prehending subject may
  14244. transmute the datum of this conceptual feeling into a contrast with the
  14245. nexus of those prehended actual entities, or of some part of that nexus;
  14246. so that the nexus (or its part), thus qualified, is the objective datum of a
  14247. feeling entertained by this prehending subject.
  14248.  
  14249. Such a transmutation of simple physical feelings of many actualities
  14250. into one physical feeling of a nexus as one, is called a 'transmuted feeling/
  14251. The origination of such a feeling depends upon intensities, valuations, and
  14252. eliminations conjointly favourable.
  14253.  
  14254. In order to understand this categoreal condition, it must be noted that
  14255. the integration of simple physical feelings into a complex physical feeling
  14256. only provides for the various actual entities of the nexus being felt as sep-
  14257. arate entities requiring each other. We have to account for the substitu-
  14258. tion of the one nexus in place of its component actual entities. This is
  14259. Leibniz's problem which arises in his Monadology. He solves the problem
  14260. by an unanalysed doctrine of 'confusion/ Some category is required to pro-
  14261. vide a physical feeling of a nexus as one entity with its own categoreal
  14262. type of existence. This one physical feeling in the final subject is derived
  14263. by transmutation from the various analogous physical feelings entertained
  14264. by the various members of the nexus, together with their various analogous
  14265. conceptual feelings (with these various members as subjects) originated
  14266. from these physical feelings, either directly according to Category IV,
  14267. or indirectly according to Category V. The analogy of the physical feel-
  14268. ings consists in the fact that their definite character exhibits the same in-
  14269. gredient [385] eternal object. The analogy of the conceptual feelings con-
  14270. sists in the fact that this one eternal object, or one reversion from this
  14271. eternal object, is the datum for the various relevant conceptual feelings
  14272. entertained respectively by members of the nexus. The final prehending
  14273. subject prehends the members of the nexus, (i) by 'pure' physical feelings
  14274.  
  14275.  
  14276.  
  14277. 252 The Theory of Prehensions
  14278.  
  14279. in which the members are severally objectified by these analogous physical
  14280. feelings, and (ii) by hybrid physical feelings in which the members are
  14281. severally objectified by these analogous conceptual feelings.
  14282.  
  14283. In the prehending subject, these analogous, pure physical feelings origi-
  14284. nate a conceptual feeling, according to Category IV; and, according to
  14285. Category V, there may be a reverted conceptual feeling. There will be
  14286. only one direct conceptual feeling; for the simple physical feelings (in the
  14287. final subject) are analogous in the sense of exemplifying the same eternal
  14288. object. (If there be no reversion, this analogy extends over the pure and
  14289. the hybrid physical feelings. If there be important reversion, this analogy
  14290. only extends over the hybrid feelings with the reverted conceptual feel-
  14291. ings as data. This latter case is only important when the reverted feelings
  14292. involve the predominantly intense valuation.) Thus these many physical
  14293. feelings of diverse actualities originate in the final subject one conceptual
  14294. feeling. This single conceptual feeling has therefore an impartial reference
  14295. throughout the actualities of the nexus. Also reverted conceptual feelings
  14296. in the nexus are, in this connection, negligible unless they preserved this
  14297. impartiality of reference throughout the nexus. Excluding for the moment
  14298. the consideration of reverted feelings in the actualities of the nexus, the
  14299. hybrid physical feelings in the prehending subject also, by Category IV,
  14300. generate one conceptual feeling with impartial reference; also it is the same
  14301. conceptual feeling as that generated by the pure physical feelings (in the
  14302. final subject). Thus (with no reversion) the influence of the hybrid
  14303. physical feelings [386] is to enhance the intensity of the conceptual feeling
  14304. derived from the pure physical feelings. But there may be reversions to
  14305. be considered, that is to say, reversions with impartial reference throughout
  14306. the nexus. The reversion may originate in the separate actualities of the
  14307. nexus, or in the final prehending subject, or there may be a double rever-
  14308. sion involving both sources. Thus we must allow for the possibility of di-
  14309. verse reverted feelings, each with impartial reference. In so far as there
  14310. is concordance and the reversions are dominant, there will issue one con-
  14311. ceptual feeling of enhanced intensity. When there is discordance among
  14312. these various conceptual feelings, there will be elimination, and in general
  14313. no transmutation. But when, from some (or all) of these sources of im-
  14314. partial conceptual feelings, one dominant impartial conceptual feeling
  14315. emerges with adequate intensity, transmutation will supervene.
  14316.  
  14317. This impartiality of reference has then been transmuted into the physi-
  14318. cal feeling of that nexus, whole or partial, contrasted with some one eternal
  14319. object. It will be noted that this one impartial conceptual feeling is an
  14320. essential element of the process, whereby an impartial reference to the
  14321. whole nexus is introduced. Otherwise there would be no element to trans-
  14322. mute particular relevancies to the many members into general relevance
  14323. to the whole.
  14324.  
  14325. The eternal object which characterizes the nexus in this physical feeling
  14326.  
  14327.  
  14328.  
  14329. The Transmission of Feelings 253
  14330.  
  14331. may be an eternal object characterizing the analogous physical feelings,
  14332. belonging to all, or some, of the members of the nexus. In this case, the
  14333. nexus as a whole derives a character which in some way belongs to its
  14334. various members.
  14335.  
  14336. Again in the transmuted feeling only part of the original nexus may
  14337. be objectified, and the eternal object may have been derived from mem-
  14338. bers of the other part of the original nexus. This is the case for perception
  14339. in the mode of 'presentational immediacy/ to be further discussed in a
  14340. later chapter (Part IV, Ch. V; cf. alsof [387] Part II, Ch. II, Sect. I, and
  14341. Part II, Ch. IV, Sect. VII, and Part II, Ch. VIII) .
  14342.  
  14343. Also the eternal object may be the datum of a reverted conceptual feel-
  14344. ing, only indirectly derived from the members of the original nexus. In
  14345. this case, the transmuted feeling of the nexus introduces novelty; and in
  14346. unfortunate cases this novelty may be termed 'error/ But all the same,
  14347. the transmuted feeling, whatever be its history of transmutation, is a definite
  14348. physical fact whereby the final subject prehends the nexus. For example,
  14349. considering the example of presentational immediacy, colour-blindness
  14350. may be called 'error'; but nevertheless, it is a physical fact. A transmuted
  14351. feeling comes under the definition of a physical feeling.
  14352.  
  14353. Our usual way of consciously prehending the world is by these trans-
  14354. muted physical feelings. It is only when we are consciously aware of alien
  14355. mentalities that we even approximate to the conscious prehension of a
  14356. single actual entity. It will be found that transmuted feelings are very
  14357. analogous to prepositional feelings, and to conscious perceptions and
  14358. judgments in their sequence of integration. Vagueness has its origin in
  14359. transmuted feelings. For a quality, characterizing the mutual prehen-
  14360. sions of all the members of a nexus, is transmuted into a predicate of the
  14361. nexus. The intensity arising from the force of repetition makes this trans-
  14362. muted perception to be the prominent type of those feelings which in
  14363. further integrations acquire consciousness as an element in their subjective
  14364. forms. It represents a simplification of physical feeling, effected in the
  14365. course of integration.
  14366.  
  14367. According to this category the conceptual feelings entertained in any
  14368. nexus modify the future role of that nexus as a physical objective datum.
  14369. This category governs the transition from conceptual feelings in one actual
  14370. entity to physical feelings either in a supervening phase of itself or in a
  14371. later actual entity. What is conceptual earlier is felt physically later in an
  14372. extended role. Thus, for instance, a new 'form' has its emergent ingres-
  14373. sion con- [388] ceptually by reversion, and receives delayed exemplification
  14374. physically when the other categoreal conditions permit.
  14375.  
  14376. This joint operation of Categories IV and VI produces what has been
  14377. termed 'adversion' and 'aversion/ For the conceptual feelings in the ac-
  14378. tualities of the nexus, produced according to Category IV, have data
  14379. identical with the pattern exemplified in the objective data of the many
  14380.  
  14381.  
  14382.  
  14383. 254 The Theory of Prehensions
  14384.  
  14385. physical feelings. If in the conceptual feelings there is valuation upward,
  14386. then the physical feelings are transmitted t to the new concrescence with
  14387. enhanced intensity in its subjective form. This is 'adversion/
  14388.  
  14389. But if in the conceptual feelings there is valuation downward, then the
  14390. physical feelings are (in the later concrescence) either eliminated, or are
  14391. transmitted to it with attenuated intensity. This is 'aversion/ Thus 'adver-
  14392. sion' and 'aversion' are types of 'decision/
  14393.  
  14394. Thus the conceptual feeling with its valuation has primarily the charac-
  14395. ter of purpose, since it is the agent whereby the decision is made as to
  14396. the causal efficacy of its subject in its objectifications beyond itself. But it
  14397. only achieves this character of purpose by its integration with the physical
  14398. feeling from which it originates. This integration is considered in Chapter
  14399. V on 'Comparative Feelings/
  14400.  
  14401. It is evident that ad version and aversion, and also the Category of
  14402. Transmutation, only have importance in the case of high-grade organ-
  14403. isms. They constitute the first step towards intellectual mentality, though
  14404. in themselves they do not amount to consciousness. But an actual entity
  14405. which includes these operations must have an important intensity of con-
  14406. ceptual feelings able to mask and fuse the simple physical feelings.
  14407.  
  14408. Also the examination of the Category of Transmutation shows that the
  14409. approach to intellectuality consists in the gain of a power of abstraction.
  14410. The irrelevant multiplicity of detail is eliminated, and emphasis is laid
  14411. on the elements of systematic order in the actual world. In [389] so far
  14412. as there is trivial order, there must be trivialized actual entities. The right
  14413. coordination of the negative prehensions is one secret of mental progress;
  14414. but unless some systematic scheme of relatedness characterizes the en-
  14415. vironment, there will be nothing left whereby to constitute vivid pre-
  14416. hension of the world. The low-grade organism is merely the summation
  14417. of the forms of energy which flow in upon it in all their multiplicity of
  14418. detail. It receives, and it transmits; but it fails to simplify into intelligible
  14419. system. The physical theory of the structural flow of energy has to do
  14420. with the transmission of simple physical feelings from individual actuality
  14421. to individual actuality. Thus some sort of quantum theory in physics,
  14422. relevant to the existing type of cosmic order, is to be expected. The physical
  14423. theory of alternative forms of energy, and of the transformation from one
  14424. form to another form, ultimately depends upon transmission conditioned
  14425. by some exemplification of the Categories of Transmutation and Reversion.
  14426.  
  14427. SECTION V
  14428.  
  14429. The seventh categoreal condition governs the efficacy of conceptual
  14430. feelings both in the completion of their own subjects, and also in the
  14431. objectifications of their subjects in subsequent concrescence. It is the
  14432. Category of 'Subjectivet Harmony/
  14433.  
  14434. Category VII. The Category of Subjective Harmony. The valuations of
  14435.  
  14436.  
  14437.  
  14438. The Transmission of Feelings 255
  14439.  
  14440. conceptual feelings are mutually determined by their adaptation to be
  14441. joint elements in a satisfaction aimed at by the subject.
  14442.  
  14443. This categoreal condition should be compared with the Category of
  14444. 'Subjective Unity/ and also with the Category of 'Conceptual Reversion/ In
  14445. the former category the intrinsic inconsistencies, termed logical/ are the
  14446. formative conditions in the pre-established harmony. In this seventh
  14447. category, and in the Category of Reversion, aesthetic adaptation for an
  14448. end is the formative condition in the pre-established harmony. These three
  14449. categories [390] express the ultimate particularity of feelings. For the
  14450. superject which is their outcome is also the subject which is operative in
  14451. their production. They are the creation of their own creature. The point
  14452. to be noticed is that the actual entity, in a state of process during which it
  14453. is not fully definite, determines its own ultimate definiteness. This is the
  14454. whole point of moral responsibility. Such responsibility is conditioned by
  14455. the limits of the data, and by the categoreal conditions of concrescence.
  14456.  
  14457. But autonomy is negligible unless the complexity is such that there is
  14458. great energy in the production of conceptual feelings according to the
  14459. Category of Reversion. This Category of Reversion has to be considered in
  14460. connection with the Category of Aesthetic Harmony.** For the contrasts
  14461. produced by reversion are contrasts required for the fulfillment of the
  14462. aesthetic ideal. Unless there is complexity, ideal diversities lead to physical
  14463. impossibilities, and thence to impoverishment. It requires a complex con-
  14464. stitution to stage diversities as consistent contrasts.
  14465.  
  14466. It is only by reason of the Categories of Subjective Unity, and of Subjec-
  14467. tive Harmony, that the process constitutes the character of the product,
  14468. and that conversely the analysis of the product discloses the process. J
  14469.  
  14470.  
  14471.  
  14472. CHAPTER IV
  14473. PROPOSITIONS AND FEELINGS
  14474.  
  14475. SECTION I
  14476.  
  14477. [391] The nature of consciousness has not yet been adequately ana-
  14478. lysed. The initial basic feelings, physical and conceptual, have been men-
  14479. tioned, and so also has the final synthesis into the affirmation-negation
  14480. contrast. But between the beginning and the end of the integration into
  14481. consciousness, there lies the origination of a 'propositional feeling/ A
  14482. propositional feeling is a feeling whose objective datum is a proposition.
  14483. Such a feeling does not in itself involve consciousness. But all forms of
  14484. consciousness arise from ways of integration of propositional feelings with
  14485. other feelings, either physical feelings or conceptual feelings. Conscious-
  14486. ness belongs to the subjective forms of such feelings.
  14487.  
  14488. A proposition enters into experience as the entity forming the datum of
  14489. a complex feeling derived from the integration of a physical feeling with
  14490. a conceptual feeling. 1 Now a conceptual feeling does not refer to the actual
  14491. world, in the sense that the history of this actual world has any peculiar
  14492. relevance to its datum. This datum is an eternal object; and an eternal
  14493. object refers only to the purely general any among undetermined actual
  14494. entities. In itself an eternal object evades any selection among actualities
  14495. or epochs. You cannot know what is red by merely thinking of redness.
  14496. You can only find red things by adventuring amid physical experiences
  14497. in this actual world. This doctrine is the ultimate ground of empiricism;
  14498. namely, that eternal objects tell no tales as to their ingressions.
  14499.  
  14500. [392] But now a new kind of entity presents itself. Such entities are the
  14501. tales that perhaps might be told about particular actualities. Such entities
  14502. are neither actual entities, nor eternal objects, nor feelings. They are prop-
  14503. ositions. A proposition must be true or false. Herein a proposition differs
  14504. from an eternal object; for no eternal object is ever true or false. This
  14505. difference between propositions and eternal objects arises from the fact
  14506. that truth and falsehood are always grounded upon a reason. But according
  14507. to the ontological principle (the eighteenth! 'category of explanation'),
  14508. a reason is always a reference to determinate actual entities. Now an eter-
  14509. nal object, in itself, abstracts from all determinate actual entities, includ-
  14510. ing even God. It is merely referent to any such entities, in the absolutely
  14511. general sense of any. Then there can be no reason upon which to found
  14512.  
  14513. 1 Cf.t also 'Physical Purposes' considered in Ch. V.
  14514.  
  14515.  
  14516.  
  14517. Propositions and Feelings 257
  14518.  
  14519. the truth or falsehood of an eternal object. The very diversity of eternal
  14520. objects has for its reason their diversity of functioning in this actual world.
  14521.  
  14522. Thus the endeavour to understand eternal objects in complete abstrac-
  14523. tion from the actual world results in reducing them to mere undifferen-
  14524. tiated nonentities. This is an exemplification of the categoreal principle,
  14525. that the general metaphysical character of being an entity is *'to be a deter-
  14526. minant in the becoming of actualities/ Accordingly the differentiated
  14527. relevance of eternal objects to each instance of the creative process re-
  14528. quires their conceptual realization in the primordial nature of God. He
  14529. does not create eternal objects; for his nature requires them in the same
  14530. degree that they require him. This is an exemplification of the coherence
  14531. of the categoreal types of existence. The general relationships of eternal
  14532. objects to each other, relationships of diversity and of pattern, are their
  14533. relationships in God's conceptual realization. Apart from this realization,
  14534. there is mere isolation indistinguishable from nonentity.
  14535.  
  14536. But a proposition, while preserving the indeterminateness of an eternal
  14537. object, makes an incomplete abstrac- [393] tion from determinate actual
  14538. entities. It is a complex entity, with determinate actual entities among its
  14539. components. These determinate actual entities, considered formaliter and
  14540. not as in the abstraction of the proposition, do afford a reason determining
  14541. the truth or falsehood of the proposition. But the proposition in itself,
  14542. apart from recourse to these reasons, tells no tale about itself; and in this
  14543. respect it is indeterminate like the eternal objects.
  14544.  
  14545. A propositional feeling (as has been stated) arises from a special type
  14546. of integration synthesizing a physical feeling with a conceptual feeling.
  14547. The objective datum of the physical feeling is either one actual entity,
  14548. if the feeling be simple, or is a determinate nexus of actual entities, if the
  14549. physical feeling be more complex. The datum of the conceptual feeling is
  14550. an eternal object which is referent (qua possibility) + to any actual entities,
  14551. where the any is absolutely general and devoid of selection. In the in-
  14552. tegrated objective datum the physical feeling provides its determinate set
  14553. of actual entities, indicated by their felt physical relationships to the sub-
  14554. ject of the feeling. These actual entities are the logical subjects of the
  14555. proposition. The absolute generality of the notion of any, inherent in an
  14556. eternal object, is thus eliminated in the fusion. In the proposition, the
  14557. eternal object, in respect to its possibilities as a determinant of nexus, f is
  14558. restricted to these logical subjects. The proposition may have the restricted
  14559. generality of referring to any among these provided logical subjects; or
  14560. it may have the singularity of referring to the complete set of provided
  14561. logical subjects as potential relata, each with its assigned status, in the
  14562. complex pattern which is the eternal object. The proposition is the poten-
  14563. tiality of the eternal object, as a determinant of denniteness, in some
  14564. determinate mode of restricted reference to the logical subjects. This
  14565. e ternal object is the 'predicative pattern' of the proposition. The set of
  14566. logical subjects is either completely singled out as these logical subjects in
  14567.  
  14568.  
  14569.  
  14570. 258 The Theory of Prehensions
  14571.  
  14572. this predicative pattern or is collec- [394] tively singled out as any of these
  14573. logical subjects in this pattern, or as some of these logical subjects in this
  14574. pattern. Thus the physical feeling indicates the logical subjects and pro-
  14575. vides them respectively with that individual definition necessary to assign
  14576. the hypothetic status of each in the predicative pattern. The conceptual
  14577. feeling provides the predicative pattern. Thus in a proposition the logical
  14578. subjects are reduced to the status of food for a possibility. Their real role
  14579. in actuality is abstracted from; they are no longer factors in fact, except
  14580. for the purpose of their physical indication. Each logical subject becomes
  14581. a bare 'W among actualities, with its assigned hypothetical relevance to
  14582. the predicate. 2
  14583.  
  14584. It is evident that the datum of the conceptual feeling reappears as the
  14585. predicate in the proposition which is the datum of the integral, preposi-
  14586. tional feeling. In this synthesis the eternal object has suffered the elimina-
  14587. tion of its absolute generality of reference. The datum of the physical
  14588. feeling has also suffered elimination. For the peculiar objectification of
  14589. the actual entities, really effected in the physical feeling, is eliminated,
  14590. except in so far as it is required for the services of the indication. The
  14591. objectification remains only to indicate that definiteness which the logical
  14592. subjects must have in order to be hypothetical food for that predicate.
  14593. This necessary indication of the logical subjects requires the actual world
  14594. as a systematic environment. For there can be no definite position in pure
  14595. abstraction. The proposition is the possibility of that predicate applying
  14596. in that assigned way to those logical subjects. In every proposition, as
  14597. such and without going beyond it, there is complete indeterminateness
  14598. so far as concerns its own realization in a propositional feeling, and as
  14599. regards its own truth. The logical subjects are, nevertheless, in fact actual
  14600. entities which are definite in their realized mutual relatedness. Thus the
  14601. proposition is in fact true, or false. But its own [395] truth, or its own
  14602. falsity, is no business of a proposition. That question concerns only a
  14603. subject entertaining a propositional feeling with that proposition for its
  14604. datum. Such an actual entity is termed a 'prehending subject' of the
  14605. proposition. Even a prehending subject is not necessarily judging the
  14606. proposition. That particular case has been discussed earlier in Chapter
  14607. IX of Part II. In that chapter the term 'judging subject' was used in place
  14608. of the wider term 'prehending subject/
  14609.  
  14610. To summarize this discussion of the general nature of a proposition:
  14611. A proposition shares with an eternal object the character of indeterminate-
  14612. ness, in that both are definite potentialities for actuality with undeter-
  14613. mined realization in actuality. But they differ in that an eternal object
  14614. refers to actuality with absolute generality, whereas a proposition refers
  14615. to indicated logical subjects. Truth and falsehood always require some
  14616. element of sheer givenness. Eternal objects cannot demonstrate what they
  14617.  
  14618. 2 Cf . my Concept of Nature, Ch. I, for another exposition of this train of
  14619. thought.
  14620.  
  14621.  
  14622.  
  14623. Propositions and Feelings 259
  14624.  
  14625. are except in some given fact. The logical subjects of a proposition supply
  14626. the element of givenness requisite for truth and falsehood.
  14627.  
  14628.  
  14629.  
  14630. SECTION II
  14631.  
  14632. A proposition has neither the particularity of a feeling, nor the reality
  14633. of a nexus. It is at datum for feeling, awaiting a subject feeling it. Its
  14634. relevance to the actual world by means of its logical subjects makes it a
  14635. lure for feeling. In fact many subjects may feel it with diverse feelings,
  14636. and with diverse sorts of feelings. The fact that propositions were first
  14637. considered in connection with logic, and the moralistic preference for
  14638. true propositions, have obscured the role of propositions in the actual
  14639. world. Logicians only discuss the judgment of propositions. Indeed some
  14640. philosophers fail to distinguish propositions from judgments; and most
  14641. logicians consider propositions as merely appanages to judgments. The
  14642. result is that false propositions have fared badly, thrown into the dust-
  14643. heap, neglected. But in the real world it is more important [396] that a
  14644. proposition be interesting than that it be true. The importance of truth is,
  14645. that it adds to interest. The doctrine here maintained is that judgment-
  14646. feelings form only one subdivision of propositional feelings: and arise
  14647. from the special sort of integration of propositional feelings with other
  14648. feelings. Propositional feelings are not, in their simplest examples, con-
  14649. scious feelings. Consciousness only arises in some integrations in which
  14650. propositional feelings are among the components integrated. Another point
  14651. to notice is that the physical feeling, which is always one component in
  14652. the history of an integral propositional feeling, has no unique relation to
  14653. the proposition in question, nor has the subject of that feeling, which is
  14654. also a subject prehending the proposition. Any subject with any physical
  14655. feeling which includes in its objective datum the requisite logical subjects!
  14656. can in a supervening phase entertain a propositional feeling with that
  14657. proposition as its datum. It has only to originate a conceptual feeling with
  14658. the requisite predicative pattern as its datum, and then to integrate the
  14659. two feelings into the required propositional feeling.
  14660.  
  14661. Evidently new propositions come into being with the creative advance of
  14662. the world. For every proposition involves its logical subjects; and it cannot
  14663. be the proposition which it is, unless those logical subjects are the actual
  14664. entities which they are. Thus no actual entity can feel a proposition, if its
  14665. actual world does not include the logical subjects of that proposition. The
  14666. proposition 'Caesar crossed the Rubicon' could not be felt by Hannibal
  14667. m any occasion of his existence on earth. Hannibal could feel propositions
  14668. with certain analogies to this proposition, but not this proposition. It is,
  14669. farther, to be noticed that the form of words in which propositions are
  14670. framed also includes an incitement to the origination of an affirmative
  14671. judgment-feeling. In imaginative literature, this incitement is inhibited
  14672. by the general context, and even by the form and make-up of the material
  14673.  
  14674.  
  14675.  
  14676. 260 The Theory of Prehensions
  14677.  
  14678. book. Sometimes there is even a form of words designed [397] to inhibit
  14679. the formation of a judgment-feeling, such as 'once upon a time/ The
  14680. verbal statement also includes words and phrases to symbolize the sort of
  14681. physical feelings necessary to indicate the logical subjects of the proposi-
  14682. tion. But language is always elliptical, and depends for its meaning upon
  14683. the circumstances of its publication. For example, the word 'Caesar' may
  14684. mean a puppy dog, or a negro slave, or the first Roman emperor.
  14685.  
  14686. The actual entities whose actual worlds include the logical subjects of
  14687. a proposition will be said to fall within the 'locus' of that proposition.
  14688. The proposition is prehensible by them. Of those actual entities which
  14689. fall within the locus of a proposition, only some will prehend it positively.
  14690. There are two kinds of pure propositional feelings, namely, 'imaginative
  14691. feelings' and 'perceptive feelings/ These kinds are not sharply distin-
  14692. guished, but their extreme instances function very differently.
  14693.  
  14694. SECTION III
  14695.  
  14696. A propositional feeling can arise only in a late phase of the process of
  14697. the prehending subject. For it requires, in earlier phases: (a) a physical
  14698. feeling whose objective datum includes the requisite logical subjects; and
  14699. (/?) a physical feeling involving a certain eternal object among the deter-
  14700. minants of the definiteness of its datum; and (y) the conceptual feeling
  14701. of this eternal object, necessarily derivate from the physical feeling under
  14702. heading (/?), according to categoreal condition IV; and perhaps (8), some
  14703. conceptual feeling which is a reversion from the former conceptual feeling,
  14704. according to categoreal condition V, involving another eternal object as
  14705. its datum.
  14706.  
  14707. The physical feeling under the heading (a) will be termed the 'indica-
  14708. tive feeling'; the physical feeling under heading (/?) will be called the
  14709. 'physical recognition/ The physical recognition is the physical basis of the
  14710. conceptual feeling which provides the predicative pattern.
  14711.  
  14712. [398] The 'predicative pattern' is either the eternal object which is the
  14713. datum of the conceptual feeling under the heading (y), or it is the eternal
  14714. object which is the datum of the conceptual feeling under the heading (8).
  14715. In the former case, the second conceptual feeling, namely, that under the
  14716. heading (8), is irrelevant to the consideration of the propositional feeling.
  14717. In either case, that conceptual feeling whose datum is the predicative
  14718. pattern is called the 'predicative feeling/
  14719.  
  14720. In this account of the origin of the predicative feeling, we are in gen-
  14721. eral agreement with Locke and Hume, who hold that every conceptual
  14722. feeling has a physical basis. But Hume lays down the principle that all
  14723. eternal objects are first felt physically, and thus would only allow of the
  14724. origination of the predicative feeling under heading (y). However he
  14725. makes two concessions which ruin his general principle. For he allows the
  14726. independent origination of intermediate 'shades' in a scale of shades, and
  14727.  
  14728.  
  14729.  
  14730. Propositions and Feelings 261
  14731.  
  14732. also of new 'manners' of pattern. Both of these cases are allowed for by
  14733. the principle of 'reversion/ which is appealed to under heading (8). The
  14734. propositional feeling arises in the later phase in which there is integration
  14735. of the 'indicative feeling' with the 'predicative feeling/ In this integra-
  14736. tion the two data are synthesized by a double elimination involving both
  14737. data. The actual entities involved in the datum of the indicative feeling
  14738. are reduced to a bare multiplicity in which each is a bare 'it' with the elimi-
  14739. nation of the eternal object really constituting the definiteness of that
  14740. nexus. But the integration rescues them from this mere multiplicity by
  14741. placing them in the unity of a proposition with the given predicative!
  14742. pattern. Thus the actualities, which were first felt as sheer matter of fact,
  14743. have been transformed into a set of logical subjects with the potentiality
  14744. for realizing an assigned predicative pattern. The predicative pattern has
  14745. also been limited by elimination. For as a datum in the conceptual feeling,
  14746. it held its possibility for realization in respect to absolutely any actual en-
  14747. tities; but in [399] the proposition its possibilities are limited to just
  14748. these logical subjects.
  14749.  
  14750. The subjective form of the propositional feeling will depend on cir-
  14751. cumstances, according to categoreal condition VII. It may, or may not,
  14752. involve consciousness; it may, or may not, involve judgment. It will involve
  14753. aversion, or adversion, that is to say, decision. The subjective form will
  14754. only involve consciousness when the 'affirmation-negation* contrast has
  14755. entered into it. In other words, consciousness enters into the subjective
  14756. forms of feelings, when those feelings are components in an integral feel-
  14757. ing whose datum is the contrast between a nexus which is, and a propo-
  14758. sition which in its own nature negates the decision of its truth or false-
  14759. hood. The logical subjects of the proposition are the actual entities in the
  14760. nexus. Consciousness is the way of feeling that particular real nexus, as in
  14761. contrast with imaginative freedom about it. The consciousness may con-
  14762. fer importance upon what the real thing is, or upon what the imagination
  14763. is, or upon both.
  14764.  
  14765. SECTION IV
  14766.  
  14767. A proposition, as such, is impartial between its prehending subjects,
  14768. and in its own nature it does not fully determine the subjective forms of
  14769. such prehensions. But the different propositional feelings, with the same
  14770. proposition as datum, in different prehending subjects, are widely different
  14771. according to differences of their histories in these subjects. They can be
  14772. divided into two main types, here termed, respectively, 'perceptive feel-
  14773. ings' and 'imaginative feelings/ This difference is founded on the com-
  14774. parison between the 'indicative feeling' from which the logical subjects
  14775. are derived, and the 'physical recognition' from which the predicative
  14776. pattern is derived.
  14777.  
  14778. [400] t These physical feelings are either identical or different. If they
  14779.  
  14780.  
  14781.  
  14782. 262 The Theory of Prehensions
  14783.  
  14784. be one and the same feeling, the derived propositional feeling is here
  14785. called a 'perceptive feeling/ For in this case, as will be seen, the proposi-
  14786. tion predicates of its logical subjects a character derived from the way in
  14787. which they are physically felt by that prehending subject.
  14788.  
  14789. If the physical feelings be different, the derived propositional feeling
  14790. is here called an 'imaginative feeling: For in this case, as will be seen, the
  14791. proposition predicates of its logical subjects a character without any guar-
  14792. antee of close relevance to the logical subjects. Since these physical feel-
  14793. ings are complex, there are degrees of difference between them. Two
  14794. physical feelings may be widely diverse or almost identical. Thus the
  14795. distinction between the two types of propositional feelings is not as sharp-
  14796. cut as it might be. This distinction is still further blurred by noting that
  14797. three distinct cases arise which differentiate perceptive feelings into three
  14798. species, which in their turn shade off into each other.
  14799.  
  14800. Since we are now dealing with perceptive feelings, we have on hand only
  14801. one physical feeling which enjoys the role both of the indicative feeling,
  14802. and of the physical recognition. In the first place, suppose that the predica-
  14803. tive pattern is derived straight from the physical recognition under the
  14804. heading (y), so that there is no reversion and the heading (8) is irrelevant.
  14805. In this case the derived propositional feeling will be termed an 'authen-
  14806. tic perceptive feeling/ Such a feeling, by virtue of its modes of origination,
  14807. has as its datum a proposition whose predicate is in some way realized in
  14808. the real nexus of its [401] logical subjects. Thus the proposition felt pro-
  14809. poses a predicate derived from the real nexus, and not refracted by the
  14810. prehending subject. But nevertheless the proposition need not be true, so
  14811. far as concerns the way in which it implicates the logical subjects with
  14812. the predicate. For the primary physical feeling of that nexus by the pre-
  14813. hending subject may have involved 'transmutation' according to categoreal
  14814. condition VI. In this case, the proposition ascribes to its logical subjects
  14815. the physical enjoyment of a nexus with the definition of its predicate;
  14816. whereas that predicate may have only been enjoyed conceptually by these
  14817. logical subjects. Thus, what the proposition proposes as a physical fact
  14818. in the nexus, was in truth only a mental fact. Unless it is understood for
  14819. what it is, error arises. Such understanding belongs to the subjective form.
  14820.  
  14821. But if the primary physical feeling involves no reversion in any stage,
  14822. then the predicate of the proposition is that eternal object which con-
  14823. stitutes the definiteness of that nexus. In this case, the proposition is, with-
  14824. out qualification, true. The authentic perceptive feeling will then be
  14825. termed 'direct/ Thus there are 'indirect' perceptive feelings (when 're-
  14826. version' is involved), and 'direct' perceptive feelings; and feelings of both
  14827. these species are termed 'authentic/ In the case of these 'authentic' feelings,
  14828. the predicate has realization in the nexus, physically or ideally, apart from
  14829. any reference to the prehending subject.
  14830.  
  14831. + Thirdly, and lastly, the predicative feeling may have arisen in the pre-
  14832. hending subject by reversion, according to the heading (8) of the previous
  14833.  
  14834.  
  14835.  
  14836. Propositions and Feelings 263
  14837.  
  14838. section. In this case the predicate has in it some elements which really
  14839. contribute to the definiteness of the nexus; but it has also some elements
  14840. which contrast with corresponding elements in the nexus. These latter
  14841. elements have been introduced in the concrescence of the prehending
  14842. subject. The predicate is thus distorted from the truth by the subjectivity
  14843. of the prehending subject. Such a perceptive feeling will be termed 'un-
  14844. authentic/
  14845.  
  14846. Unauthentic feelings are feelings derived from a 'tied' imagination, in
  14847. the sense that there is only one physical basis for the whole origination,
  14848. namely, that physical feeling which is both the 'indicative' feeling! and
  14849. the 'physical recognition/ The imagination is tied to one ultimate fact.
  14850.  
  14851. SECTION V
  14852.  
  14853. Imaginative feelings belong to the general case when the indicative
  14854. feeling and the physical recognition differ. [402] But there are degrees
  14855. of difference, which can vary from the case when the two nexus, forming
  14856. the objective data of the two feelings respectively, enjoy the extreme of
  14857. remote disconnection, to the case at the other extreme when the two
  14858. nexus are almost identical. But in so far as there is diversity between the
  14859. feelings, there is some trace of a free imagination. The proposition which
  14860. is the objective datum of an imaginative feeling has a predicate derived,
  14861. with or without reversions, from a nexus which in some respects differs
  14862. from the nexus providing the logical subjects. Thus the proposition is felt
  14863. as an imaginative notion concerning its logical subjects. The proposition
  14864. in its own nature gives no suggestion as to how it should be felt. In one
  14865. prehending subject it may be the datum of a perceptive feeling, and in
  14866. another prehending subject it may be the datum of an imaginative feeling.
  14867. But the subjective forms of the two feelings will differ according to the
  14868. differences in the histories of the origination of those feelings in their
  14869. respective subjects.
  14870.  
  14871. The subjective forms of propositional feelings are dominated by valua-
  14872. tion, rather than by consciousness. In a pure propositional feeling the
  14873. logical subjects have preserved their indicated particularity, but have lost
  14874. their own real modes of objectification. The subjective form lies in the
  14875. twilight zone between pure physical feeling and the clear consciousness
  14876. which apprehends the contrast between physical feeling and imagined
  14877. possibility. A propositional feeling is a lure to creative emergence in the
  14878. transcendent future. When it is functioning as a lure, the propositional
  14879. feeling about the logical subjects of the proposition may in some subse-
  14880. quent phase promote decision involving intensification of some physical
  14881. reeling of those subjects in the nexus. Thus, according to the various
  14882. categoreal conditions, propositions intensify, attenuate, inhibit, or trans-
  14883. mute, without necessarily entering into clear consciousness, or encounter-
  14884. ing judgment.
  14885.  
  14886.  
  14887.  
  14888. 264 The Theory of Prehensions
  14889.  
  14890. It follows that in the pursuit of truth even physical [403] feelings must
  14891. be criticized, since their evidence is not final apart from an analysis of
  14892. their origination. This conclusion merely confirms what is a commonplace
  14893. in all scientific investigation, that we can never start from dogmatic cer-
  14894. tainty. Such certainty is always an ideal to which we approximate as the
  14895. result of critical analysis. When we have verified that we depend upon an
  14896. authentic perceptive feeling, whose origination involves no reversions,
  14897. then we know that the proposition which is the datum of that feeling is
  14898. true. Thus there can be no immediate guarantee of the truth of a propo-
  14899. sition, by reason of the mode of origination of the propositional feeling,
  14900. apart from a critical scrutiny of that mode of origination.
  14901.  
  14902. The feeling has to be (i) perceptive, (ii) authentic, and (iii) direct,
  14903. where a definite meaning has, in the preceding section, been assigned to
  14904. each of these conditions.
  14905.  
  14906. t There is, however, always this limitation to the security of direct
  14907. knowledge, based on direct physical feeling, namely, that the creative
  14908. emergence can import into the physical feelings of the actual world
  14909. pseudo-determinants which arise from the concepts entertained in that
  14910. actual world, and not from the physical feelings in that world.
  14911.  
  14912. This possibility of error is peculiarly evident in the case of that special
  14913. class of physical feelings which belong to the mode of 'presentational
  14914. immediacy/
  14915.  
  14916. The proposition which is the datum of an imaginative feeling may be
  14917. true. The two questions of the origination of consciousness in the sub-
  14918. jective forms of feelings, and of the intuitive judgment of a proposition,
  14919. apart from the mode of origination of the feeling of it, must now be
  14920. considered.
  14921.  
  14922. SECTION VI
  14923.  
  14924. Language, as usual, is always ambiguous as to the exact proposition
  14925. which it indicates. Spoken language is merely a series of squeaks. Its func-
  14926. tion is (a) to arouse in the prehending subject some physical feeling in-
  14927. dicative of the logical subjects of the proposition, (/?) to arouse in the
  14928. prehending subject some physical feeling which plays the part of the
  14929. 'physical recognition/ (y) to promote the sublimation of the 'physical
  14930. recognition' into the conceptual 'predicative feeling/ (8) to promote the
  14931. integration of the indicative feeling and the predicative feeling into the
  14932. required propositional feeling. But in this complex function there is always
  14933. a tacit reference to [404] the environment of the occasion of utterance.
  14934. Consider the traditional example, 'Socrates is mortal/
  14935.  
  14936. This proposition may mean It is mortal/ In this case the word 'Socrates'
  14937. in the circumstances of its utterance merely promotes a physical feeling
  14938. indicating the it which is mortal.
  14939.  
  14940. The proposition may mean 'It is Socratic and mortal'; where 'Socratic
  14941. is an additional element in the predicative pattern.
  14942.  
  14943.  
  14944.  
  14945. Propositions and Feelings 265
  14946.  
  14947. We now turn to the words denoting the predicative pattern, namely,
  14948. either 'mortal,' or 'Socratic and mortal.' The slightest consideration dis-
  14949. closes the fact that it is pure convention to suppose that there is only
  14950. one logical subject to the proposition. The word 'mortal' means a certain
  14951. relationship to the general nexus of actual entities in this world which isf
  14952. possible for any one of the actual entities. 'Mortal' does not mean 'mortal
  14953. in any possible world/ it means 'mortal in this world.' Thus there is a
  14954. general reference to this actual world as exemplifying a scheme of things
  14955. which render 'mortality' realizable in it.
  14956.  
  14957. The word 'Socratic' means 'realizing the Socratic predicate in Athenian
  14958. society.' It does not mean 'Socratic, in any possible world'; nor does it
  14959. mean 'Socratic, anywhere in this world': it means 'Socratic, in Athens.'
  14960. Thus 'Socratic,' as here used, refers to a society of actual entities realizing
  14961. certain general systematic properties such that the Socratic predicate is
  14962. realizable in that environment. Also the 'Athenian society' requires that
  14963. this actual world exemplifies a certain systematic scheme, amid which
  14964. 'Athenianism' is realizable.
  14965.  
  14966. Thus in the one meaning of the phrase 'Socrates is mortal,' the logical
  14967. subjects are one singular It (Socrates) and the actual entities of this actual
  14968. world, forming a society amid which mortality is realizable and including
  14969. the former 'IV In the other meaning, there are also included among the
  14970. logical subjects the actual entities forming the Athenian society. These
  14971. actual entities are [405] required for the realization of the predicative
  14972. pattern 'Socratic and mortal' and are the definitely indicated logical sub-
  14973. jects. They also require that the general scheme of this actual world be
  14974. such as to support 'Athenianism' in conjunction with 'mortality .'+
  14975.  
  14976.  
  14977.  
  14978. CHAPTER V
  14979. THE HIGHER PHASES OF EXPERIENCE
  14980.  
  14981. SECTION I
  14982.  
  14983. [406] 'Comparative feelings' are the result of integrations not yet con-
  14984. sidered: their data are generic contrasts. The infinite variety of the more
  14985. complex feelings come under the heading 'comparative feelings/
  14986.  
  14987. We have now to examine two simple types of comparative feelings.
  14988. One type arises from the integration of a 'propositional feeling' with the
  14989. 'indicative feeling' from which it is partly derived. Feelings of this type
  14990. will be termed 'intellectual feelings/ This type of comparative feelings is
  14991. subdivided into two species: one species consists of 'conscious percep-
  14992. tions'; and the other species consists of 'intuitive judgments/ The sub-
  14993. jective forms of intuitive judgments also involve consciousness. Thus
  14994. 'conscious perceptions' and 'intuitive judgments' are alike 'intellectual
  14995. feelings/ Comparative feelings of the other type are termed 'physical pur-
  14996. poses/ Such a feeling arises from the integration of a conceptual feeling
  14997. with the basic physical feeling from which it is derived, either directly
  14998. according to categoreal condition IV (the Category of Conceptual Valua-
  14999. tion), or indirectly according to categoreal condition V (the Category
  15000. of Conceptual Reversion). But this integration is a more primitive type
  15001. of integration than that which produces, from the same basic physical
  15002. feeling, the species of propositional feelings termed 'perceptive/ The
  15003. subjective forms of these physical purposes are either 'adversions' or
  15004. 'aversions/ The subjective forms of physical purposes do not involve
  15005. consciousness unless these feelings acquire integration with conscious
  15006. perceptions or intuitive judgments. \407]
  15007.  
  15008. SECTION II
  15009.  
  15010. In an intellectual feeling the datum is the generic contrast between a
  15011. nexus of actual entities and a proposition with its logical subjects mem
  15012. bers of the nexus. In every generic contrast its unity arises from the two-
  15013. way functioning of certain entities which are components in each of the
  15014. contrasted factors. This unity expresses the conformation to the second
  15015. categoreal condition (the Category of Objective Identity). The common
  15016. 'subject' entertaining the two feelings effects an integration whereby each
  15017. of these actual entities obtains its one role of a two-way functioning in
  15018. the one generic contrast. As an element in the subject no objectified actual
  15019.  
  15020. 266
  15021.  
  15022.  
  15023.  
  15024. The Higher Phases of Experience 267
  15025.  
  15026. entity can play two disconnected parts. There can only be one analysable
  15027. part. Thus what in origination is describable as a pair of distinct ways of
  15028. functioning of each actual entity in the two factors of the generic con-
  15029. trast respectivelyt is realized in the subject as one r61e with a two-way
  15030. aspect. This two-way aspect is unified as 'contrast/ This one analysable
  15031. part involves in itself the contrast between the sheer matter of fact, namely,
  15032. what the objectified actual entity in question contributes to the objecti-
  15033. fied nexus in the physical feeling, and the mere potentiality of the same
  15034. actual entity for playing its assigned part in the predicative pattern of the
  15035. proposition, in the eventuality of the proposition's realization. This con-
  15036. trast is what has been termed the 'affirmation-negation contrast/ It is the
  15037. contrast between the affirmation of objectified fact in the physical feeling,
  15038. and the mere potentiality, which is the negation of such affirmation, in
  15039. the propositional feeling. It is the contrast between 'in fact' and 'might be,'
  15040. in respect to particular instances in this actual world. The subjective form
  15041. of the feeling of this contrast is consciousness. Thus in experience, con-
  15042. sciousness arises by reason of intellectual feelings, and in proportion to
  15043. the variety and intensity of such feelings. But, in conformity with the
  15044. seventh [408] categoreal condition (the Category of Subjective Harmony),
  15045. subjective forms, which arise as factors in any feeling, are finally in the
  15046. satisfaction shared in the unity of all feelings;f all feelings acquire their
  15047. quota of irradiation in consciousness.
  15048.  
  15049. This account agrees with the plain facts of our conscious experience.
  15050. Consciousness flickers; and even at its brightest, there is a small focal
  15051. region of clear illumination, and a large penumbral region of experience
  15052. which tells of intense experience in dim apprehension. The simplicity of
  15053. clear consciousness is no measure of the complexity of complete experi-
  15054. ence. Also this character of our experience suggests that consciousness is
  15055. the crown of experience, only occasionally attained, not its necessary
  15056. base.
  15057.  
  15058. SECTION III
  15059.  
  15060. A feeling is termed a 'belief/ or is said to include an element of 'belief/
  15061. when its datum is a proposition, and its subjective form includes, as the
  15062. defining element in its emotional pattern, a certain form, or eternal object,
  15063. associated with some gradation of intensity. This eternal object is 'belief-
  15064. character/ When this character enters into the emotional pattern, then,
  15065. according to the intensity involved, the feeling, whatever else it be, is to
  15066. some degree a belief.
  15067.  
  15068. This variation in the intensity of belief-character is insisted on by Locke
  15069. in his Essay. He writes (IV, XV, 3) :
  15070. The entertainment the mind gives this sort of propositions is called
  15071. "belief/' "assent/' or "opinion/' which is the admitting or receiving any
  15072. proposition for true, upon arguments or proofs that are found to per-
  15073. suade us to receive it as true, without certain knowledge that it is so.
  15074.  
  15075.  
  15076.  
  15077. 268 The Theory of Prehensions
  15078.  
  15079. And herein lies the difference between probability and certainty,
  15080. faith and knowledge, that in all thef parts of knowledge there is intui-
  15081. tion; each immediate idea, each step has its visible and certain connec-
  15082. tion: in belief not so.
  15083.  
  15084. [409] Locke's distinction between certainty and uncertain belief is ad-
  15085. mirable. But it is not nearly so important as it looks. For it is not the im-
  15086. mediate intuition that we are usually concerned with. We only have its
  15087. recollection recorded in words. Whether the verbal record of a recollec-
  15088. tion recalls to our minds a true proposition must always be a matter of
  15089. great uncertainty. Accordingly our attitude towards an immediate intuition
  15090. must be that of the gladiators, "morituri te salutamus," as we pass into the
  15091. limbo where we rely upon the uncertain record. It must be understood
  15092. that we are not speaking of the objective probability of a proposition,
  15093. expressing its relation to certain other propositions. Comparative firmness
  15094. of belief is a psychological fact which may, or may not, be justified by the
  15095. objective evidence. This belief-character takes various forms from its fusion
  15096. with consciousness derived from the various types of intellectual feelings.
  15097.  
  15098. SECTION IV
  15099.  
  15100. Conscious perception is the feeling of what is relevant to immediate
  15101. fact in contrast with its potential irrelevance. This general description
  15102. must now be explained in detail.
  15103.  
  15104. "Conscious perceptions' are of such importance that it is worth while
  15105. to rehearse the whole sequence of their origination. It will be seen that
  15106. alternative modes of origination are involved, and that some of these
  15107. modes produce erroneous perceptions. Thus the criticism of conscious per-
  15108. ceptions has the same importance as the criticism of judgments, intuitive
  15109. and inferential.
  15110.  
  15111. In the first place, there is one basic physical feeling, from which the
  15112. whole sequence of feelings originates for the 'subject' in question. From
  15113. this physical feeling, the propositional feeling of the sort termed 'percep-
  15114. tive' arises. The conscious perception is the comparative feeling arising
  15115. from the integration of the perceptive feeling with this original physical
  15116. feeling.
  15117.  
  15118. [410] In the account of the origination of the 'perceptive' feeling (Part
  15119. III, Ch. IV, Sect. IV), the various species of such feelings are analysed
  15120. first into 'authentic' feelings and 'unauthentic' feelings; and secondly,
  15121. 'authentic' feelings are analysed into 'direct' feelingsf and 'indirect' feel-
  15122. ings. Without qualification a direct perceptive feeling feels its logical sub-
  15123. jects as potentially invested with a predicate expressing an intrinsic char-
  15124. acter of the nexus which is the initial datum of the physical feeling; with
  15125. qualification this statement is also true of an indirect feeling. The qualifi-
  15126. cation is that the secondary conceptual feelings, entertained in the nexus
  15127.  
  15128.  
  15129.  
  15130. The Higher Phases of Experience 269
  15131.  
  15132. by reason of reversion (cf. categoreal condition V), have been trans-
  15133. muted so as to be felt in the 'subject' (the final subject of the conscious
  15134. perception) as if they had been physical facts in the nexus. Of course
  15135. such transmutation of physical feeling only arises when no incompatibili-
  15136. ties are involved.
  15137.  
  15138. Thus, in general, a transmuted physical feeling only arises as the out-
  15139. come of a complex process of incompatibilities and inhibitions. Apart
  15140. from exceptional circumstances only to be found in few high-grade organ-
  15141. isms, transmutation only accounts for physical feelings of negligible in-
  15142. tensity. It is, however, important to note that even authentic physical
  15143. feelings can distort the character of the nexus felt by transmuting felt
  15144. concept into felt physical fact. In this way authentic perceptive feelings
  15145. can introduce error into thought; and transmuted physical feelings can
  15146. introduce novelty into the physical world. Such novelty may be either for-
  15147. tunate or disastrous. But the point is that novelty in the physical world,
  15148. and error in authentic perceptive feeling, arise by conceptual functioning,
  15149. according to the Category of Reversion.
  15150.  
  15151. Putting aside the case when these transmuted perceptive feelings have
  15152. importance, consider the prehending subject with its direct perceptive
  15153. feeling. The subject has its concrescent phase involving two factors, the
  15154. orig- [411] inal physical feeling, and the derived perceptive feeling. In the
  15155. earlier factor the nexus, physically felt, is objectified through its own proper
  15156. physical bonds. There are no incompatibilities between fact and reverted
  15157. concept to produce attenuation. The objective datum is therefore felt
  15158. with its own proper intensities, transmitted to the subjective form of the
  15159. physical feeling. The other factor in the integration is the 'perceptive'
  15160. feeling. The datum of this feeling is the proposition with the actual en-
  15161. tities of the nexus as its logical subjects, and with its predicate also de-
  15162. rived from the nexus. The whole origination of this perceptive feeling has
  15163. its sole basis in the physical feeling, which plays the part both of 'indicative
  15164. feeling' and of 'physical recognition' (cf. Part III, Ch. IV, Sect. III).
  15165.  
  15166. The integration of the two factors into the conscious perception thus
  15167. confronts the nexus as fact, with the potentiality derived from itself, lim-
  15168. ited to itself, and exemplified in itself. This confrontation is the generic
  15169. contrast which is the objective datum of the integral feeling. The sub-
  15170. jective form thus assumes its vivid immediate consciousness of what the
  15171. nexus really is in the way of potentiality realized. In Hume's phraseology,
  15172. there is an 'impression' of the utmost 'force and vivacity/
  15173.  
  15174. There are therefore two immediate guarantees of the correctness of a
  15175. conscious perception: one is Hume's test of 'force and vivacity,' and the
  15176. other is the illumination by consciousness of the various feelings involved
  15177. m the process. Thus the fact, that the physical feeling has not transmuted
  15178. concept into physical bond, lies open for inspection. Neither of these
  15179. tests is infallible. There is also the delayed test, that the future conforms
  15180.  
  15181.  
  15182.  
  15183. 270 The Theory of Prehensions
  15184.  
  15185. to expectations derived from this assumption. This latter test can be re-
  15186. alized only by future occasions in the life of an enduring object, the en-
  15187. during percipient.
  15188.  
  15189. It is to be observed that what is in doubt is not the immediate percep-
  15190. tion of a nexus which is a fragment of [412] the actual world. The du-
  15191. bitable element is the definition of this nexus by the observed predicate.
  15192.  
  15193. An unauthentic perceptive feeling arises in the subject when its own
  15194. conceptual origination from its own basic physical feeling passed on to
  15195. the secondary stage of producing a reverted conceptual feeling to play the
  15196. part of predicative feeling. The physical feeling may, or may not, have also
  15197. suffered loss of direct relevance by reason of derivation from conceptual
  15198. reversions in the nexus. But anyhow the subject by its own process of
  15199. reversion has produced for the logical subjects a predicate which has no
  15200. immediate relevance to the nexus, either as physical fact or as conceptual
  15201. functioning in the nexus. Thus the comparative feeling which integrates
  15202. the physical feeling with the unauthentic perceptive feeling has for its
  15203. datum the generic contrast of the nexus with a proposition, whose logical
  15204. subjects comprise the actualities in the nexus, and whose predicate partly
  15205. agrees with the complex pattern exemplified in the nexus and partly dis-
  15206. agrees with it This case is really the conscious perception of a proposition
  15207. imaginatively arrived at, which concerns the nexus and disagrees with the
  15208. facts. The case is in fact more analogous to intellectual feelings of the
  15209. second species, namely, to intuitive judgments. But by reason of the use
  15210. of one basic physical feeling, in the double function of indicative feeling
  15211. and of physical recollection, the proposition in the comparative feeling
  15212. will have some of the vivid relevance to the nexus in the same feeling,
  15213. which arises in the case of authentic perceptions. Practically, however, this
  15214. case is an intuitive judgment in which there is consciousness of a proposi-
  15215. tion as erroneous.
  15216.  
  15217. SECTION V
  15218.  
  15219. The term 'judgment' refers to three species among the comparative
  15220. feelings with which we are concerned. In each of these feelings the datum
  15221. is the generic contrast between an objectified nexus and a proposition
  15222. whose logical subjects make up the nexus. The three species [413] are com-
  15223. posed of (i) those feelings in the 'yes-form/ (ii) those feelings in the
  15224. 'no-form/ and (iii) those feelings in the 'suspense-form.'
  15225.  
  15226. In all three species of felt contrast, the datum obtains its unity by reason
  15227. of the objective identify of the actual entities on both sides of the con-
  15228. trast In the yes-form' there is the further ground of unity by reason of
  15229. the identity of the pattern of the objectified nexus with the predicate. In
  15230. the 'no-form' this latter ground of unity is replaced by a contrast involving
  15231. incompatible diversity. In the 'suspense-form' t the predicate is neither
  15232. identical, nor incompatible, with the pattern. It is diverse from, and com-
  15233.  
  15234.  
  15235.  
  15236. The Higher Phases of Experience 271
  15237.  
  15238. patible with, the pattern in the nexus as objectified: the nexus, in its own
  15239. 'formal' existence, may, or may not, in fact exemplify both the pattern
  15240. and the predicate. In this species of comparative feeling there is therefore
  15241. contrast between pattern and predicate, without incompatibility.
  15242.  
  15243. In intuitive judgments, as has been stated, the comparative feeling is
  15244. the integration of the physical feeling of a nexus with a propositional feel-
  15245. ing whose logical subjects are the actual entities in the nexus. So far as
  15246. this general description is concerned intuitive judgments and conscious
  15247. perceptions do not differ, and are therefore classed together as 'intellectual'
  15248. feelings. But in the case of intuitive judgments there is a more complex
  15249. process of origination. There are two distinct physical feelings, the in-
  15250. dicative feeling and the physical recollection (Part III, Ch. IV, Sect. III).
  15251. The predicative feeling originates from the physical recollection, either
  15252. immediately according to categoreal condition IV or mediately according
  15253. to categoreal condition V. The integration of the predicative feeling with
  15254. the indicative feeling produces the 'imaginative feeling' f (cf. Part III,
  15255. Ch. IV, Sect. V). This is a propositional feeling with the logical subjects
  15256. of its datum* derived from the indicative feelingf and with the predica-
  15257. tive pattern derived from the! physical recollection. These two physical
  15258. feelings may be relatively \414) disconnected in their origination. Thus the
  15259. imaginative feeling may have in its subjective form no bias as to belief or
  15260. disbelief; or, if there be such bias, the intensity of the emotion may be
  15261. slight.
  15262.  
  15263. The intuitive judgment is the comparative feeling with its datum con-
  15264. stituted by the generic contrast between the nexus involved in the indica-
  15265. tive feeling and the proposition involved in the imaginative feeling. In this
  15266. generic contrast each actual entity has its contrast of two-way functioning.
  15267. One way is its functioning in the exemplified pattern of the nexus, and
  15268. the other way is its functioning in the potential pattern of the proposition.
  15269. If in addition to the contrast between exemplification and potentiality,
  15270. there be identity as to pattern and predicate, then by the Category of Ob-
  15271. jective Unity there is also the single complex eternal object in its two-
  15272. way functioning, namely, as exemplified and as potential. In this case, the
  15273. proposition coheres with the nexus and this coherence is its truth. Thus
  15274. 'truth' is the absence of incompatibility or of any 'material contrast' in
  15275. the patterns of the nexus and of the proposition in their generic contrast.
  15276. The sole contrast, involving the Category of Objective Diversity, is merely
  15277. that between exemplification and potentiality, and in all other respects
  15278. the coherence is governed by the Category of Objective Identity.
  15279.  
  15280. If a contrast arise in any respect other than that between exemplifica-
  15281. tion and potentiality, then the two patterns are not identical. Then the
  15282. proposition in some sense, important or unimportant, is not felt as true.
  15283.  
  15284. It will be noted that the intuitive judgment in its subjective form con-
  15285. forms to what there is to feel in its datum. Thus error cannot arise from
  15286. the subjective form of the integration constituting the judgment. But it
  15287.  
  15288.  
  15289.  
  15290. 272 The Theory of Prehensions
  15291.  
  15292. can arise because the indicative feeling, which is one of the factors in-
  15293. tegrated, may in its origin have involved [415] reversion. Thus error arises
  15294. by reason of operations which lie below consciousness, though they may
  15295. emerge into consciousness and lie open for criticism.
  15296.  
  15297. Finally, what differentiates an intuitive judgment from a conscious
  15298. perception is that a conscious perception is the outcome of an originative
  15299. process which has its closest possible restriction to the fact, thus con-
  15300. sciously perceived. But the distinction between the two species is not
  15301. absolute. Among the conscious perceptions we find transmutations by
  15302. which concepts entertained in the nexus are transmuted into physical
  15303. feelings in the nexus, and also the unauthentic propositional feelings in
  15304. which a proposition with a 'reverted' predicate has arisen. These are cases
  15305. in which conscious perceptions take on the general character of intuitive
  15306. judgments. On the other hand the diversity between the two physical
  15307. feelings— when they are diverse— may be trivial. The nexus which is the
  15308. datum of the one may be practically identical with the nexus which is
  15309. the datum of the other. In such a case an intuitive judgment approximates
  15310. to a conscious perception.
  15311.  
  15312. The condensed analysis of the stages of origination of an intuitive judg-
  15313. ment is (i) the 'physical recollection' and the 'indicative feeling/ (ii) the
  15314. 'predicative feeling/ derived from the 'physical recollection/ f (iii) the
  15315. 'imaginative feeling/I derived by integration of the 'predicative feeling'
  15316. with the 'indicative feeling/ (iv) the 'intuitive judgment/ f derived by
  15317. integration of the 'imaginative feeling' with the 'indicative feeling.' t
  15318.  
  15319. It is a great mistake to describe the subjective form of an intuitive
  15320. judgment as necessarily including definite belief or disbelief in the propo-
  15321. sition. Three cases arise. The generic contrast which is the datum of the
  15322. intuitive judgment may exhibit the predicate of the proposition as exem-
  15323. plified in the objectified nexus. In this case, the subjective form will in-
  15324. clude definite belief. Secondly, the predicate may be exhibited as incom-
  15325. patible with the [416] eternal objects exemplified in the objectified nexus.
  15326. In this case, the subjective form will include definite disbelief. But there is
  15327. a third case, which is in fact the more usual one: the predicate may be
  15328. exhibited as irrelevant, wholly or partially, to the eternal objects exem-
  15329. plified in the objectified nexus. In this case, the subjective form need ex-
  15330. hibit neither belief nor disbelief. It may include one or the othert of these
  15331. decisions, but it need not do so. This third case will be termed the case
  15332. of 'suspended judgment,' Thus an intuitive judgment may be a belief, or
  15333. a disbelief, or a suspended judgment It is the task of the inferential pro-
  15334. cess sometimes to convert a suspended judgment into a belief, or a dis-
  15335. belief, so far as the final satisfaction is concerned.
  15336.  
  15337. But the main function of intellectual feelings is neither belief, nor dis-
  15338. belief, nor even suspension of judgment. The main function of these
  15339. feelings is to heighten the emotional intensity accompanying the valua-
  15340. tions in the conceptual feelings involved, and in the mere* physical
  15341.  
  15342.  
  15343.  
  15344. The Higher Phases of Experience 273
  15345.  
  15346. purposes which are more primitive than any intellectual feelings. They per-
  15347. form this function by the sharp-cut way in which they limit abstract
  15348. valuation to express possibilities relevant to definite logical subjects.
  15349. In so far as these logical subjects, by reason of other prehensions, are
  15350. topics of interest, the proposition becomes a lure for the conditioning of
  15351. creative action. In other words, its prehension effects a modification of the
  15352. subjective aim.
  15353.  
  15354. Intellectual feelings, in their primary function, are concentration of
  15355. attention involving increase of importance. This concentration of atten-
  15356. tion also introduces the criticism of physical purposes, which is the intel-
  15357. lectual judgment of truth or falsehood. But intellectual feelings are not
  15358. to be understood unless it be remembered that they already find at work
  15359. 'physical purposes' more primitive than themselves. Consciousness follows,
  15360. and does not precede, the entry of the conceptual prehensions of the
  15361. relevant universals. [417]
  15362.  
  15363. SECTION VI
  15364.  
  15365. It is evident that an affirmative intuitive judgment is very analogous to
  15366. a conscious perception. A conscious perception is a very simplified type
  15367. of affirmative intuitive judgment; and a direct affirmative intuitive judg-
  15368. ment is a very sophisticated case of conscious perception. The difference
  15369. between the two has its origin in the fact that one involves a perceptive
  15370. feeling, and the other involves an imaginative feeling. Only one set of
  15371. actual entities is involved in the formation of the perceptive feeling. These
  15372. actual entities are the logical subjects of the proposition which is felt.
  15373. But two sets of actual entities are involved in the formation of an imagi-
  15374. native feeling. Only one of these sets provides the logical subjects of the
  15375. proposition which is felt: the other set is finally eliminated in the process
  15376. of origination. The difference between the two feelings, the perceptive
  15377. feeling and the imaginative feeling, does not therefore lie in the proposi-
  15378. tion which is felt. It lies in the emotional patterns of the two feelings. In
  15379. either case this emotional pattern is derivative from the process of origina-
  15380. tion. In the case of the perceptive feeling, the emotional pattern reflects
  15381. the close connection of the predicate with the logical; subjects, throughout
  15382. the process of origination. In the case of the imaginative feeling, this emo-
  15383. tional pattern reflects the initial disconnection of the predicate from the
  15384. logical subjects. This example illustrates that in the integration of feelings,
  15385. components which are eliminated from the matter of the integral feeling
  15386. may yet leave their mark on its emotional pattern. The triumph of con-
  15387. sciousness comes with the negative intuitive judgment. In this case there
  15388. is a conscious feeling of what might be, and is not. The feeling directly
  15389. concerns the definite negative prehensions enjoyed by its subject. It is the
  15390. feeling of absence, and it feels this absence as produced by the definite
  15391. exclusiveness of what is really present. Thus, the explicitness of negation,
  15392.  
  15393.  
  15394.  
  15395. 274 The Theory of Prehensions
  15396.  
  15397. [418] which is the peculiar characteristic of consciousness, is here at its
  15398.  
  15399. maximum.
  15400. The two cases of intuitive judgment, namely, the affirmative intuitive
  15401.  
  15402. judgment and the negative intuitive judgment, are comparatively rare.
  15403.  
  15404. These two cases of intuitive judgment, together with conscious perception,
  15405.  
  15406. correspond to what Locke calls 'knowledge/ Locke's section (IV, XIV, 4)t
  15407.  
  15408. on this subject is short enough to be quoted in full:
  15409. Judgment is the presuming things to be so without perceiving it.—
  15410. Thus the mind has two faculties conversant about truth and false-
  15411. hood,—
  15412.  
  15413. First, Knowledge, whereby it certainly perceives, and is undoubt-
  15414. edly satisfied of the agreement or disagreement of any ideas.
  15415.  
  15416. Secondly, Judgment, which is the putting ideas together, or separat-
  15417. ing them from one another in the mind, when their certain agree-
  15418. ment or disagreement is not perceived, but presumed to be so; which
  15419. is, as the word imports, taken to be so before it certainly appears.
  15420. And if it so unites or separates them as in reality things are, it is right
  15421. judgment
  15422.  
  15423. What Locke calls 'judgment' is here termed 'inferential judgment/
  15424. The process of origination of a suspended judgment consists in (i) the
  15425. 'physical recollection' and the 'indicative feeling/ (ii) the 'conceptual
  15426. imagination/ derivative from the 'physical recollection/ (iii) the 'preposi-
  15427. tional imagination/ derived by integration of the 'indicative feeling' with
  15428. the 'conceptual imagination/ (iv) the 'suspended judgment,* derived by
  15429. integration of the 'indicative feeling' with the 'propositional imagination/
  15430. the relation between the objectifying predicate and the imagined predi-
  15431. cate} being such as to preclude either case of direct judgment.
  15432.  
  15433. The suspended judgment thus consists of the integration of the imagi-
  15434. native feeling with the indicative feeling, in the case where the imagined
  15435. predicate fails to find identification with the objectifying predicate, or
  15436. with [419] any part of it; but does find compatible contrast with it. It is
  15437. the feeling of the contrast between what the logical subjects evidently are,
  15438. and what the same subjects in addition may be. This suspended judgment
  15439. is our consciousness of the limitations involved in objectification. If, in the
  15440. comparison of an imaginative feeling with fact, we merely knew what is
  15441. and what is not, then we should have no basis for discovering the work of
  15442. objectification in effecting omissions from the formal constitutions of
  15443. things. It is this additional knowledge of the compatibility of what we
  15444. imagine with what we physically feel, that gives this information. We must
  15445. not oversimplify the formal constitutions of the higher grade of acts of
  15446. concrescence by construing a suspended judgment as though it were a
  15447. negative judgment. Our whole progress in scientific theory, and even in
  15448. subtility of direct observation, depends on the use of suspended judgments.
  15449. It is to be noted that a suspended judgment is not a judgment of proba-
  15450. bility. It is a judgment of compatibility. The judgment tells us what may
  15451. be additional information respecting the formal constitutions of the logical
  15452.  
  15453.  
  15454.  
  15455. The Higher Phases of Experience 275
  15456.  
  15457. subjects, information which is neither included nor excluded by our direct
  15458. perception. This is a judgment of fact concerning ourselves. Suspended
  15459. judgments are weapons essential to scientific progress. But in intuitive
  15460. judgments the emotional pattern may be dominated by indifference to
  15461. truth or falsehood. We have then 'conscious imagination/ We are feeling
  15462. the actual world with the conscious imputation of imagined predicates
  15463. be they true or false.
  15464.  
  15465. When we compare these three cases of intuitive judgment (involving
  15466. attention to truth) with conscious imagination (involving inattention to
  15467. truth), that is to say, with 'imputative feeling/ we note that, except in the
  15468. case of negative judgments, the datum of the conscious imagination is
  15469. identical with the datum of the corresponding judgment. Nevertheless,
  15470. the feelings are very different in their emotional patterns. One emotional
  15471. [420] pattern is dominated by indifference to truth; and the other emo-
  15472. tional pattern by attention to truth. This indifference to truth is other-
  15473. wise to be expressed as readiness to eliminate the true objectifying pat-
  15474. tern exemplified in the objective datum of the physical feeling in question;
  15475. while the attention to truth is merely the refusal to eliminate this pattern.
  15476. But these emotional elements in the subjective forms are not dictated
  15477. by any diversity of data in the two feelings. For except in the case of the
  15478. direct negative judgment, the datum is the same in both types of feeling.
  15479. The emotional form of a feeling cannot be merely deduced from datum
  15480. felt, though it has close relation to it. The emotional pattern in the sub-
  15481. jective form of any one feeling arises from the subjective aim dominating
  15482. the entire concrescent process. The other feelings of the subject may be
  15483. conceived as catalytic agents. They are intellectually separable from the
  15484. feeling in question. But that feeling is in fact the outcome of the subjec-
  15485. tive aim of the subject which is its locus; and the emotional pattern is the
  15486. peculiar way in which the subject asserts itself in its feeling. This explana-
  15487. tion of the status of the emotional pattern is merely an application of the
  15488. doctrine that a feeling appropriates elements of the universe, which in
  15489. themselves are other than the subject; and absorbs these elements into
  15490. the real internal constitution of its subject by synthesizing them in the
  15491. unity of an emotional pattern expressive of its own subjectivity.
  15492.  
  15493. This mutual dependence of the emotional pattern of a feeling on the
  15494. other feelings of the same subjectf may be termed the 'mutual sensitivity'
  15495. of feelings. It is also one aspect of the incurable 'particularity' of a feeling,
  15496. in the sense that no feeling can be abstracted from its subject.
  15497.  
  15498.  
  15499.  
  15500. SECTION VII
  15501.  
  15502. 'Physical purposes' constitute a type of comparative feelings more primi-
  15503. tive than the type of intellectual feel- \421] ings. In general, it seems as
  15504. though intellectual feelings are negligible, so as only to obtain importance
  15505. in exceptional actual entities. We have no means of testing this assump-
  15506.  
  15507.  
  15508.  
  15509. 276 The Theory of Prehensions
  15510.  
  15511. tion in any crucial way. It is however the assumption usually made; and
  15512. therefore it may be presumed that there is some evidence which persuades
  15513. people to embrace the doctrine. But in fact no evidence, one way or the
  15514. other, has ever been produced. We know that there are some few entities
  15515. on the surface of this earth with intellectual feelings; and there our knowl-
  15516. edge ends, so far as temporal entities are concerned.
  15517.  
  15518. In the more primitive type of comparative feelings indetermination as
  15519. to its own ingressions— so prominent in intellectual feelings— is the aspect
  15520. of the eternal object which is pushed into the background. In such a type
  15521. of physical purposes the integration of a physical feeling and a conceptual
  15522. feeling does not involve the reduction of the objective datum of the physi-
  15523. cal feeling to a multiplicity of bare logical subjects. The objective datum
  15524. remains the nexus that it is, exemplifying the eternal objects whose in-
  15525. gression constitutes its definiteness. Also the indeterminateness as to its
  15526. own ingressions is eliminated from the eternal object which is the datum
  15527. of the conceptual} feeling. In the integral comparative feeling the datum
  15528. is the contrast of the conceptual datum with the reality of the objectified
  15529. nexus. The physical feeling is feeling a real fact; the conceptual feeling is
  15530. valuing an abstract possibility. The new datum is the compatibility or in-
  15531. compatibility of the fact as felt with the eternal object as a datum in
  15532. feeling. This synthesis of a pure abstraction with a real fact, as in feeling,
  15533. is a generic contrast. In respect to physical purposes, the cosmological
  15534. scheme which is here being developed requires f us to hold that all actual
  15535. entities include physical purposes. The constancy of physical purposes ex-
  15536. plains the persistence of the order of nature, and in particular of 'enduring
  15537. objects/
  15538.  
  15539. [422] The chain of stages in which a physical purpose originates is sim-
  15540. pler than in the case of intellectual feelings: (i) there is a physical feeling;
  15541. (ii) the primary conceptual correlate of the physical feeling is generated,
  15542. according to categoreal condition IV; (iii) this physical feeling is in-
  15543. tegrated with its conceptual correlate to form the physical purpose. Such
  15544. physical purposes are called physical purposes of the first species.
  15545.  
  15546. In such a physical purpose, the datum is the generic contrast between
  15547. the nexus, felt in the physical feeling, and the eternal object valued in the
  15548. conceptual feeling. This eternal object is also exemplified as the pattern of
  15549. the nexus. Thus the conceptual valuation now closes in upon the feeling
  15550. of the nexus as it stands in the generic contrast, exemplifying the valued
  15551. eternal object. This valuation accorded} to the physical feeling endows
  15552. the transcendent creativity with the character of adversion, or of aversion.
  15553. The character of adversion secures the reproduction of the physical feeling,
  15554. as one element in the objectification of the subject beyond itself. Such re-
  15555. production may be thwarted by incompatible objectification derived from
  15556. other feelings. But a physical feeling, whose valuation produces adversion,
  15557. is thereby an element with some force of persistence into the future be-
  15558. yond its own subject. It is felt and re-enacted down a route of occasions
  15559.  
  15560.  
  15561.  
  15562. The Higher Phases of Experience 277
  15563.  
  15564. forming an enduring object. Finally this chain of transmission meets with
  15565. incompatibilities, and is attenuated, or modified, or eliminated from fur-
  15566. ther endurance.
  15567.  
  15568. When there is aversion, instead of adversion, the transcendent creativity
  15569. assumes the character that it inhibits, or attenuates, the objectification of
  15570. that subject in the guise of that feeling. Thus aversion tends to eliminate
  15571. one possibility by which the subject may itself be objectified in the future.
  15572. Thus adversions promote stability; and aversions promote change without
  15573. any indication of the sort of change. In itself an aversion [423] promotes
  15574. the elimination of content, and the lapse into triviality.
  15575.  
  15576. The bare character of mere responsive re-enaction constituting the origi-
  15577. nal physical feeling in its first phase t is enriched in the second phase by
  15578. the valuation accruing from integration with the conceptual correlate. In
  15579. this way, the dipolar character of concrescent experience provides in the
  15580. physical pole for the objective side of experience, derivative from an ex-
  15581. ternal actual world, and provides in the mental pole for the subjective side
  15582. of experience, derivative from the subjective conceptual valuations cor-
  15583. relate to the physical feelings. The mental operations have a double office.
  15584. They achieve, in the immediate subject, the subjective aim of that subject
  15585. as to the satisfaction to be obtained from its own initial data. In this way
  15586. the decision derived from the actual world, which is the efficient cause, is
  15587. completed by the decision embodied in the subjective aim,f which is the
  15588. final cause. Secondly, the physical purposes of a subject by their valuations
  15589. determine the relative efficiency of the various feelings to enter into the
  15590. objectifications of that subject in the creative advance beyond itself. In
  15591. this function, the mental operations determine their subject in its charac-
  15592. ter of an efficient cause. Thus the mental pole is the link whereby the
  15593. creativity is endowed with the double character of final causation, and
  15594. efficient causation. The mental pole is constituted by the decisions in vir-
  15595. tue of which matters of fact enter into the character of the creativity. It
  15596. has no necessary connection with consciousness; though, where there is
  15597. origination of intellectual feelings, consciousness does in fact enter into
  15598. the subjective forms.
  15599.  
  15600. SECTION VIII
  15601.  
  15602. The second species of physical purposes is due to the origination of
  15603. reversions in the mental pole. It is due to this second species that vibration
  15604. and rhythm have a [424] dominating importance in the physical world.
  15605. Reversions are the conceptions which arise by reason of the lure of con-
  15606. trast, as a condition for intensity of experience. This lure is expressible as
  15607. a categoreal condition.
  15608.  
  15609. Categoreal Condition VIII. The Category of Subjective Intensity. The
  15610. subjective aim, whereby there is origination of conceptual feeling, is at+
  15611. intensity of feeling (a) in the immediate subject, and (p) in the relevant
  15612. future.
  15613.  
  15614.  
  15615.  
  15616. 278 The Theory of Prehensions
  15617.  
  15618. We first note (i) that intensity of feeling due to any realized ingression
  15619. of an eternal object is heightened when that eternal object is one element
  15620. in a realized contrast between eternal objects, and (ii) that two or more
  15621. contrasts may be incompatible for joint ingression, or may jointly enter
  15622. into a higher contrast.
  15623.  
  15624. It follows that balanced complexity is the outcome of this* Category of
  15625. Subjective Aim. Here 'complexity' means the realization of contrasts, of
  15626. contrasts of contrasts, and so on; and 'balance' means the absence of at-
  15627. tenuations due to the elimination of contrasts which some elements in the
  15628. pattern would introduce and other elements inhibit.
  15629.  
  15630. Thus there is the urge towards the realization of the maximum number
  15631. of eternal objects subject to the restraint that they must be under condi-
  15632. tions of contrast. But this limitation to 'conditions of contrast' is the de-
  15633. mand for 'balance/ For 'balance' here means that no realized eternal ob-
  15634. ject shall eliminate potential contrasts between other realized eternal ob-
  15635. jects. Such eliminations attenuate the intensities of feeling derivable from
  15636. the ingressions of the various elements of the pattern. Thus so far as the
  15637. immediate present subject is concerned, the origination of conceptual val-
  15638. uation according to Category IV is devoted to such a disposition of em-
  15639. phasis as to maximize the integral intensity derivable from the most fa-
  15640. vourable balance. The subjective aim is the selection of the balance amid
  15641. the given materials. But one element in the immediate feelings of the
  15642. concrescent [425] subject is comprised of the anticipatory feelings of the
  15643. transcendent future in its relation to immediate fact. This is the feeling
  15644. of the objective immortality inherent in the nature of actuality. Such an-
  15645. ticipatory feelings involve realization of the relevance of eternal objects as
  15646. decided in the primordial nature of God. In so far as these feelings in the
  15647. higher organisms rise to important intensities there are effective feelings
  15648. of the more remote alternative possibilities. Such feelings are the con-
  15649. ceptual feelings which arise in accordance with the Category of Reversion
  15650. (Category Vt).
  15651.  
  15652. But there must be 'balance/ and 'balance' is the adjustment of identities
  15653. and diversities for the introduction of contrast with the avoidance of in-
  15654. hibitions by incompatibilities. Thus this secondary phase, involving the
  15655. future, introduces reversion and is subject to Category VIII. t Each re-
  15656. verted conceptual feeling hast its datum largely identical with that of its
  15657. correlate primary feeling of the same pole. In this way, readiness for syn-
  15658. thesis is promoted. But the introduction of contrast is obtained by the
  15659. differences, or reversions, in some elements of the complex data. The
  15660. category expresses the rule that what is identical, and what is reverted, are
  15661. determined by the aim at a favourable balance. The reversion is due to
  15662. the aim at complexity as one condition for intensity.
  15663.  
  15664. When this reverted conceptual feeling acquires a relatively high in-
  15665. tensity of upward valuation in its subjective form, the resulting integra-
  15666. tion of physical feeling, primary conceptual feeling, and secondary con-
  15667.  
  15668.  
  15669.  
  15670. The Higher Phases of Experience 279
  15671.  
  15672. ceptual feeling, produces a more complex physical purpose than in the
  15673. former case when the reverted conceptual feeling was negligible. There is
  15674. now the physical feeling as valued by its integration with the primary
  15675. conceptual feeling, the integration with the contrasted secondary concep-
  15676. tual feeling, the heightening of the scale of subjective intensity by the
  15677. introduction of conceptual contrast, and the concentration of this height-
  15678. ened intensity upon the reverted \426] feeling in virtue of its being the
  15679. novel factor introducing the contrast. The physical purpose thus provides
  15680. the creativity with a complex character, which is governed (i) by the
  15681. Category of Conceptual Reversion, in virtue of which the secondary concep-
  15682. tual feeling arises, (ii) bv the Category of Transmutation, in virtue of which
  15683. conceptual feeling can be transmitted as physical feeling, (iii) by the
  15684. Category of Subjective Harmony, in virtue of which the subjective forms of
  15685. the two conceptual feelings are adjusted to procure the subjective aim,
  15686. and (iv) bv the Category of Subjective Intensity, in virtue of which the
  15687. aim is determined to the attainment of balanced intensity from feelings
  15688. integrated in virtue of near-identity, and contrasted in virtue of reversions.
  15689.  
  15690. Thus in the successive occasions of an enduring object in which the
  15691. inheritance is governed by this complex physical purpose, the reverted
  15692. conceptual feeling is transmitted into the next occasion as physical feeling,
  15693. and the pattern of the original physical feeling now reappears as the datum
  15694. in the reverted conceptual feeling. Thus along the route of the life-history
  15695. there is a chain of contrasts in the physical feelings of the successive occa-
  15696. sions. This chain is inherited as a vivid contrast of physical feelings, and
  15697. in each occasion there is the physical feeling with its primary valuation in
  15698. contrast with the reverted conceptual feeling.
  15699.  
  15700. Thus an enduring object gains the enhanced intensity of feeling arising
  15701. from contrast between inheritance and novel effect, and also gains the en-
  15702. hanced intensity arising from the combined inheritance of its stable
  15703. rhythmic character throughout its life-history. It has the weight of repeti-
  15704. tion, the intensity of contrast, and the balance between the two factors of
  15705. the contrast. In this way the association of endurance with rhythm and
  15706. physical vibration ist to be explained. They arise out of the conditions
  15707. for intensity and stability. The subjective aim is seeking width with its
  15708. contrasts, within the unity of a general design. An intense experience is
  15709. an aesthetic fact, and [427] its categoreal conditions are to be generalized
  15710. from aesthetic laws in particular arts.
  15711.  
  15712. T .ie categoreal conditions, appealed to above, can be summarized thus : 1
  15713.  
  15714. 1. The novel consequent must be graded in relevance so as to pre-
  15715. serve some identity of character with the ground.
  15716.  
  15717. 2. The novel consequent must be graded in relevance so as to pre-
  15718. serve some contrast with the ground in respect to that same identity
  15719. of character,
  15720.  
  15721. 1 My Religion in the Making, Ch. Ill, Sect. VIl.t
  15722.  
  15723.  
  15724.  
  15725. 280 The Theory of Prehensions
  15726.  
  15727. These two principles are derived from the doctrine that an actual
  15728. fact is a fact of aesthetic experience. All aesthetic experience is feeling
  15729. arising out of the realization of contrast under identity.
  15730. In the expansion of this account which has been given here, a third
  15731. principle has been added, that new forms enter into positive realizations
  15732. first as conceptual experience, and are then transmuted into physical
  15733. experience. But conceptual experience does not in itself involve con-
  15734. sciousness; its essence is valuation.
  15735.  
  15736. Between physical purposes and the conscious purposes introduced by
  15737. the intellectual feelings there lie the propositional feelings which have
  15738. not acquired consciousness in their subjective forms by association with
  15739. intellectual feelings. Such propositional feelings mark a stage of existence
  15740. intermediate between the purely physical stage and the stage of conscious
  15741. intellectual operations. The propositions are lures for feelings, and give
  15742. to feelings a definiteness of enjoyment and purpose which is absent in
  15743. the blank evaluation of physical feeling into physical purpose. In this
  15744. blank evaluation we have merely the determination of the comparative
  15745. creative efficacies of the component feelings of actual entities. In a proposi-
  15746. tional feeling there is the 'hold up'— or, in its original sense, the epoch—
  15747. of the valuation of the predicative pattern in its relevance to the definite
  15748. logical subjects which are otherwise felt as definite elements in experience.
  15749. \428] There is the arrest of the emotional pattern round this sheer fact
  15750. as a possibility, with the corresponding gain in distinctness of its relevance
  15751. to the future. The particular possibility for the transcendent creativity—
  15752. in the sense of its advance from subject to subject— this particular possi-
  15753. bility has been picked out, held up, and clothed with emotion. The stage
  15754. of existence in which propositional feelings are important apart from in-
  15755. tellectual feelings, may be identified with Bergson's stage of pure and in-
  15756. stinctive intuition. There are thus three stages, the stage of pure physical
  15757. purpose, the stage of pure instinctive intuition, and the stage of intellectual
  15758. feelings. But these stages are not sharply distinguished. There are stages
  15759. in which there are propositional feelings with every degree of importance
  15760. or of unimportance; there are stages in which there are intellectual feelings
  15761. with every degree of importance or of unimportance. Also,f even in a higher
  15762. stage, there are whole recesses of feeling which in the final satisfaction
  15763. acquire merely the characteristics of their own proper stage, physical or
  15764. propositional.
  15765.  
  15766.  
  15767.  
  15768. PART IV
  15769. THE THEORY OF EXTENSION
  15770.  
  15771.  
  15772.  
  15773. CHAPTER I
  15774. COORDINATE! DIVISION
  15775.  
  15776. SECTION I
  15777.  
  15778. [433] There are two distinct ways of 'dividing' the satisfaction of an
  15779. actual entity into component feelings, genetically and coordinately. Genetic
  15780. division is division of the concrescence; coordinate division is division of
  15781. the concrete. In the 'genetic' mode, the prehensions are exhibited in their
  15782. genetic relationship to each other. The actual entity is seen as a process;
  15783. there is a growth from phase to phase; there are processes of integration
  15784. and of [434] reintegration. At length a complex unity of objective datum
  15785. is obtained, in the guise of a contrast of actual entities, eternal objects,
  15786. and propositions, felt with corresponding complex unity of subjective form.
  15787. This genetic passage from phase to phase is not in physical time: the
  15788. exactly converse point of view expresses the relationship of concrescence
  15789. to physical time. It can be put shortly by saying, that physical time ex-
  15790. presses some features of the growth, but not the growth of the features.
  15791. The final complete feeling is the "'satisfaction.'
  15792.  
  15793. Physical time makes its appearance in the 'coordinate' analysis of the
  15794. 'satisfaction/ The actual entity is the enjoyment of a certain quantum of
  15795. physical time. But the genetic process is not the temporal succession:
  15796. such a view is exactly what is denied by the epochal theory of time. Each
  15797. phase in the genetic process presupposes the entire quantum, and so does
  15798. each feeling in each phase. The subjective unity dominating the process
  15799. forbids the division of that extensive quantum which originates with the
  15800. primary phase of the subjective aim. The problem dominating the con-
  15801. crescence is the actualization of the quantum in solidoA The quantum is
  15802. that standpoint in the extensive continuum which is consonant with the
  15803. subjective aim in its original derivation from God. Here 'God' is that
  15804. actuality in the world, in virtue of which there is physical law/
  15805.  
  15806. There is a spatial element in the quantum as well as a temporal ele-
  15807. ment. Thus the quantum is an extensive region. This region is the deter-
  15808. minate basis which the concrescence presupposes. This basis governs the
  15809. objectifications of the actual world which are possible for the novel con-
  15810. crescence. The coordinate divisibility of the satisfaction is the 'satisfaction'
  15811. considered in its relationship to the divisibility of this region.
  15812.  
  15813. The concrescence presupposes its basic region, and not the region its
  15814. concrescence. Thus the subjective unity of the concrescence is irrelevant
  15815.  
  15816. 283
  15817.  
  15818.  
  15819.  
  15820. 284 The Theory of Extension
  15821.  
  15822. to the divisibility of the [435] region. In dividing the region we are ignoring
  15823. the subjective unity which is inconsistent with such division. But the re-
  15824. gion is, after all, divisible, although in the genetic growth it is undivided.
  15825.  
  15826. So this divisible character of the undivided region is reflected into the
  15827. character of the satisfaction. When we divide the satisfaction coordinately,
  15828. we do not find feelings which are separate, but feelings which might be
  15829. separate. In the same way, the divisions of the region are not divisions
  15830. which are; they are divisions which might be. Each such mode of division
  15831. of the extensive region yields 'extensive quanta': also an 'extensive quan-
  15832. tum' has been termed a 'standpoint/ This notion of a 'standpoint' must
  15833. now be briefly explained.
  15834.  
  15835. The notion has reference to three allied doctrines. First, there is the
  15836. doctrine of 'the actual world' as receiving its definition from the immediate
  15837. concrescent actuality in question. Each actual entity arises out of its own
  15838. peculiar actual world. Secondly, there is the doctrine of each actual world
  15839. as a 'medium/ According to this doctrine, if S be the concrescent subject
  15840. in question, and A and B be two actual entities in its actual world, then
  15841. either A is in the actual world of B, or B is in the actual world of A, or A
  15842. and B are contemporaries. If, for example, A be in the actual world of B,
  15843. then for the immediate subject S there are (1) the direct objectification
  15844. of A in S, and (2) the indirect objectification by reason of the chain of
  15845. objectification, A in B and B in S. Such chains can be extended to any
  15846. length by the inclusion of many intermediate actualities between A
  15847. and S.
  15848.  
  15849. Thirdly, it is to be noticed that 'decided' conditions are never such as
  15850. to banish freedom. They only qualify it. There is always a contingency
  15851. left open for immediate decision. This consideration is exemplified by an
  15852. indetermination respecting 'the actual world' which is to decide the con-
  15853. ditions for an immediately novel concrescence. There are alternatives as to
  15854. its determination, which are left over for immediate decision. Some actual
  15855. [436] entities may be either in the settled past, or in the contemporary
  15856. nexus, or even left to the undecided future, according to immediate de-
  15857. cision. Also the indirect chains of successive objectifications will be modi-
  15858. fied according to such choice. These alternatives are represented by the
  15859. indecision as to the particular quantum of extension to be chosen for the
  15860. basis of the novel concrescence.
  15861.  
  15862. SECTION II
  15863.  
  15864. The sense in which the coordinate divisions of the satisfaction are
  15865. 'feelings which might be separated has now to be discussed.
  15866.  
  15867. Each such coordinate division corresponds to a definite sub-region of
  15868. the basic region. It expresses that component of the satisfaction which
  15869. has the character of a unified feeling of the actual world from the stand-
  15870. point of that sub-region. In so far as the objectification of the actual world
  15871.  
  15872.  
  15873.  
  15874. Coordinate Division 285
  15875.  
  15876. from this restricted standpoint is concerned, there is nothing to distinguish
  15877. this coordinate division from an actual entity. But it is only the physical
  15878. pole of the actual entity which is thus divisible. The mental pole is in-
  15879. curably one. Thus the subjective form of this coordinate division is de-
  15880. rived from the origination of conceptual feelings which have regard to
  15881. the complete region, and are not restricted to the sub-region in question.
  15882. In other words, the conceptual feelings have regard to the complete actual
  15883. entity, and not to the coordinate division in question. Thus the whole
  15884. course of the genetic derivation of the coordinate division is not explicable
  15885. by reference to the categoreal conditions governing the concrescence of
  15886. feeling arising from the mere physical feeling of the restricted objective
  15887. datum. The originative energy of the mental pole constitutes the urge
  15888. whereby its conceptual prehensions adjust and readjust subjective forms
  15889. and thereby determine the specific modes of integration terminating in
  15890. the 'satisfaction/
  15891.  
  15892. It is obvious that in so far as the mental pole is trivial [437] as to orig-
  15893. inality, what is inexplicable in the coordinate division (taken as actually
  15894. separate) becomes thereby trivial. Thus for many abstractions concerning
  15895. low-grade actual entities, the coordinate divisions approach the character
  15896. of being actual entities on the same level as the actual entity from which
  15897. they are derived.
  15898.  
  15899. It is thus an empirical question to decide in relation to special topics,
  15900. whether the distinction between a coordinate division and a true actual
  15901. entity is, or is not, relevant. In so far as it is not relevant we are dealing
  15902. with an indefinitely subdivisible extensive universe.
  15903.  
  15904. A coordinate division is thus to be classed as a generic contrast. The two
  15905. components of the contrast are, (i) the parent actual entity, and (ii) the
  15906. proposition which is the potentiality of that superject having arisen from
  15907. the physical standpoint of the restricted sub-region. The proposition is
  15908. thus the potentiality of eliminating from the physical pole of the parent
  15909. entity all the objectified actual world, except those elements derivable from
  15910. that standpoint; and yet retaining the relevant elements of the subjective
  15911. form.
  15912.  
  15913. The unqualified proposition is false, because the mental pole, which
  15914. is in fact operative, would not be the mental pole under the hypothesis
  15915. of the proposition. But, for many purposes, the falsity of the proposition
  15916. is irrelevant. The proposition is very complex; and with the relevant quali-
  15917. fications depending on the topic in question, it expresses the truth. In
  15918. other words, the unqualified false proposition is a matrix from which an
  15919. indefinite number of true qualified propositions can be derived. The req-
  15920. uisite qualification depends on the special topic in question, and ex-
  15921. presses the limits of the application of the unqualified proposition rele-
  15922. vantly to that topic.
  15923.  
  15924. The unqualified proposition expresses the indefinite divisibility of the
  15925. actual world; the qualifications express the features of the world which
  15926.  
  15927.  
  15928.  
  15929. 286 The Theory of Extension
  15930.  
  15931. are lost sight of by the [438] unguarded use of this principle. The actual
  15932. world is atomic: but in some senses it is indefinitely divisible.
  15933.  
  15934.  
  15935.  
  15936. SECTION III
  15937.  
  15938. The atomic actual entities individually express the genetic unity of the
  15939. universe. The world expands through recurrent unifications of itself, each,
  15940. by the addition of itself, automatically recreating the multiplicity anew.
  15941.  
  15942. The other type of indefinite multiplicity, introduced by the indefinite
  15943. coordinate divisibility of each atomic actuality, seems to show that, at
  15944. least for certain purposes, the actual world is to be conceived as a mere
  15945. indefinite multiplicity.
  15946.  
  15947. But this conclusion is to be limited by the principle of 'extensive order'
  15948. which steps in. The atomic unity of the world, expressed by a multiplicity
  15949. of atoms, is now replaced by the solidarity of the extensive continuum.
  15950. This solidarity embraces not only the coordinate divisions within each
  15951. atomic actuality, but also exhibits the coordinate divisions of all atomic
  15952. actualities from each other in one scheme of relationship.
  15953.  
  15954. In an earlier chapter (Part II, Ch. IV, Sects. IV to IXt) the sense in
  15955. which the world can be conceived as a medium for the transmission of in-
  15956. fluences! has been discussed. This orderly arrangement of a variety of
  15957. routes of transmission, by which alternative objectifications of an ante-
  15958. cedent actuality A can be indirectly received into the constitution of a sub-
  15959. sequent actuality B, is the foundation of the extensive relationship among
  15960. diverse actual entities. But this scheme of external extensive relationships
  15961. links itself with the schemes of internal division which are internal to the
  15962. several actual entities. There is, in this way, one basic scheme of extensive
  15963. connection which expresses on one uniform plant (i) the general condi-
  15964. tions to which the bonds, uniting the atomic actualities into a nexus, con-
  15965. form, and (ii) the general conditions to which the bonds, uniting the
  15966. infinite num- [439] ber of coordinate subdivisions of the satisfaction of any
  15967. actual entity, conform.
  15968.  
  15969. As an example of (ii), suppose that P is a coordinate division of an
  15970. actual occasion A. Then P can be conceived as an actual occasion with its
  15971. own actual world forming its initial datum in its first phase of genetic
  15972. origination. In fact, P is the hypothetical satisfaction of a hypothetical
  15973. process of concrescence with this standpoint. The other coordinate divi-
  15974. sions of A are either in the 'actual world' for P, or are contemporary with
  15975. P, or are coordinate divisions of P, or have a complex relation to P ex-
  15976. pressed by the property that each one of them is coordinately divisible
  15977. into prehensions Q^ Q 2 . . ., such that each of them has one or othert
  15978. of the three above-mentioned relations to P.
  15979.  
  15980. Further, in addition to the merely potential subdivisions of a satisfaction
  15981. into coordinate feelings, there is the merely potential aggregation of actual
  15982. entities into a super-actuality in respect to which the true actualities play
  15983.  
  15984.  
  15985.  
  15986. Coordinate Division 287
  15987.  
  15988. the part of coordinate subdivisions. In other words, just as,f for some pur-
  15989. poses, one atomic actuality can be treated as though it were many co-
  15990. ordinate actualities, in the same way, for other purposes, t a nexus of many
  15991. actualities can be treated as though it were one actuality. This is what we
  15992. habitually do in the case of the span of life of a molecule, or of a piece of
  15993. rock, or of a human body.
  15994.  
  15995. This extensiveness is the pervading generic form to which the morpho-
  15996. logical structures t of the organisms of the world conform. These organisms
  15997. are of two types: one type consists of the individual actual entities; the
  15998. other type consists of nexus of actual entities. Both types are correlated
  15999. by their common extensiveness. If we confine our attention to the sub-
  16000. division of an actual entity into coordinate parts, we shall conceive of
  16001. extensiveness as purely derived from the notion of 'whole and part/ that
  16002. is to say, 'extensive whole and extensive part/ This was the view taken
  16003. by me in myt two earlier investigations of the [440] subject. 1 This defect
  16004. of starting-point revenged itself in the fact that the 'method of extensive
  16005. abstraction' developed in those works was unable to define a 'point't with-
  16006. out the intervention of the theory of 'duration/ Thus what should have
  16007. been a property of 'durations' became the definition of a point. By this
  16008. mode of approach the extensive relations of actual entities mutually ex-
  16009. ternal to each other were pushed into the background; though they are
  16010. equally fundamental.
  16011.  
  16012. Since that date Professor T. de Laguna 2 has shown that the somewhat
  16013. more general notion of 'extensive connection' can be adopted as the start-
  16014. ing-point for the investigation of extension; and that the more limited
  16015. notion of 'whole and part 7 can be defined in terms of it. In this way, as
  16016. Professor de Laguna has shown, my difficulty in the definition of a point,
  16017. without recourse to other considerations, can be overcome.
  16018.  
  16019. This whole question is investigated in the succeeding chapters of this
  16020. Part.t Also I there give a definition of a straight line, and of 'flat' loci gen-
  16021. erally, in terms of purely extensive principles without reference to measure-
  16022. ment or to durations.
  16023.  
  16024. SECTION IV
  16025.  
  16026. An actual entity, in its character of being a physical occasion, is an act
  16027. of blind perceptivity of the other physical occasions of the actual world.
  16028. When we consider such an occasion morphologically, as a given entity,
  16029. its perceptive bonds are divisible by reason of the extensive divisibility of
  16030. its own standpoints, and by reason of the extensive divisibility of the other
  16031. actual occasions. Thus we reach perceptive bonds involving one sub-region
  16032. of the basic region of the perceiver, and one subdivision of the basic region
  16033.  
  16034. 1 Cf. The Principles of Natural Knowledge, 1919, and The Concept of Nature,
  16035. 1920, Cambridge University Press, England.
  16036.  
  16037. 2 Cf. Professor de Laguna'sf three articles in the Journal of Philosophy, Psy-
  16038. chology, and Scientific Method, Vol. XIX, 1922, especially the third article.
  16039.  
  16040.  
  16041.  
  16042. 288 The Theory of Extension
  16043.  
  16044. of the perceived. The relationship between these sub-regions involves the
  16045. status of inter- [441] mediate regions functioning as agents in the process
  16046. of transmission. In other words, the perspective of one sub-region from
  16047. the other is dependent on the fact that the extensive relations express
  16048. the conditions laid on the actual world in its function of a medium.
  16049.  
  16050. These extensive relations do not make determinate what is transmitted;
  16051. but they do determine conditions to which all transmission must conform.
  16052. They represent the systematic scheme which is involved in the real poten-
  16053. tiality from which every actual occasion arises. This scheme is also involved
  16054. in the attained fact which every actual occasion is. The 'extensive' scheme
  16055. is nothing else than the generic morphology of the internal relations which
  16056. bind the actual occasions into a nexus, and which bind the prehensions of
  16057. any one actual occasion into a unity, coordinately divisible.
  16058.  
  16059. For Descartes the primary attribute of physical bodies is extension; for
  16060. the philosophy of organism the primary relationship of physical occasions
  16061. is extensive connection. This ultimate relationship is sui generis 7 and can-
  16062. not be defined or explained. But its formal properties can be stated. Also,t
  16063. in view of these formal properties, there are definable derivative notions
  16064. which are of importance in expressing the morphological structure. Some
  16065. general character of coordinate divisibility is probably an ultimate meta-
  16066. physical character, persistent in every cosmic epoch of physical occasions.
  16067. Thus some of the simpler characteristics of extensive connection, as here
  16068. stated, are probably such ultimate metaphysical necessities.
  16069.  
  16070. But when we examine the characteristics considered in the next chapter,
  16071. it is difficult to draw the line distinguishing characteristics so general that
  16072. we cannot conceive any alternatives, from characteristics so special that we
  16073. imagine them to belong merely to our cosmic epoch. Such an epoch may
  16074. be, relatively to our powers, of immeasurable extent, temporally and spa-
  16075. tially. But in reference to the ultimate nature of things, it is a limited
  16076. nexus. Beyond that nexus, entities with new relationships, unrealized in
  16077. our experiences and unforeseen by our imagi- [442} nations, will make their
  16078. appearance, introducing into the universe new types of order.
  16079.  
  16080. But, for our epoch, extensive connection with its various characteristics
  16081. is the fundamental organic relationship whereby the physical world is
  16082. properly described as a community. There are no important physical rela-
  16083. tionships outside the extensive scheme. To be an actual occasion in the
  16084. physical world means that the entity in question is a relatum in this
  16085. scheme of extensive connection. In this epoch, the scheme defines what
  16086. is physically actual.
  16087.  
  16088. The more ultimate side of this scheme, perhaps that side which is meta-
  16089. physically necessary, is at once evident by the consideration of the mutual
  16090. implication of extensive whole and extensive part. If you abolish the
  16091. whole, you abolish its parts; and if you abolish any part, then that whole
  16092. is abolished.
  16093.  
  16094. In this general description of the states of extension, nothing has been
  16095.  
  16096.  
  16097.  
  16098. Coordinate Division 289
  16099.  
  16100. said about physical time or physical space, or of the more general notion
  16101. of creative advance. These are notions which presuppose the more gen-
  16102. eral relationship of extension. They express additional facts about the
  16103. actual occasions. The extensiveness of space is really the spatialization of
  16104. extension; and the extensiveness of time is really the temporalization of
  16105. extension. Physical time expresses the reflection of genetic divisibility into
  16106. coordinate divisibility.
  16107.  
  16108. So far as mere extensiveness is concerned, space might as well have
  16109. three hundred and thirty-three dimensions, instead of the modest three
  16110. dimensions of our present epoch. The three dimensions of space form
  16111. an additional fact about the physical occasions. Indeed the sheer dimen-
  16112. sionality of space, apart from the precise number of dimensions, is such
  16113. an additional fact, not involved in the mere notion of extension. Also the
  16114. seriality of time, unique or multiple, cannot be derived from the sole no-
  16115. tion of extension.
  16116.  
  16117. [443] The notion of nature as an organic extensive community omits
  16118. the equally essential point of view that nature is never complete. It is
  16119. always passing beyond itself. This is the creative advance of nature. Here
  16120. we come to the problem of time. The immediately relevant point to notice
  16121. is that time and space are characteristics of nature which presuppose the
  16122. scheme of extension. But extension does not in itself determine the special
  16123. facts which are true respecting physical time and physical space.
  16124.  
  16125. SECTION V
  16126.  
  16127. The consideration of coordination and genesis raises a question wider
  16128. than any yet discussed in this chapter.
  16129.  
  16130. The theory of 'prehensions' embodies a protest against the 'bifurcation'
  16131. of nature. It embodies even more than that: its protest is against the
  16132. bifurcation of actualities. In the analysis of actuality the antithesis be-
  16133. tween publicity and privacy obtrudes itself at every stage. There are ele-
  16134. ments only to be understood by reference to what is beyond the fact in
  16135. question; and there are elements expressive of the immediate, private, per-
  16136. sonal, individuality of the fact in question. The former elements express
  16137. the publicity of the world; the latter elements express the privacy of the
  16138. individual.
  16139.  
  16140. An actual entity considered in reference to the publicity of things is a
  16141. superjecf ; namely, it arises from the publicity which it finds, and it adds
  16142. itself to the publicity which it transmits. It is a moment of passage from
  16143. decided public facts to a novel public fact. Public facts are, in their nature,
  16144. coordinate.
  16145.  
  16146. An actual entity considered in reference to the privacy of things is a
  16147. 'subject'; namely, it is a moment of the genesis of self-enjoyment. It con-
  16148. sists of a purposed self-creation out of materials which are at hand in vir-
  16149. tue of their publicity.
  16150.  
  16151.  
  16152.  
  16153. 290 The Theory of Extension
  16154.  
  16155. Eternal objects have the same dual reference. An eternal object con-
  16156. sidered in reference to the publicity [444] of things is at 'universal';
  16157. namely, in its own nature it refers to the general public facts of the world
  16158. without any disclosure of the empirical details of its own implication in
  16159. them. Its own nature as an entity requires ingression— positive or negative
  16160. —in every detailed actuality; but its nature does not disclose the private
  16161. details of any actuality.
  16162.  
  16163. An eternal object considered in reference to the privacy of things is a
  16164. 'quality' or 'characteristic'; namely, in its own nature, as exemplified in any
  16165. actuality, it constitutes an element in the private definiteness of that ac-
  16166. tuality. It refers itself publicly; but it is enjoyed privately.
  16167.  
  16168. The theory of prehensions is founded upon the doctrine that there are
  16169. no concrete facts which are merely public, or merely private. The dis-
  16170. tinction between publicity and privacy is a distinction of reason, and is
  16171. not a distinction between mutually exclusive concrete facts. The sole
  16172. concrete facts, in terms of which actualities can be analysed, are prehen-
  16173. sions; and every prehension has its public side and its private side. Its
  16174. public side is constituted by the complex datum prehended; and its private
  16175. side is constituted by the subjective form through which a private quality
  16176. is imposed on the public datum. The separations of perceptual fact from
  16177. emotional fact; and of causal fact from emotional fact, and from per-
  16178. ceptual fact;t and of perceptual fact, emotional fact, and causal fact, from
  16179. purposive fact; have constituted a complex of bifurcations, fatal to a satis-
  16180. factory cosmology. The facts of nature are the actualities; and the facts
  16181. into which the actualities are divisible are their prehensions, with their
  16182. public origins, their private forms, and their private aims. But the actuali-
  16183. ties are moments of passage into a novel stage of publicity; and the co-
  16184. ordination of prehensions expresses the publicity of the world, so far as
  16185. it can be considered in abstraction from private genesis. Prehensions have
  16186. public careers, but they are born privately. [445]
  16187.  
  16188.  
  16189.  
  16190. SECTION VI
  16191.  
  16192. The antithesis between publicity and privacy is reflected in the classi-
  16193. fication of eternal objects according to their primary modes of ingression
  16194. into actual entities. An eternal object can only function in the con-
  16195. crescence of an actual entity in one of three ways: (i) it can be an element
  16196. in the definiteness of some objectified nexus, or of some single actual entity,
  16197. which is the datum of a feeling; (ii) it can be an element in the definite-
  16198. ness of the subjective form of some feeling; or (iii) it can be an element
  16199. in the datum of a conceptual, or propositional, feeling. AH other modes
  16200. of ingression arise from integrations which presuppose these modes.
  16201.  
  16202. Now the third mode is merely the conceptual valuation of the potential
  16203. ingression in one of the other two modes. It is a real ingression into actu-
  16204.  
  16205.  
  16206.  
  16207. Coordinate Division 291
  16208.  
  16209. ality; but it is a restricted ingression with mere potentiality withholding
  16210. the immediate realization of its function of conferring definiteness.
  16211.  
  16212. The two former modes of ingression thus constitute the ways in which
  16213. the functioning of an eternal object is unrestrictedly realized. But we
  16214. now ask whether either mode is indifferently open to each eternal object.
  16215. The answer is the classification of eternal objects into two species, the
  16216. 'objective' species, and the 'subjective' species.
  16217.  
  16218. An eternal object of the objective species can only obtain ingression in
  16219. the first mode, and never in the second mode. It is always, in its un-
  16220. restricted realization, an element in the definiteness of an actual entity,
  16221. or a nexus, which is the datum of a feeling belonging to the subject in
  16222. question.
  16223.  
  16224. Thus a member of this species can only function relationally: by a
  16225. necessity of its nature it is introducing one actual entity, or nexus, into
  16226. the real internal constitution of another actual entity. Its sole avocation
  16227. is to be an agent in objectification. It can never be an element in [446] the
  16228. definiteness of a subjective form. The solidarity of the world rests upon
  16229. the incurable objectivity of this species of eternal objects. A member of
  16230. this species inevitably introduces into the immediate subject other actu-
  16231. alities. The definiteness with which it invests the external world may, or
  16232. may not, conform to the real internal constitutions of the actualities ob-
  16233. jectified. But conformably, or non-con formably, such is the character of
  16234. that nexus for that actual entity. This is a real physical fact, with its
  16235. physical consequences. Eternal objects of the objective species are the
  16236. mathematical Platonict forms. They concern the world as a medium.
  16237.  
  16238. But the description of sensa given above (Part II, Ch. IV,t Sect. Ill)
  16239. will include some members of the subjective species.
  16240.  
  16241. A member of the subjective species is, in its primary character, an ele-
  16242. ment in the definiteness of the subjective form of a feeling. It is a deter-
  16243. minate way in which a feeling can feel. It is an emotion, or an intensity, or
  16244. an adversion, or an aversion, or a pleasure, or a pain. It defines the sub-
  16245. jective form of feeling of one actual entity. Aj may be that component of
  16246. A's constitution through which A is objectified for B. Thus when B feels
  16247. A b it feels 'A with that feeling/ In this way, the eternal object which con-
  16248. tributes to the definiteness of A's feeling becomes an eternal object con-
  16249. tributing to the definiteness of A as an objective datum in B ? s prehension
  16250. of A. The eternal object can then function both subjectively and relatively.
  16251. It can be a private element in a subjective form, and also an agent in the
  16252. objectification. In this latter character it may come under the operation
  16253. of the Category of Transmutation and become a characteristic of a nexus
  16254. as objectified for a percipient.
  16255.  
  16256. In the first stage of B's physical feeling, the subjective form of B's feel-
  16257. ing is conformed to the subjective form of A's feeling. Thus this eternal
  16258. object in B's experience will have a two-way mode of functioning. It will
  16259. be among the determinants of A for B, and it will be among [447] the
  16260.  
  16261.  
  16262.  
  16263. 292 The Theory of Extension
  16264.  
  16265. determinants of B's way of sympathy with A. The intensity of physical
  16266. energy belongs to the subjective species of eternal objects, but the peculiar
  16267. form of the flux of energy belongs to the objective species.
  16268.  
  16269. For example, 'redness* may first be the definiteness of an emotion which
  16270. is a subjective form in the experience of A; it then becomes an agent
  16271. whereby A is objectified for B, so that A is objectified in respect to its
  16272. prehension with this emotion. But A may be only one occasion of a nexus,
  16273. such that each of its members is objectified for B by a prehension with an
  16274. analogous subjective form. Then by the operation of the Category of
  16275. Transmutation, the nexus is objectified for B as illustrated by the charac-
  16276. teristic 'redness/ The nexus will also be illustrated by its mathematical
  16277. forms which are eternal objects of the objective species.
  16278.  
  16279. SECTION VII
  16280.  
  16281. The feelings— or, more accurately, the quasi-feelings— introduced by
  16282. the coordinate division of actual entities eliminate the proper status of the
  16283. subjects entertaining the feelings. For the subjective forms of feelings are
  16284. only explicable by the categoreal demands arising from the unity of the
  16285. subject. Thus the coordinate division of an actual entity produces feelings
  16286. whose subjective forms are partially eliminated and partially inexplicable.
  16287. But this mode of division preserves undistorted the elements of deflnite-
  16288. ness introduced by eternal objects of the objective species.
  16289.  
  16290. Thus in so far as the relationships of these feelings require an appeal
  16291. to subjective forms for their explanation, the gap must be supplied by the
  16292. introduction of arbitrary laws of nature regulating the relations of inten-
  16293. sities. Alternatively, the subjective forms become arbitrary epiphenomenal
  16294. facts, inoperative in physical nature, though claiming operative importance.
  16295.  
  16296. The order of nature, prevalent in the cosmic epoch in question, exhibits
  16297. itself as a morphological scheme in- [448] volving eternal objects of the ob-
  16298. jective species. The most fundamental elements in this scheme are those
  16299. eternal objects in terms of which the general principles of coordinate divi-
  16300. sion itself are expressed. These eternal objects express the theory of exten-
  16301. sion in its most general aspect. In this theory the notion of the atomicity
  16302. of actual entities, each with its concrescent privacy, has been entirely
  16303. eliminated. We are left with the theory of extensive connection, of whole
  16304. and part, of points, lines, and surfaces, and of straightness and flatness.
  16305.  
  16306. The substance of this chapter can be recapitulated in a summary: Ge-
  16307. netic division is concerned with an actual occasion in its character of a
  16308. concrescent immediacy. Coordinate division is concerned with an actual
  16309. occasion in its character of a concrete object. Thus for genetic division
  16310. the primary fact about an occasion is its initial 'dative 7 phase; for coordi-
  16311. nate division the primary fact is the final 'satisfaction/ But with the at-
  16312. tainment of the 'satisfaction/ the immediacy of final causation is lost, and
  16313. the occasion passes into its objective immortality, in virtue of which efE-
  16314.  
  16315.  
  16316.  
  16317. Coordinate Division 293
  16318.  
  16319. cient causation is constituted. Thus in coordinate division we are analysing
  16320. the complexity of the occasion in its function of an efficient cause. It is
  16321. in this connection that the morphological scheme of extensiveness attains
  16322. its importance. In this way we obtain an analysis of the dative phase in
  16323. terms of the 'satisfactions* of the past world. These satisfactions are sys-
  16324. tematically disposed in their relative status, according as one is, or is not,
  16325. in the actual world of another. Also they are divisible into prehensions
  16326. which can be treated as quasi-actualities with the same morphological
  16327. system of relative status. This morphological system gains special order
  16328. from the defining characteristic of the present cosmic epoch. The ex-
  16329. tensive continuum is this specialized ordering of the concrete occasions
  16330. and of the prehensions into which they are divisible.
  16331.  
  16332.  
  16333.  
  16334. CHAPTER II
  16335. EXTENSIVE CONNECTION
  16336.  
  16337. SECTION I
  16338.  
  16339. [449] In this chapter we enumerate the chief characteristics of the
  16340. physical relationship termed 'extensive connection/ We also enumerate
  16341. the derivative notions which are of importance in our physical experience.
  16342. This importance has its origin in the characteristics enumerated. The defi-
  16343. nitions of the derivative notions, as mere definitions, are equally applicable
  16344. to any scheme of relationship whatever its characteristics. But they are
  16345. only of importance when the relationship in question has the character-
  16346. istics here enumerated for extensive connection.
  16347.  
  16348. No attempt will be made to reduce these enumerated characteristics to
  16349. a logical minimum from which the remainder can be deduced by strict
  16350. deduction. There is not a unique set of logical minima from which the
  16351. rest can be deduced. There are many such sets. The investigation of such
  16352. sets has great logical interest and has an importance which extends beyond
  16353. logic. But it is irrelevant for the purposes of this discussion.
  16354.  
  16355. For the sake of brevity the terms 'connection' and 'connected' will be
  16356. used in the place of 'extensive connection' and Extensively connected/
  16357. The term 'region' will be used for the relata which are involved in the
  16358. scheme of 'extensive connection/ Thus, in the shortened phraseology,
  16359. regions are the things which are connected.
  16360.  
  16361. A set of diagrams will illustrate the type of relationship meant by 'con-
  16362. nection/ The two areas, A and B, in each diagram exhibit an instance of
  16363. connection with each other,
  16364.  
  16365. [450] Such diagrams are apt to be misleading: t for one reason, because
  16366. they introduce features as obvious, which it is our business to define in
  16367. terms of our fundamental notion of 'connection'; for another reason, be-
  16368. cause they introduce features which are special to the two-dimensional,
  16369. spatial extensiveness of a sheet of paper.
  16370.  
  16371. In the three diagrams of Set II, the areas, A and B, are not connected;
  16372. but they are 'mediately' connected by the area C.
  16373.  
  16374. SECTION II
  16375.  
  16376. Definition Li Two regions are 'mediately' connected when they are
  16377. both connected with a third region.
  16378.  
  16379. 294
  16380.  
  16381.  
  16382.  
  16383. Extensive Connection
  16384.  
  16385.  
  16386.  
  16387. 295
  16388.  
  16389.  
  16390.  
  16391.  
  16392. DIAGRAMS I
  16393.  
  16394.  
  16395.  
  16396.  
  16397. (vi)
  16398.  
  16399.  
  16400.  
  16401.  
  16402. Assumption 1. Connection and mediate connection are both of them
  16403. symmetrical relations; that is to say, if region A is connected, or mediately
  16404. connected, with region B, then region B is connected, or mediately con-
  16405. nected, with region A.
  16406.  
  16407. [451] It is obvious that the part of this assumption which concerns medi-
  16408. ate connection can be proved from the terms of the definition. In the sub-
  16409. sequent development of definitions and assumptions we shall not draw at-
  16410. tention to such instances of the possibility of proof.
  16411.  
  16412. Assumption 2. No region is connected with all the other regions; and
  16413. any two regions are mediately connected.
  16414.  
  16415. Assumption 3. Connection is not transitive; that is to say, if A be con-
  16416. nected with B, and B with C, it does not thereby follow that A is con-
  16417. nected with C; though in certain cases it does happen that A is connected
  16418. with C.
  16419.  
  16420. Assumption 4, No region is connected, or mediately connected, with
  16421. itself.
  16422.  
  16423. [452] This assumption is merely a convenient arrangement of nomen-
  16424. clature.
  16425.  
  16426. Definition 2. Region A is said to 'include' region B when every region
  16427. connected with B is also connected with A. As an alternative nomen-
  16428. clature, region B will be said to be 'part' of region A.
  16429.  
  16430. This definition of 'inclusion' is due to Professor de Laguna; it constitutes
  16431. an important addition to the theory of extension. In such investigations,
  16432. as the present one, the definitions are the really vital portion of the subject.
  16433.  
  16434.  
  16435.  
  16436. 296
  16437.  
  16438.  
  16439.  
  16440. The Theory of Extension
  16441.  
  16442.  
  16443.  
  16444. (i)
  16445.  
  16446.  
  16447.  
  16448. DIAGRAMS II t
  16449.  
  16450.  
  16451.  
  16452. (ii)
  16453.  
  16454.  
  16455.  
  16456.  
  16457. Assumption 5. When one region includes another, the two regions are
  16458. connected.
  16459.  
  16460. Assumption 6. The relation of inclusion is transitive.
  16461.  
  16462. Assumption 7. A region does not include itself.
  16463.  
  16464. Assumption 8. The relation of inclusion is asymmetrical: that is to say,
  16465. if A includes B, then B does not include A.
  16466.  
  16467. Assumption 9. Every region includes other regions; and a pair of regions
  16468. thus included in one region are not necessarily connected with each other.
  16469. Such pairs can always be found, included in any given region.
  16470.  
  16471. Definition 3, Two regions are said to 'overlap/ when there is a third re-
  16472. gion which they both include.
  16473.  
  16474. Assumption 10. The relation of overlapping is symmetrical.
  16475.  
  16476. Assumption J J. If one region includes another region, the two regions
  16477. overlap.
  16478.  
  16479. Assumption 12. Two regions which overlap are connected.
  16480.  
  16481. Definition 4. A 'dissection' of any given region A, is a set of regions,
  16482. which is such that (i) all its members are included in A, (ii) no two of
  16483. its members overlap, (iii) any region included in A, but not a member of
  16484. the set, either is included in one member of the set, or overlaps more than
  16485. one member of the set.
  16486.  
  16487. Assumption 13. t There are many dissections of any given region.
  16488.  
  16489.  
  16490.  
  16491. Extensive Connection 297
  16492.  
  16493. [453] Assumption 14A A dissection of a region is not a dissection of any
  16494. other region.
  16495.  
  16496. Definition 5. A region is called an 'intersect' of two overlapping regions,
  16497. A and B, when (i) either it is included in both A and B, or it is one of the
  16498. two regions and is included in the other, and (ii) no region, also included
  16499. in both A and B, can overlap it without being included in it.
  16500.  
  16501. Definition 6A If there be one, and only one, intersect of two regions, A
  16502. and B, those regions are said to overlap with 'unique intersection'; if there
  16503. be more than one intersect, they are said to overlap with 'multiple
  16504. intersection/
  16505.  
  16506. Assumption ISA Any region included in both of two overlapping re-
  16507. gions, and not itself an intersect, is included in one, and only one, inter-
  16508. sect.
  16509.  
  16510. Assumption 16 A If A includes B, then B is the sole intersect of A and B.
  16511.  
  16512. Assumption 17 A An intersect of two regions, which is not one of the
  16513. two regions, is included in both regions.
  16514.  
  16515. Assumption 18 A Each pair of overlapping regions has at least one
  16516. intersect.
  16517.  
  16518. Definition 7. Two regions are 'externally' connected when (i) they are
  16519. connected, and (ii) they do not overlap. The possibility of this definition
  16520. is another of the advantages gained from the adoption of Professor de
  16521. Laguna's starting-point, 'extensive connection/ over my original starting-
  16522. point, 1 'extensive whole and extensive part/ External connection is il-
  16523. lustrated by diagrams (v) and (vi) in Set I of the diagrams. So far, we
  16524. have not discriminated between the two cases illustrated respectively by
  16525. these two diagrams. The notion of external connection is a long step
  16526. towards the elaboration of the notion of a 'surface/ which has not yet been
  16527. touched upon.
  16528.  
  16529. Definition 8, A region B is 'tangentially' included in a region A, when
  16530. (i) B is included in A, and (ii) there are \454] regions which are externally
  16531. connected with both A and B.
  16532.  
  16533. Definition 9. A region B is 'non-tangentially' included in a region A
  16534. when (i) B is included in A, and (ii) there is no third region which is
  16535. externally connected with both A and B.
  16536.  
  16537. The possibility, at this stage, of the three definitions 7, 8, and 9, con-
  16538. stitutes the advantage to be gained by starting from Professor de Laguna's
  16539. notion of 'extensive connection/ Non-tangential inclusion is illustrated by
  16540. diagram (i) of the first set; and the two cases—as yet undiscriminated—
  16541. of tangential inclusion are illustrated by diagrams (ii) and (iii).
  16542.  
  16543. SECTION III
  16544.  
  16545. Definition 10. A set of regions is called an 'abstractive set/ when (i) any
  16546. two members of the set are such that one of them includes the other
  16547.  
  16548. 1 Cf . my Principles of Natural Knowledge, and Concept of Nature.
  16549.  
  16550.  
  16551.  
  16552. 298 The Theory of Extension
  16553.  
  16554. non-tangentially, andf (ii) there is no region included in every member of
  16555. the set.
  16556.  
  16557. This definition practically limits abstractive sets to those sets which were
  16558. termed 'simple abstractive sets' in iiiy Principles of Natural Knowledge
  16559. (paragraph 37.6). Since every region includes other regions, and since the
  16560. relation of inclusion is transitive, it is evident that every abstractive set
  16561. must be composed of an infinite number of members.
  16562.  
  16563. By reference to the particular case of three-dimensioned space, we see
  16564. that abstractive sets can have different types of convergence. For in this
  16565. case, an abstractive set can converge either to a point, or to a line, or to an
  16566. area. But it is to be noted that we have not defined either points, or lines,
  16567. or areas; and that we propose to define them in terms of abstractive sets.
  16568. Thus we must define the various types of abstractive sets without reference
  16569. to the notions, point, line, area.
  16570.  
  16571. Definition 11. An abstractive set a is said to 'cover' an [455] abstractive
  16572. set p, when every member of the set a includes some members of the
  16573. set p.
  16574.  
  16575. It is to be noticed that each abstractive set is to be conceived with its
  16576. members in serial order, determined by the relation of inclusion. The
  16577. series starts with a region of any size, and converges indefinitely towards
  16578. smaller and smaller regions, without any limiting region. When the set a
  16579. covers the set p 7 each member of a includes all the members of the con-
  16580. vergent tail of p,\ provided that we start far enough down in the serial
  16581. arrangement of the set p. It will be found that, though an abstractive set
  16582. must start with some region at its big end, these initial large-sized regions
  16583. never enter into our reasoning. Attention is always fixed on what relations
  16584. occur when we have proceeded far enough down the series. The only re-
  16585. lations which are interesting are those which, if they commence anywhere,
  16586. continue throughout the remainder of the infinite series.
  16587.  
  16588. Definition 12. Two abstractive sets are said to be 'equivalent' when each
  16589. set covers the other.
  16590.  
  16591. Thus if a and p be the two equivalent abstractive sets, and A 1 be any
  16592. member of a, there is some member of p, B ± say, which is included in Aijf
  16593. also there is some member of a, A 2 say, which is included in B^ also
  16594. there is some member of p, B 2 say, which is included in A 2 ;t and so
  16595. on indefinitely. Two equivalent abstractive sets are equivalent in respect to
  16596. their convergence. But, in so far as the two sets are diverse, there will be
  16597. relationships and characteristics in respect to which those sets are not
  16598. equivalent, in a more general sense of the term 'equivalence/ The connec-
  16599. tion of this special sense of 'equivalence' to physical properties is explained
  16600. more particularly in Chapter IV of the Concept of Nature.
  16601.  
  16602. Assumption 19 A An abstractive set is equivalent to itself. This assump-
  16603. tion is merely a convenient arrangement of nomenclature. An abstractive
  16604. set obviously satisfies the conditions for such reflexive equivalence.
  16605.  
  16606. Definition 13. A geometrical element is a complete [456] group of ab-
  16607.  
  16608.  
  16609.  
  16610. Extensive Connection 299
  16611.  
  16612. stractive sets equivalent to each other, and not equivalent to any abstrac-
  16613. tive set outside the group.
  16614.  
  16615. Assumption 20 A The relation of equivalence is transitive and sym-
  16616. metrical.
  16617.  
  16618. Thus any two members of a geometrical element are equivalent to each
  16619. other; and an abstractive set, not belonging to the geometrical element, is
  16620. not equivalent to any member of that geometrical element. It is evident
  16621. that each abstractive set belongs to one, and only one, geometrical element.
  16622.  
  16623. Definition 14. The geometrical element to which an abstractive set
  16624. belongs! is called the geometrical element 'associated' with that abstrac-
  16625. tive set. Thus a geometrical element is 'associated* with each of its
  16626. members.
  16627.  
  16628. Assumption 21 A Any abstractive set which covers any member of a geo-
  16629. metrical elementf also covers every member of that element.
  16630.  
  16631. Assumption 22 A An abstractive set which is covered by any member of
  16632. a geometrical elementf is also covered by every member of that element.
  16633.  
  16634. Assumption 23 A If a and b be two geometrical elements, either every
  16635. member of a covers every member of b, or no member of a covers any
  16636. member of b.
  16637.  
  16638. Definition IS. The geometrical element a is said to be 'incident* in the
  16639. geometrical element 6, when every member of b covers every member of a,
  16640. but a and b are not identical.
  16641.  
  16642. Assumption 24 A A geometrical element is not incident in itself.
  16643.  
  16644. This assumption is merely a convenient arrangement of nomenclature.
  16645.  
  16646. When the geometrical element a is incident in the geometrical element
  16647. 6, the members of a will be said to have a 'sharper convergence* than those
  16648. of 6.
  16649.  
  16650. Definition 16. A geometrical element is called a 'point/ when there is no
  16651. geometrical element incident in it. This definition of a 'point* is to be
  16652. compared with Euclid's definition: 'A point is without parts.*
  16653.  
  16654. [457} Definition 16.1. The members of a geometrical element are said to
  16655. be 'prime* in reference to assigned conditions, when (i) every member of
  16656. that geometrical element satisfies! those conditions; (ii) if any abstractive
  16657. set satisfies those conditions, every member of its associated geometrical
  16658. element satisfies them; (iii) there is no geometrical element, with mem-
  16659. bers satisfying those conditions, which is also incident in the given geo-
  16660. metrical element.
  16661.  
  16662. The term 'prime* will also be applied to a geometrical element, when
  16663. its members are 'prime* in the sense defined above.
  16664.  
  16665. It is obvious that a point is, in a sense, an 'absolute* prime. This is, in
  16666. fact, the sense in which the definition! of a point, given here, conforms to
  16667. Euclid's definition.
  16668.  
  16669. Definition 17. An abstractive set which is a member of a point will be
  16670. called punctual.*
  16671.  
  16672. Definition 18. A geometrical element is called a 'segment between two
  16673.  
  16674.  
  16675.  
  16676. 300 The Theory of Extension
  16677.  
  16678. points P and QJ when its members are prime in reference to the condition
  16679. that the points P and O are incident in it.
  16680.  
  16681. Definition 19. When a geometrical element is a segment between two
  16682. points, those points are called the 'end-points' of the segment.
  16683.  
  16684. Definition 20. An abstractive set which is a member of a segment is
  16685. called 'segmental/
  16686.  
  16687. Assumption 25. f There are many diverse segments with the same end-
  16688. points; t but a segment has only one pair of end-points.
  16689.  
  16690. This assumption illustrates the fact that there can be many geometrical
  16691. elements which are prime in reference to some given conditions. There are,
  16692. however, conditions such that there is only one geometrical element prime
  16693. to any one of them. For example, the set of points incident in one geo-
  16694. metrical element uniquely defines that geometrical element. Also another
  16695. instance of uniqueness is to be found in the theory of 'flat' geometrical
  16696. elements, to be considered in the next chapter. A particular instance of
  16697. such 'flat' elements is afforded \458] by straight lines. The whole theory of
  16698. geometry depends upon the discovery of conditions which correspond to
  16699. one, and only one, prime geometrical element. The Greeks, with their
  16700. usual fortunate intuition, chanced upon such conditions in their notions of
  16701. straight lines and planes. There is every reason, however, to believe that,
  16702. in other epochs, widely different types of conditions with this property may
  16703. be important— perhaps even in this epoch. The discovery of them is ob-
  16704. viously of the first importance. It is possible that the modern Einsteinian
  16705. reconstruction of physics is best conceived as the discovery of the inter-
  16706. weaving in nature of different types of such conditions.
  16707.  
  16708. SECTION IV
  16709.  
  16710. Definition 21. A point is said to be 'situated' in a region, when the
  16711. region is a member of one of the punctual abstractive sets which compose
  16712. that point.
  16713.  
  16714. Assumption 26 A If a point be situated in a region, the regions, suf-
  16715. ficiently far down the convergent tails of the various abstractive sets com-
  16716. posing that point, are included in that region non-tangentially.
  16717.  
  16718. Definition 22, A point is said to be situated in the 'surface' of a region,
  16719. when all the regions in which it is situated overlap that region but are
  16720. not included in it.
  16721.  
  16722. Definition 23. A 'complete locus' is a set of points which compose either
  16723. (i) all the points situated in a region, or (ii) all the points situated in the
  16724. surface of a region, or (hi) all the points incident in a geometrical element
  16725.  
  16726. A 'locus' always means a 'locus of points. 7
  16727.  
  16728. Assumption 27 X A 'complete locus,' as defined in Definition 23, consists
  16729. of an infinite number of points.
  16730.  
  16731. Definition 24. When a complete locus consists of all the points situated
  16732. in a region, it is called the 'volume' of that region; when a complete locus
  16733. consists of all the points in the surface of a region, the locus itself is called
  16734.  
  16735.  
  16736.  
  16737. Extensive Connection 301
  16738.  
  16739. the 'surface* of that region; when a complete locus consists of all the points
  16740. incident in a segment between end- [459] points, the locus is called a linear
  16741. stretch* between those end-points.
  16742.  
  16743. Assumption 28 A There is a one-to-one correlation between volumes and
  16744. regions, between surfaces and regions, and between linear stretches and
  16745. segments, and between any geometrical element and the locus of points
  16746. incident in it.
  16747.  
  16748. Assumption 29 A If two points lie in a given volume, there are linear
  16749. stretches joining those two points, whose points all lie in that volume.
  16750.  
  16751. Assumption 30 A If two points lie in a given surface, there are linear
  16752. stretches joining those two points, whose points all lie in that surface.
  16753.  
  16754. Assumption 31 A If two points lie in a given linear stretch, there is one,
  16755. and only one, linear stretch with those points as end-points, whose points
  16756. lie wholly in the given linear stretch.
  16757.  
  16758. It should be noted that the terms 'volume' and 'surface* are not meant
  16759. to imply that volumes are three-dimensional, or that surfaces are two-di-
  16760. mensional. In the application of this theory of extension to the existing
  16761. physical world of our epoch, volumes are four-dimensional, and surfaces
  16762. are three-dimensional. But linear stretches are one-dimensional.
  16763.  
  16764. +A sufficient number of assumptions, some provable and some axio-
  16765. matic, have now been stated; so as to make clear the sort of development
  16766. of the theory required for this stage of the definitions. In particular, the
  16767. notion of the order of points in a linear stretch can now be elaborated
  16768. from the definition of the notion of 'between/ But such investigations will
  16769. lead us too far into the mathematical principles of geometry. +
  16770.  
  16771.  
  16772.  
  16773. [S46]i An explanatory paragraph is required at the end of this chapter to
  16774. make clear the principle that a certain determinate boundedness is re-
  16775. quired for the notion of a region— i.e., for the notion of an extensive
  16776. standpoint in the real potentiality for actualization. The inside of a re-
  16777. gion, its volume, has a complete boundedness denied to the extensive po-
  16778. tentiality external to it. The boundedness applies both to the spatial and
  16779. the temporal aspects of extension. Wherever there is ambiguity as to the
  16780. contrast of boundedness between inside and outside, there is no proper
  16781. region. In the next chapter all the ovals, members of one ovate class, pre-
  16782. serve this property of boundedness, in the same sense for each of the ovals.
  16783. Thus in the case of Elliptic Geometry (page 330) no oval can include
  16784. half a straight line. On page 304, Condition vii has been expressed care-
  16785. lessly, so as to apply only to the case of infinite spatiality, i.e., to Euclidean
  16786. and Hyperbolic Geometry.
  16787.  
  16788.  
  16789.  
  16790. CHAPTER III
  16791. FLAT LOCI
  16792.  
  16793. SECTION I
  16794.  
  16795. [460] Modern physical science, with its dependence on the exact no-
  16796. tions of mathematics, began with the foundation of Greek Geometry. The
  16797. first definition of Euclid's Elements runs,
  16798.  
  16799. "A point is that of which there is no part/'
  16800.  
  16801. The second definition runs,
  16802.  
  16803. "A line is breadthless length."
  16804.  
  16805. The fourth definition runs,
  16806.  
  16807. "A straight line is any line which lies evenly with the points on itself."
  16808.  
  16809. These translations are taken from Euclid In Greek, Book I, edited with
  16810. notes by Sir Thomas L. Heath, the greatest living authority on Euclid's
  16811. Elements. Heath ascribes the second definition "to the Platonic school, if
  16812. not to Plato himself/' f For the Greek phrase translated 'evenly' Heath
  16813. also suggests the alternatives 'on a footing of equality,' 'evenly placed/
  16814. 'without bias/
  16815.  
  16816. Euclid's first 'postulate* is (Heath's translation):
  16817.  
  16818. "Let the following be postulated: to draw a straight line from any point
  16819. to any point."
  16820.  
  16821. Heath points out that this postulate was meant to imply f existence and
  16822. uniqueness.
  16823.  
  16824. As these statements occur in Greek science, a muddle arises between
  16825. 'forms' and concrete physical things. Geometry starts with the purpose of
  16826. investigating cer- [461] tain forms of physical things. But in its initial defini-
  16827. tions of the 'point' and the 'line,' it seems immediately to postulate certain
  16828. ultimate physical things of a very peculiar character. Plato himself ap-
  16829. pears to have had some suspicion of this confusion when (Heath, loc.
  16830. cit.) he "objected to recognizing points as a separate class of things at
  16831. all."t He ought to have gone further, and have made the same objection to
  16832. all the geometrical entities, namely, points, lines, and surfaces. He wanted
  16833. 'forms,' and he obtained new physical entities.
  16834.  
  16835. According to the previous chapter, "extension' should be construed in
  16836. terms of 'extensive connection'; that is to say, extension is a form of
  16837. relationship between the actualities of a nexus. A point is a nexus of actual
  16838. entities with a certain 'form'; and so is a 'segment/ Thus geometry is the
  16839. investigation of the morphology of nexus.
  16840.  
  16841. 302
  16842.  
  16843.  
  16844.  
  16845. Flat Loci 303
  16846.  
  16847.  
  16848.  
  16849. SECTION II
  16850.  
  16851.  
  16852.  
  16853. The weak point of the Euclidean definition of a straight line is, that
  16854. nothing has been deduced from it. The notion expressed by the phrases
  16855. 'evenly/ or 'evenly placed/ requires definition. The definition should be
  16856. such that the uniqueness of the straight segment between two points can
  16857. be deduced from it. Neither of these demands has ever been satisfied, with
  16858. the result that in modern times the notion of 'straightness' has been based
  16859. on that of measurement. A straight line has, in modern times, been defined
  16860. as the shortest distance between two points. In the classic geometry, the
  16861. converse procedure was adopted, and measurement presupposed straight
  16862. lines. But, with the modern definition, the notion of the 'shortest distance'
  16863. in its turn requires explanation. 1 This notion is practically defined to mean
  16864. the line which is the route of certain physical occurrences.
  16865.  
  16866. In this section it will be shown that the gap in the old [462] classical
  16867. theory can be remedied. Straight lines will be defined in terms of the
  16868. extensive notions, developed in the preceding chapter; and the uniqueness
  16869. of the straight line joining two points will be proved to follow from the
  16870. terms of the definition.
  16871.  
  16872. A class of 'oval' regions must first be defined. Now the only weapon
  16873. which we have for this definition is the notion of regions which overlap
  16874. with a unique intersect (cf. Def. 6 of previous chapter). It is evidently a
  16875. property of a pair of ovals that they can only overlap with a unique inter-
  16876. sect. But it is equally evident that some regions which are not ovals also
  16877. overlap with a unique intersect. However the class of ovals has the prop-
  16878. erty that any region, not a member of it, intersects some ovals with mul-
  16879. tiple intersects. Also sub-sets of ovals can be found satisfying various
  16880. conditions.
  16881.  
  16882. Thus we proceed to define a class whose region shall have those relations
  16883. to each other, and to other regions, which we ascribe to the class of ovals.
  16884. In other words,! we cannot define a single oval, but we can define a class
  16885. of ovals. Such a class will be called 'ovate/ The definition of an ovate class
  16886. proceeds by enumerating all those peculiar properties possessed by in-
  16887. dividual members of the class, or by sub-sets of members of the class. It will
  16888. be found in the course of this enumeration that an extensive continuum
  16889. which possesses an ovate class is dimensional in respect to that class. Thus
  16890. existence of straight lines in an extensive continuum is bound up with the
  16891. dimensional character of the continuum; and both characteristics are rela-
  16892. tive to a particular ovate class of regions in the continuum. It seems prob-
  16893. able that an extensive continuum will possess only one ovate class. But I
  16894. have not succeeded in proving that property; nor is it necessary for the
  16895. argument.
  16896.  
  16897. A preliminary definition is convenient:
  16898.  
  16899. 1 Cf. Part IV, Ch. V, on 'Measurement.'
  16900.  
  16901.  
  16902.  
  16903. 304 The Theory of Extension
  16904.  
  16905. Definition 0.1. An 'ovate abstractive set' is an abstractive set whose
  16906. members all belong to the complete ovate class under consideration.
  16907.  
  16908. [463] The characteristics of an ovate class will be divided into two
  16909. groups: (a) the group of non-abstractive conditions, and (b) the group of
  16910. abstractive conditions.
  16911.  
  16912. Definition 1. A class of regions is called 'ovate/ when it satisfies the
  16913. conditions belonging to the two following groups, (a) and (b):
  16914.  
  16915. (a) The N on- Abstractive Group
  16916.  
  16917. (i) Any two overlapping regions of the ovate class have a unique inter-
  16918. sect which also belongs to that ovate class.
  16919.  
  16920. (ii) Any region, not a member of the ovate class, overlaps some members
  16921. of that class with 'multiple intersection' (cf. Def. 6 of previous chapter).
  16922.  
  16923. (iii) Any member of the ovate class overlaps some regions, not of that
  16924. class, with multiple intersection.
  16925.  
  16926. (iv) Any pair of members of the ovate class, which are externally con-
  16927. nected, have their surfaces touching either in a 'complete locus' of points
  16928. (cf. Ch. II, Def. 23 and Ass. 27t ), or in a single point.
  16929.  
  16930. (v) Any region, not belonging to the ovate class, is externally con-
  16931. nected with some member of that class so that their surfaces touch in a
  16932. set of points which does not form a 'complete locus/
  16933.  
  16934. (vi) Any member of the ovate class is externally connected with some
  16935. region not of that class so that their surfaces touch in a set of points which
  16936. does not form a 'complete locus/
  16937.  
  16938. (vii) Any finite number of regions are jointly included in some member
  16939. of the ovate class.*
  16940.  
  16941. (viii) If A and B be members of the ovate class, and A include B, then
  16942. there are members of the class which include B and are included in A.
  16943.  
  16944. (ix) There are dissections (cf. Def. 4 of the previous chapter) of every
  16945. member of the ovate class, which consist wholly of members of that class;
  16946. and there are dissections consisting wholly or partly of members not be-
  16947. longing to that class.
  16948.  
  16949. [464] (b) The Abstractive Group
  16950.  
  16951. (i) Among the members of any point, there are ovate abstractive sets.
  16952.  
  16953. (ii) If any set of two, or of three, or of four, points be considered, there
  16954. are abstractive sets 'prime in reference to the twofold condition, (a) of
  16955. covering the points in question, and (b) of being equivalent to an ovate
  16956. abstractive set.
  16957.  
  16958. (iii) Theret are sets of five points such that no abstractive set exists
  16959. prime in reference to the twofold condition, (a) of covering the points in
  16960. question, and (b) oi being equivalent to an ovate abstractive set.
  16961.  
  16962. By reason of the definitions of this latter group, the extensive continuum
  16963. in question is called 'four-dimensional/ Analogously, an extensive con-
  16964.  
  16965.  
  16966.  
  16967. Flat Loci 305
  16968.  
  16969. tinuum of any number of dimensions can be defined. The physical ex-
  16970. tensive continuum with which we are concerned in this cosmic epoch is
  16971. four-dimensional. Notice that the property of being 'dimensional* is rela-
  16972. tive to a particular ovate class in the extensive continuum. There may be
  16973. 'ovate' classes satisfying all the conditions with the exception of the 'di-
  16974. mensional* conditions. Also a continuum may have one number of dimen-
  16975. sions relating to one ovate class, and another number of dimensions relat-
  16976. ing! to another ovate class.
  16977.  
  16978. Possibly physical laws, of the type presupposing continuity, depend on
  16979. the interwoven properties of two, or more, distinct ovate classes.
  16980.  
  16981. SECTION III
  16982.  
  16983. Assumption 1. In the extensive continuum of the present epoch there is
  16984. at least one ovate class, with the characteristics of the two groups, (a) and
  16985. (b), of the previous section.
  16986.  
  16987. Definition 2. One such ovate class will be denoted by a: all definitions
  16988. will be made relatively to this selected ovate class.
  16989.  
  16990. [465] It is indifferent to the argument whether or no there be an al-
  16991. ternative ovate class. If there be, the derivative entities defined in reference
  16992. to this alternative class are entirely different to those defined in reference to
  16993. a. It is sufficient for us, that one such class interests us by the importance
  16994. of its physical relations.
  16995.  
  16996. Assumption 2. If two abstractive sets are prime in reference to the same
  16997. twofold condition, (a) of covering a given group of points, and (b) of be-
  16998. ing equivalent to some ovate abstractive set, then they are equivalent
  16999.  
  17000. By reason of the importance of this proposition a proof is given.
  17001.  
  17002. Proof. The two abstractive sets are either equivalent to the same ovate
  17003. abstractive set, or to different ovate abstractive sets. In the former al-
  17004. ternative, the required conclusion is obvious. In the latter alternative, let
  17005. /a and v be the two different ovate abstractive sets. Each of these sets,
  17006. /a and v, satisfies the twofold condition. We have to prove that they are
  17007. equivalent to each other. Let M and N be any regions belonging to ju. and
  17008. v respectively. Then since the convergent portions of the abstractive sets
  17009. belonging to the various points of the given group must ultimately consist
  17010. of regions all lying in M and all lying in N, it follows that M and N inter-
  17011. sect. But, being oval, M and N have only one intersect, and all the points
  17012. in question must be situated in it. Also this intersect is oval. Hence, by
  17013. selecting such intersects, a third abstractive set can be found which satisfies
  17014. the twofold condition and is covered both by //, and by v. But since
  17015. /* and v are prime in reference to this condition, they are both of them
  17016. equivalent to this third abstractive class. Hence they are equivalent to each
  17017. other. Q.E.D.
  17018.  
  17019. Corollary, It follows that all abstractive sets, prime with respect to the
  17020. same twofold condition of this type, belong to one geometrical element.
  17021.  
  17022.  
  17023.  
  17024. 306 The Theory of Extension
  17025.  
  17026. Definition 3. The single geometrical element defined, as in the enuncia-
  17027. tion of Assumption 2, by a set of two points is called a 'straight' segment
  17028. between those end- [466] points. If the set comprise more than two points,
  17029. the geometrical element is called 'flat/ 'Straight 7 segments are also in-
  17030. cluded under the designation 'flat geometrical elements/
  17031.  
  17032. If a set of points define a flat geometrical element, as in the enunciation
  17033. of Assumption 2, it may happen that the same geometrical element is
  17034. defined by some sub-set of those points. Hence we have the following
  17035. definition:
  17036.  
  17037. Definition 4. A set of points, defining a flat geometrical element, is said
  17038. to be in its lowest terms when it contains no sub-set defining the same
  17039. flat geometrical element.
  17040.  
  17041. Assumption 3. No two sets of a finite number of points, both in their
  17042. lowest terms, define the same flat geometrical element.
  17043.  
  17044. Definition 5. The locus of points incident in a 'straight segment' is called
  17045. the 'straight line' between the end-points of the segment.
  17046.  
  17047. Definition 6. The locus of points incident in a flat geometrical element
  17048. is called the 'content' of that element. It is also called a 'flat locus/
  17049.  
  17050. Assumption 4. If any sub-set of points lief in a flat locus, that sub-set also
  17051. defines a flat locus contained within the given locus.
  17052.  
  17053. Definition 6.1 A A complete straight line is a locus of points such that,
  17054. (i) the straight line joining any two members of the locus lies wholly
  17055. within the locus, (ii) every sub-set in the locus, which is in its lowest terms,
  17056. consists of a pair of points, (iii) no points can be added to the locus with-
  17057. out loss of one, or both, of the characteristics (i) and (ii).
  17058.  
  17059. Definition 7. A triangle is the flat locus defined by three points which
  17060. are not collinear. The three points are the angular points of the triangle.
  17061.  
  17062. Definition 8. A plane is a locus of non-collinear points such that, (i) the
  17063. triangle defined by any three non-collinear members of the locus lies
  17064. wholly within the locus, [467] (ii) any finite number of points in the
  17065. locus lie in some triangle wholly contained in the locus, (iii) no set of
  17066. points can be added to the locus without loss of one, or both, of the
  17067. characteristics (i) and (ii).
  17068.  
  17069. Definition 9. A tetrahedron is the flat locus defined by four points which
  17070. are not coplanar. The four points are called the corners of the tetrahedron.
  17071.  
  17072. Definition 10. A three-dimensional flat space is a locus of non-coplanar
  17073. points such that, (i) the tetrahedron defined by any four non-coplanar
  17074. points of the locus lies wholly within the locus, (ii) any finite number of
  17075. points in the locus lief in some tetrahedron wholly contained in the
  17076. locus, (iii) no set of points can be added to the locus without the loss of
  17077. one, or both, of the characteristics (i) and (ii).
  17078.  
  17079. Any further development of definitions and propositions will lead to
  17080. mathematical details irrelevant to our immediate purposes. It suffices to
  17081. have proved that characteristic properties of straight lines, planes, and
  17082. three-dimensional flat spaces are discoverable in the extensive continuum
  17083.  
  17084.  
  17085.  
  17086. Flat Loci 307
  17087.  
  17088. without any recourse to measurement. The systematic character of a con-
  17089. tinuum depends on its possession of one or more ovate classes. Here, the
  17090. particular case of a 'dimensional' ovate class has been considered.
  17091.  
  17092. SECTION IV
  17093.  
  17094. The importance of the notion of 'external connection* requires further
  17095. discussion.
  17096.  
  17097. First, there is a purely geometrical question to be noted. The theory of
  17098. the external connection of oval regions throws light on the Euclidean
  17099. concept of 'evenness/ A pair of ovals (cf. Sect. Ill) can only be externally
  17100. connected in a 'complete locus/ or in a single point. We now consider that
  17101. species of 'complete loci' which can be the points common to the surfaces
  17102. of a pair of ovals externally connected. We exclude the case of one-point
  17103. contact. The species seems to have what the [468] Greeks meant by their
  17104. term 'even* (taoq). On either side of such a locus, there is the interior of
  17105. one oval and the exterior of another oval, so that the locus is 'even' in
  17106. respect to the contrasted notions of 'concavity' and 'convexity/ It is an
  17107. extra 'assumption'— provable or otherwise according to the particular log-
  17108. ical development of the subject which may have been adopted— that all
  17109. 'even' loci are 'flat/ and that all 'flat' loci are 'even/
  17110.  
  17111. The second question for discussion concerns the physical importance of
  17112. 'external connection/ So long as the atomic character of actual entities is
  17113. unrecognized, the application of Zeno's method of argument makes it
  17114. difficult to understand the notion of continuous transmission which reigns
  17115. in physical science. But the concept of 'actual occasions/ adopted in the
  17116. philosophy of organism, allows of the following explanation of physical
  17117. transmission.
  17118.  
  17119. Let two actual occasions be termed 'contiguous' when the regions con-
  17120. stituting their 'standpoints' are externally connected. Then by reason of
  17121. the absence of intermediate actual occasions, the objectification of the
  17122. antecedent occasion in the later occasion is peculiarly complete. There will
  17123. be a set of antecedent, contiguous occasions objectified in any given occa-
  17124. sion; and the abstraction which attends every objectification will merely be
  17125. due to the necessary harmonizations of these objectifications. The ob-
  17126. jectifications of the more distant past will be termed 'mediate'; the con-
  17127. tiguous occasions will have 'immediate' objectification. The mediate ob-
  17128. jectifications will be transmitted through various routes of successive im-
  17129. mediate objectifications. Thus the notion of continuous transmission in
  17130. science must be replaced by the notion of immediate transmission through
  17131. a route of successive quanta of extensiveness. These quanta of extensive-
  17132. ness are the basic regions of successive contiguous occasions. It is not neces-
  17133. sary for the philosophy of organism entirely to deny that there [469] is
  17134. direct objectification of one occasion in a later occasion which is not
  17135. contiguous to it. Indeed, the contrary opinion would seem the more nat-
  17136.  
  17137.  
  17138.  
  17139. 308 The Theory of Extension
  17140.  
  17141. ural for this doctrine. Provided that physical science maintains its denial
  17142. of 'action at a distance/ the safer guess is that direct objectification is
  17143. practically negligible except for contiguous occasions; but that this prac-
  17144. tical negligibility is a characteristic of the present cosmic epoch, without
  17145. any metaphysical generality. Also a further distinction should be intro-
  17146. duced. Physical prehensions fall into two species, pure physical prehen-
  17147. sions and hybrid physical prehensions. A pure physical prehension is a
  17148. prehension whose datum is an antecedent occasion objectified in respect to
  17149. one of its own physical prehensions. A hybrid prehension has as its datum
  17150. an antecedent occasion objectified in respect to a conceptual prehension.
  17151. Thus a pure physical prehension is the transmission of physical feeling,
  17152. while hybrid prehension is the transmission of mental feeling.
  17153.  
  17154. There is no reason to assimilate the conditions for hybrid prehensions to
  17155. those for pure physical prehensions. Indeed the contrary hypothesis is the
  17156. more natural. For the conceptual pole does not share in the coordinate
  17157. divisibility of the physical pole, and the extensive continuum is derived
  17158. from this coordinate divisibility. Thus the doctrine of immediate objecti-
  17159. fication for the mental poles and of mediate objectification for the physi-
  17160. cal poles seems most consonant to the philosophy of organism in its ap-
  17161. plication to the present cosmic epoch. This conclusion has some empirical
  17162. support, both from the evidence for peculiar instances of telepathy, and
  17163. from the instinctive apprehension of a tone of feeling in ordinary social
  17164. intercourse.
  17165.  
  17166. But of course such immediate objectification is also reinforced, or weak-
  17167. ened, by routes of mediate objectification. Also pure and hybrid prehen-
  17168. sions are integrated and thus hopelessly intermixed. Hence it will only be
  17169. in exceptional circumstances that an immediate hybrid {470} prehension
  17170. has sufficient vivid definition to receive a subjective form of clear con-
  17171. scious attention.
  17172.  
  17173. SECTION V
  17174.  
  17175. We have now traced the main characteristics of that real potentiality
  17176. from which the first phase of a physical occasion takes its rise. These
  17177. characteristics remain inwoven in the constitution of the subject through-
  17178. out its adventure of self-formation. The actual entity is the product of the
  17179. interplay of physical pole with mental pole. In this way, potentiality passes
  17180. into actuality, and extensive relations mould qualitative content and ob-
  17181. jectifications of other particulars into a coherent finite experience.
  17182.  
  17183. In general, consciousness is negligible; and even the approach to it in
  17184. vivid propositional feelings has failed to attain importance. Blind physical
  17185. purposes reign. It is now obvious that blind prehensions, physical and
  17186. mental, are the ultimate bricks of the physical universe. They are bound
  17187. together within each actuality by the subjective unity of aim which governs
  17188. their allied genesis and their final concrescence. They are also bound to-
  17189.  
  17190.  
  17191.  
  17192. Flat Loci 309
  17193.  
  17194. gether beyond the limits of their peculiar subjects by the way in which the
  17195. prehension in one subject becomes f the objective datum for the prehen-
  17196. sion in a later subject, thus objectifying the earlier subject for the later
  17197. subject. The two types of interconnection of prehensions are themselves
  17198. bound together in one common scheme, the relationship of extension.
  17199.  
  17200. It is by means of 'extension' that the bonds between prehensions take
  17201. on the dual aspect of internal relations, which are yet in a sense external
  17202. relations. It is evident that if the solidarity of the physical world is to be
  17203. relevant to the description of its individual actualities, it can only be by
  17204. reason of the fundamental internality of the relationships in question. On
  17205. the other hand, if the individual discreteness of the actualities is to have
  17206. its weight, there must be an aspect in these relationships [471] from which
  17207. they can be conceived as external, that is, as bonds between divided things.
  17208. The extensive scheme serves this double purpose.
  17209.  
  17210. The Cartesian subjectivism in its application to physical science became
  17211. Newton's assumption of individually existent physical bodies, with merely
  17212. external relationships. We diverge from Descartes by holding that what he
  17213. has described as primary attributes of physical bodies t are really the forms
  17214. of internal relationships between actual occasions, and within actual occa-
  17215. sions. Such a change of thought is the shift from materialism to organism,
  17216. as the basic idea of physical science.
  17217.  
  17218. In the language of physical science, the change from materialism to
  17219. 'organic realism'— as the new outlook may be termed—is the displacement
  17220. of the notion of static stuff by the notion of fluent energy. Such energy
  17221. has its structure of action and flow, and is inconceivable apart from such
  17222. structure. It is also conditioned by 'quantum' requirements. These are the
  17223. reflections into physical science of the individual prehensions, and of the
  17224. individual actual entities to which these prehensions belong. Mathematical
  17225. physics translates the saying of Heraclitus, 'AH things flow,' into its own
  17226. language. It then becomes, All things are vectors. Mathematical physics
  17227. also accepts the atomistic doctrine of Democritus. It translates it into the
  17228. phrase, All flow of energy obeys 'quantum' conditions.
  17229.  
  17230. But what has vanished from the field of ultimate scientific conceptions
  17231. is the notion of vacuous material existence with passive endurance, with
  17232. primary individual attributes, and with accidental adventures. Some fea-
  17233. tures of the physical world can be expressed in that way. But the concept
  17234. is useless as an ultimate notion in science, and in cosmology.
  17235.  
  17236.  
  17237.  
  17238. CHAPTER IV
  17239. STRAINS
  17240.  
  17241. SECTION I
  17242.  
  17243. [472] There is nothing in the real world which is merely an inert fact.
  17244. Every reality is there for feeling: it promotes feeling; and it is felt. Also
  17245. there is nothing which belongs merely to the privacy of feeling of one
  17246. individual actuality. All origination is private. But what has been thus
  17247. originated, publicly pervades the world. Thus the geometrical facts con-
  17248. cerning straight and flat loci are public facts characterizing the feelings of
  17249. actual entities. It so happens that in this epoch of the universe the feelings
  17250. involving them are of dominating importance. A feeling in which the
  17251. forms exemplified in the datum concern geometrical, straight, and flat
  17252. loci will be called a 'strain/ In a strain qualitative elements, other than the
  17253. geometrical forms, express themselves as qualities implicated in those
  17254. forms; also the forms are the forms ingredient in particular nexus forming
  17255. the objective data of the physical feelings in question. It is to be remem-
  17256. bered that two points determine a complete straight line, that three non-
  17257. collinear points determine a complete plane, and that four non-coplanar
  17258. points determine a complete three-dimensional flat locus.
  17259.  
  17260. Thus a strain has a complex distribution of geometrical significance.
  17261. There is the geometrical 'seat' which is composed of a limited set of loci
  17262. which are certain sets of points. These points belong to the volume de-
  17263. fining the standpoint of the experient subject. A strain is a complex in-
  17264. tegration of simpler feelings; and it includes in its complex character sim-
  17265. pler feelings in which the qualities concerned are more particularly asso-
  17266. ciated with [473] this seat. But the geometrical interest which dominates
  17267. the growth of a strain lifts into importance the complete lines, planes, and
  17268. three-dimensional flats, which are defined by the seat of the strain. In the
  17269. process of integration, these wider geometrical elements acquire implica-
  17270. tion with the qualities originated in the simpler stages. The process is an
  17271. example of the Category of Transmutation; and is to be explained by the
  17272. intervention of intermediate conceptual feelings. Thus extensive regions,
  17273. which are penetrated by the geometrical elements concerned, acquire ob-
  17274. jectification by means of the qualities and geometrical relations derived
  17275. from the simpler feelings. This type of objectification is characterized by
  17276. the close association of qualities and definite geometrical relations. It is the
  17277. basis of the so-called 'projection' of sensa. This projection of sensa in a
  17278. strain takes many forms according to the differences among various strains.
  17279.  
  17280.  
  17281.  
  17282. Strains 311
  17283.  
  17284. Sometimes the 'seat' retains its individual importance; sometimes in the
  17285. final synthesis it has been almost eliminated from the final synthesis of
  17286. feelings into the one strain. Sometimes the whole extensive region indi-
  17287. cated by the wider geometrical elements is only vaguely geometricized. In
  17288. this case, there is feeble geometrical indication: the strain then takes the
  17289. vague form of feeling certain qualities which are vaguely external. Some-
  17290. times the extensive region is geometricized without any corresponding
  17291. elimination of importance from the seat. In this case,f there is a dual
  17292. reference, to the seat here, and to some objectified region there. The here
  17293. is usually some portion of an animal body; whereas the geometricized
  17294. region may be within, or without, the animal body concerned.
  17295.  
  17296. It is obvious that important feelings of strain involve complex processes
  17297. of concrescence. They are accordingly only to be found in comparatively
  17298. high-grade actual entities. They do not in any respect necessarily involve
  17299. consciousness, or even that approach to consciousness which we associate
  17300. with life. But we shall find that the [474] behaviour of enduring physical
  17301. objects is only explicable by reference to the peculiarities of their strains.
  17302. On the other hand, the occurrences in empty space require less emphasis
  17303. on any peculiar ordering of strains. But the growth of ordered physical
  17304. complexity is dependent on the growth of ordered relationships among
  17305. strains. Fundamental equations in mathematical physics, such as Maxwell's
  17306. electromagnetic equations, are expressions of the ordering of strains
  17307. throughout the physical universe.
  17308.  
  17309.  
  17310.  
  17311. SECTION II
  17312.  
  17313. Presentational immediacy is our perception of the contemporary world
  17314. by means of the senses. It is a physical feeling. But it is a physical feeling
  17315. of a complex type to the formation of which conceptual feelings, more
  17316. primitive physical feelings, and transmutation have played their parts amid
  17317. processes of integration. Its objective datum is a nexus of contemporary
  17318. events, under the definite illustration of certain qualities and relations:
  17319. these qualities and relations are prehended with the subjective form de-
  17320. rived from the primitive physical feelings, thus becoming our 'private' sen-
  17321. sations. Finally, as in the case of all physical feelings, this complex deriva-
  17322. tive physical feeling acquires integration with the valuation inherent in its
  17323. conceptual realization! as a type of experience.
  17324.  
  17325. Naive common sense insists, first, on the 'subject* entertaining this
  17326. feeling; and, secondly, on the analytic components in the order: (i) region
  17327. in contemporary world as datum, (ii) sensations as derivative from, and
  17328. illustrative of, this datum, (Hi) integral feeling involving these elements,
  17329. (iv) appreciative subjective form, (v) interpretative subjective form, (vi)
  17330. purposive subjective form. But this analysis of presentational immediacy
  17331. has not exhausted the content of the feeling. For we feel with the body.
  17332.  
  17333.  
  17334.  
  17335. 312 The Theory of Extension
  17336.  
  17337. There may be some further specialization into a particular organ of sen-
  17338. sation; but in any case the 'withness' of the body is an ever-present, [475]
  17339. though elusive, element in our perceptions of presentational immediacy.
  17340. This 'withness' is the trace of the origination of the feeling concerned,
  17341. enshrined by that feeling in its subjective form and in its objective datum.
  17342. But in itself this 'withness of the body ? can be isolated as a component
  17343. feeling in the final 'satisfaction/ From this point of view, the body, or its
  17344. organ of sensation, becomes the objective datum of a component feeling;
  17345. and this feeling has its own subjective form. Also this feeling is physical,
  17346. so that we must look for an eternal object, to be a determinant of the
  17347. definiteness of the body, as objective datum. This component feeling will
  17348. be called the feeling of bodily efficacy. It is more primitive than the feel-
  17349. ing of presentational immediacy which issues from it. Both in common
  17350. sense and in physiological theory, this bodily efficacy is a component pre-
  17351. supposed by the presentational immediacy and leading up to it. Thus, in
  17352. the immediate subject, the presentational immediacy is to be conceived as
  17353. originated in a late phase, by the synthesis of the feeling of bodily efficacy
  17354. with other feelings. We have now to consider the nature of the other
  17355. feelings, and the complex eternal object concerned in the feeling of bodily
  17356. efficacy.
  17357.  
  17358. In the first place, this eternal object must be partially identified with the
  17359. eternal object in the final feeling of presentational immediacy. The whole
  17360. point of the connection between the two feelings is that the presentational
  17361. immediacy is derivative from the bodily efficacy. The present perception is
  17362. strictly inherited from the antecedent bodily functioning, unless all phys-
  17363. iological teaching is to be abandoned. Both eternal objects are highly com-
  17364. plex; and the complex elements of the second eternal object must at least
  17365. be involved in the complex elements of the former eternal object.
  17366.  
  17367. This complex eternal object is analysable into a sense-datum and a geo-
  17368. metrical pattern. In physics, the geometrical pattern appears as a state of
  17369. strain of that actual occasion in the body which is the subject of the \476)
  17370. feeling. But this feeling of bodily efficacy in the final percipient is the re-
  17371. enaction of an antecedent feeling by an antecedent actual entity in the
  17372. body. Thus in this antecedent entity there is a feeling concerned with the
  17373. same sense-datum and a highly analogous state of strain. The feeling must
  17374. be a 'strain* in the sense defined in the previous section. Now this strain
  17375. involves a geometricized region, which in this case also involves a 'focal'
  17376. region as part of itself. This 'focal' region is a region of dense concurrence
  17377. of straight lines defined by the 'seat/ It is the region onto which there is
  17378. so-called 'projection/
  17379.  
  17380. These lines enter into feeling through a process of integration of yet
  17381. simpler feelings which primarily concern the 'seat' of the pattern. These
  17382. lines have a twofold function as determinants of the feeling. They de-
  17383. fine the 'strain* of the feeler, and they define the focal region which they
  17384. thus relate to the feeler. In so far as we are merely considering an abstract
  17385.  
  17386.  
  17387.  
  17388. Strains 313
  17389.  
  17390. pattern, we are dealing with an abstract eternal object. But as a deter-
  17391. minant of a concrete feeling in a concrete percipient we are dealing with
  17392. the feeling as relating its subject (which includes the 'seat' in its volume)
  17393. to a definite spatial region (the focal region) external to itself. This defi-
  17394. nite contemporary focal region is a nexus which is part of the objective
  17395. datum. Thus the feeling of bodily efficacy is the feeling of the sense-da-
  17396. tum as generally implicated in the whole region (of antecedent 'seats' and
  17397. focal regions) geometrically defined by the inherited strains. This pat-
  17398. terned region is peculiarly dominated by the final 'seat' in the body of the
  17399. feeler, and by the final 'focal' region. Thus the sense-datum has a general
  17400. spatial relation, in which two spatial regions are dominant. Feelings of
  17401. this sort are inherited by man}' strands from the antecedent bodily nerves.
  17402. But in considering one definite feeling of presentational immediacy, these
  17403. many strands of transmission of bodily efficacy, in their final deliverance to
  17404. the ultimate percipient, converge upon the same focal region as picked out
  17405. by the many bodily 'strains/
  17406.  
  17407. \477] In the integration of these feelings a double act of transmutation
  17408. is achieved. In each of the successive feelings transmitted along the suc-
  17409. cessive actual entities of a bodily nervous strand there are two regions
  17410. mainly concerned; and there is a relation between them constituted by
  17411. intermediate regions picked out by the linkage of the pattern. One region
  17412. is the focal region already discussed, the other region is the seat in the
  17413. immediate subject, constituting its geometrical standpoint. The 'strain' of
  17414. the final actual entity defines the 'seat' and the 'focal region' and the in-
  17415. termediarv regions, and more vaguely the whole of a 'presented' space.
  17416. This final feeling of bodily strain— in the sense of 'strain' defined in the
  17417. previous section— is the last of a route of analogous feelings inherited one
  17418. from the other along the series of bodily occasions along some nerve, or
  17419. other path in the body. There will be parallel routes of such analogous
  17420. feelings, which finally converge with concurrent reinforcement upon the
  17421. single occasion, or route of occasions, which is the ultimate percipient.
  17422.  
  17423. Each of these bodily strain-feelings defines its own seat and its own
  17424. focal region and intermediaries. The sense-datum is vaguely associated
  17425. with the external world as thus felt and defined. But as such feelings are
  17426. 'transmuted,' either gradually, or at critical nodes in the body, there is an
  17427. increasing development of special emphasis. Now emphasis is valuation,
  17428. and can only be changed by renewed valuation. But valuation arises in
  17429. conceptual feelings. The conceptual counterpart of these physical feelings
  17430. can be analysed into many conceptual feelings, associating the sense-datum
  17431. with various regions defined by the strain. This conceptual feeling, by its
  17432. reference to definite regions, belongs to the secondary type termed 'propo-
  17433. sitional feelings.' One subordinate propositionai feeling associates the
  17434. sense-datum with the 'seat' of the feeler, another with the 'focal' region of
  17435. the feeler, another with the intermediary region of the feeler, another with
  17436. the seats of the antecedent elements of the [478] nervous strand, and so
  17437.  
  17438.  
  17439.  
  17440. 314 The Theory of Extension
  17441.  
  17442. on. The total association of the sense-datum with space-time is analysable
  17443. into a bewildering variety of associations with definite regions, contem-
  17444. porary and antecedent. In general, and apart from high-grade organisms,
  17445. this spatio-temporal association of the sense-datum is integrated into a
  17446. vague sense of externality. The component valuations have in such cases
  17447. failed to differentiate themselves into grades of intensity. But in high-
  17448. gradet cases, in which presentational immediacy is prominent, one of
  17449. three cases happens. Either (i) the association of the sense-datum with
  17450. the seats of some antecedent sets of feelers is exclusively emphasized, or
  17451. (ii) the association of the sense-datum with the focal region of the final
  17452. percipient is exclusively emphasized, or (iii) the association of the sense-
  17453. datum both with the seats of antecedent feelers and with the focal region
  17454. of the immediate feeler is emphasized.
  17455.  
  17456. But these regions are not apprehended in abstraction from the general
  17457. spatio-temporal continuum. The prehension of a region is always the pre-
  17458. hension of systematic elements in the extensive relationship between the
  17459. seat of the immediate feeler and the region concerned. When these valua-
  17460. tions have been effected, the Category of Transmutation provides for the
  17461. transmission to the succeeding subject of a feeling of these regions quali-
  17462. fied by (i.e., contrasted with) that sense-datum. In the first case, there are
  17463. purely bodily sensations; in the second case, there are 'projected' sensations,
  17464. involving regions of contemporary space beyond the body; in the third
  17465. case, there are both bodily feelings and sensations externally projected.
  17466. Thus in the case of all sensory feeling, there is initial privacy of concep-
  17467. tual emphasis passing into publicity of physical feeling.
  17468.  
  17469. Thus, by the agency of the Category of Transmutation, there are two
  17470. types of feelings, for which the objective datum is a nexus with undiscrim-
  17471. inated actual entities. The feelings of the first type are feelings of 'causal
  17472. efficacy'; and those of the second type are those of 'presenta- [479] tional
  17473. immediacy/ In the first type, the analogous elements in the various feelings
  17474. of the various actualities of the bodily nexus are transmuted into a feeling
  17475. ascribed to the bodily nexus as one entity. In the second type, the trans-
  17476. mutation is more elaborate and shifts the nexus concerned from the ante-
  17477. cedent bodily nexus (i.e., the 'seat') to the contemporary focal nexus.
  17478.  
  17479. Both these types of feeling are the outcome of a complex process of
  17480. massive simplification which is characteristic of higher grades of actual
  17481. entities. They apparently have but slight importance in the constitutions
  17482. of actual occasions in empty space; but they have dominating importance
  17483. in the physical feelings belonging to the life-historyt of enduring organisms
  17484. —the inorganic and organic, alike.
  17485.  
  17486. In respect to the sensa concerned, there is a gradual transformation of
  17487. their functions as they pass from occasion to occasion along a route of in-
  17488. heritance up to some final high-grade experient. In their most primitive
  17489. form of functioning, a sensum is felt physically with emotional enjoyment
  17490.  
  17491.  
  17492.  
  17493. Strains 315
  17494.  
  17495. of its sheer individual essence. For example, red is felt with emotional en-
  17496. joyment of its sheer redness. In this primitive prehension we have aborig-
  17497. inal physical feeling in which the subject feels itself as enjoying redness.
  17498. This is Hume's 'impression of sensation' stripped of all spatial relations
  17499. with other such impressions. In so far as they spring up in this primitive,
  17500. aboriginal way, they— in Hume's words— "arise in the soul from unknown
  17501. causes." But in fact we can never isolate such ultimate irrationalities. In
  17502. our experience, as in distinct analysis, physical feelings are always derived
  17503. from some antecedent experient. Occasion B prehends occasion A as an
  17504. antecedent subject experiencing a sensum with emotional intensity. Also
  17505. B's subjective form of emotion is conformed to A's subjective form. Thus
  17506. there is a vector transmission of emotional feeling of a sensum from A to
  17507. B. In this way B feels the sensum as derived from A and feels it with an
  17508. emotional form [480] also derived from A. This is the most primitive form
  17509. of the feeling of causal efficacy. In physics it is the transmission of a form
  17510. of energy. In the bodily transmission from occasion to occasion of a high-
  17511. grade animal body, there is a gradual modification of these functions of
  17512. sensa. In their most primitive functioning for the initial occasions within
  17513. the animal body, they are qualifications of emotion— types of energy, in
  17514. the language of physics;f in their final functioning for the high-grade
  17515. experient occasion at the end of the route, they are qualities 'inherent' in
  17516. a presented, contemporary nexus. In the final percipient any conscious
  17517. feeling of the primitive emotional functioning of the sensum is often en-
  17518. tirely absent. But this is not always the case; for example, the perception
  17519. of a red cloak may often be associated with a feeling of red irritation.
  17520.  
  17521. To return to Hume's doctrine (cf. Treatise, Part III, Sect. V) of the
  17522. origination of 'impressions of sensation' from unknown causes, it is
  17523. first necessary to distinguish logical priority from physical priority. Un-
  17524. doubtedly an impression of sensation is logically the simplest of physical
  17525. prehensions. It is the percipient occasion feeling the sensum as participat-
  17526. ing in its own concrescence. This is the enjoyment of a private sensation.
  17527.  
  17528. There is a logical simplicity about such a sensation which makes it the
  17529. primitive, aboriginal type of physical feeling. But there are two objections
  17530. to Hume's doctrine which assigns to them a physical priority. First, there
  17531. is the empirical objection. Hume's theory of a complex of such impres-
  17532. sions elaborated into a supposition of a common physical world is entirely
  17533. contrary to naive experience. We find ourselves in the double role of agents
  17534. and patients in a common world, and the conscious recognition of impres-
  17535. sions of sensation is the work of sophisticated elaboration. This is also
  17536. Locke's doctrine in the third and fourth books of his Essay. The child
  17537. first dimly elucidates the complex externality of particu- [481] lar things
  17538. exhibiting a welter of forms of definiteness, and then disentangles his im-
  17539. pressions of these forms in isolation. A young man does not initiate his
  17540. experience by dancing with impressions of sensation, and then proceed
  17541.  
  17542.  
  17543.  
  17544. 316 The Theory of Extension
  17545.  
  17546. to conjecture a partner. His experience takes the converse route. The un-
  17547. empirica! character of the philosophical school derived from Hume can-
  17548. not be too often insisted upon. The true empirical doctrine is that physi-
  17549. cal feelings are in their origin vectors, and that the genetic process of con-
  17550. crescence introduces the elements which emphasize privacy.
  17551.  
  17552. Secondly, Hume's doctrine is necessarily irrational. For if the impres-
  17553. sions of sensation arise from unknown causes (cf. Hume, loc. cit.) a stop
  17554. is put to the rationalistic search for a rational cosmology. Such a cos-
  17555. mology requires that metaphysics shall provide a doctrine of relevance
  17556. between a form and any occasion in which it participates. If there be no
  17557. such doctrine, all hope of approximating to a rational view of the world
  17558. vanishes.
  17559.  
  17560. Hume's doctrine has no recommendation except the pleasure which it
  17561. gives to its adherents.
  17562.  
  17563. The philosophy of organism provides for this relevance by means of
  17564. two doctrines, (i) the doctrine of God embodying a basic completeness
  17565. of appetition, and (ii) the doctrine of each occasion effecting a concres-
  17566. cence of the universe, including God. Then, by the Category of Conceptual
  17567. Reproduction, the vector prehensions of God's appetition, and of other
  17568. occasions, issue in the mental pole of conceptual prehensions; and by
  17569. integration of this pole with the pure physical prehensions there arise the
  17570. primitive physical feelings of sensa, with their subjective forms, t emotional
  17571. and purposive. These feelings, with their primitive simplicity, arise into
  17572. distinctness by reason of the elimination effected by this integration of the
  17573. vector prehensions with the conceptual appetitions. Such primitive feel-
  17574. ings cannot be separated from their subjective forms. The subject never
  17575. loses its triple character of recipient, patient, and agent. These primitive
  17576. feel- [482] ings have already been considered under the name of 'physical
  17577. purposes' (cf. Part III, Ch. V). They correspond to Hume's 'impressions
  17578. of sensation/ But they do not originate the process of experience.
  17579.  
  17580. We see that a feeling of presentational immediacy comes into being
  17581. by reason of an integration of a conceptual feeling drawn from bodily effi-
  17582. cacy with a bare regional feeling which is also a component in a complex
  17583. feeling of bodily efficacy. Also this bare regional feeling is reinforced with
  17584. the general regional feeling which is the whole of our direct physical feel-
  17585. ing of the contemporary world: and the conceptual feeling is reinforced
  17586. by the generation of physical purpose. This integration takes the form of
  17587. the creative imputation of the complex eternal object, ingredient in the
  17588. bodily efficacy, onto some contemporary focal region felt in the strain-
  17589. feeling. Also the subjective form is transmitted from the conceptual valu-
  17590. ation and the derivate physical purpose.' But this subjective form is that
  17591. suitable to the bodily efficacy out of which it has arisen. Thus the mere
  17592. region with its imputed eternal object is felt as though there had been a
  17593. feeling of its efficacy. But there is no mutual efficacy of contemporary
  17594.  
  17595.  
  17596.  
  17597. Strains 317
  17598.  
  17599. regions. This transference of subjective form is termed 'symbolic trans-
  17600. ference/ *
  17601.  
  17602. An additional conceptual feeling, with its valuation, arises from this
  17603. physical feeling of presentational immediacy. It is the conceptual feeling
  17604. of a region thus characterized. This is the aesthetic valuation proper to
  17605. the bare objective datum of the presentational immediacy. But this valua-
  17606. tion is less primitive than that gained from the conceptual prehension
  17607. by symbolic transference. The primitive subjective form includes a valua-
  17608. tion as though the contemporary region, by its own proper constitution,
  17609. were causally effective on the percipient sub- [483] ject. The secondary
  17610. valuation is the aesthetic appreciation of the bare fact: this bare fact is
  17611. merely that region, thus qualified. Thus the contemporary world, as felt
  17612. through the senses, is valued for its own sake, by means of a later concep-
  17613. tual feeling; but it is also valued for its derivation from antecedent effi-
  17614. cacy, by means of transmutation from earlier conceptual feeling com-
  17615. bined with derivate 'physical purpose/
  17616.  
  17617. But none of these operations can be segregated from nature into the
  17618. subjective privacy of a mind. Mental and physical operations are incurably
  17619. intertwined; and both issue into publicity, and are derived from publicity.
  17620. The vector character of prehension is fundamental.
  17621.  
  17622. SECTION III
  17623.  
  17624. It is the mark of a high-grade organism to eliminate, by negative pre-
  17625. hension, the irrelevant accidents in its environment, and to elicit massive
  17626. attention to every variety of systematic order. For this purpose, the Cate-
  17627. gory of Transmutation is the master-principle. By its operation each nexus
  17628. can be prehended in terms of the analogies among its own members, or
  17629. in terms of analogies among the members of other nexus but yet relevant
  17630. to it. In this way the organism in question suppresses the mere multi-
  17631. plicities of things, and designs its own contrasts. The canons of art are
  17632. merely the expression, in specialized forms, of the requisites for depth of
  17633. experience. The principles of morality are allied to the canons of art, in
  17634. that they also express, in another connection, the same requisites. Owing
  17635. to the principle that contemporary actual entities occur in relative inde-
  17636. pendence, the nexus of contemporary actual entities are peculiarly favour-
  17637. able for this transference of systematic qualities from other nexus to them-
  17638. selves. For a difficulty arises in the operation of the Category of Transmuta-
  17639. tion, when a characteristic prevalent among the individual entities of one
  17640. nexus is to be transferred to another nexus treated as a unity. The diffi-
  17641. culty is that the individual actuali- \484] ties of the recipient nexus are also
  17642.  
  17643. 1 Cf. my three Barbour-Page lectures, Symbolism, at the University of Virginia
  17644. (New York: Macmillan, 1927, and Cambridge University Press, 1928) ;t and
  17645. also above, Part II, Ch. VIII.
  17646.  
  17647.  
  17648.  
  17649. 318 The Theory of Extension
  17650.  
  17651. respectively objectified in the percipient subject by systematic character-
  17652. istics which equally demand the transference to their own nexus; but this
  17653. is the nexus which should be the recipient of the other transference. Thus
  17654. there are competing qualities struggling to effect the objectification of the
  17655. same nexus. The result is attenuation and elimination.
  17656.  
  17657. When the recipient nexus is composed of entities contemporary with
  17658. the percipient subject, this difficulty vanishes. For the contemporary en-
  17659. tities do not enter into the constitution of the percipient subject by ob-
  17660. jectification through any of their own feelings. Thus their only direct con-
  17661. nection with the subject is their implication in the same extensive scheme.
  17662. Thus a nexus of actual entities, contemporary with the percipient subject,
  17663. puts up no alternative characteristics to inhibit the transference to it of
  17664. characteristics from antecedent nexus.
  17665.  
  17666. A high-grade percipient is necessarily an occasion in the historic route
  17667. of an enduring object. If this route is to propagate itself successfully into
  17668. the future, it is above all things necessary that its decisions in the imme-
  17669. diate occasion should have the closest relevance to the concurrent hap-
  17670. penings among contemporary occasions. For these contemporary entities
  17671. will, in the near future, form the 'immediate past' for the future embodi-
  17672. ment of the enduring object. This 'immediate past' is of overwhelming in-
  17673. fluence; for all routes of transmission from the more remote past must
  17674. pass through it. Thus the contemporary occasions tell nothing; and yet
  17675. are of supreme importance for the survival of the enduring object.
  17676.  
  17677. This gap in the experience of the percipient subject is bridged by presen-
  17678. tational immediacy. This type of experience is the lesson of the past re-
  17679. flected into the present. The more important contemporary occasions
  17680. are those in the near neighborhood. Their actual worlds \485] are prac-
  17681. tically identical with that of the percipient subject. The percipient pre-
  17682. bends the nexus of contemporary occasions by the mediation of eternal
  17683. objects which it inherits from its own past. Also it selects the contemporary
  17684. nexus thus prehended by the efficacy of strains whose focal regions are
  17685. important elements in the past of those nexus. Thus, for successful orga-
  17686. nisms, presentational immediacy— though it yields no direct experience
  17687. about the contemporary world, and though in unfortunate instances the
  17688. experience which it does yield may be irrelevant— does yield experience
  17689. which expresses how the contemporary world has in fact emerged from
  17690. its own past.
  17691.  
  17692. Presentational immediacy works on the principle that it is better to ob-
  17693. tain information about the contemporary world, even if occasionally it be
  17694. misleading.
  17695.  
  17696. SECTION IV
  17697.  
  17698. Depth of experience is gained by concentrating emphasis on the sys-
  17699. tematic structural systems in the environment, and discarding individual
  17700. variations. Every element of systematic structure is emphasized, every in-
  17701.  
  17702.  
  17703.  
  17704. Strains 319
  17705.  
  17706. dividual aberration is pushed into the background. The variety sought is
  17707. the variety of structures, and never the variety of individuals. For example, t
  17708. we neglect empty space in comparison with the structural systematic
  17709. nexus which is the historic route of an enduring object. In every possible
  17710. way, the more advanced organisms simplify their experience so as to em-
  17711. phasize those nexus with some element of tightness of systematic structure.
  17712.  
  17713. In pursuance of this principle, the regions, geometricized by the various
  17714. strains in such an organism, not only lie in the contemporary world, t but
  17715. they coalesce so as to emphasize one unified locus in the contemporary
  17716. world. This selected locus is penetrated by the straight lines, the planes,
  17717. and the three-dimensional flat loci associated with the strains. This is the
  17718. 'strain-locus' belonging to an occasion in the history of an enduring object.
  17719. \486] This occasion is the immediate percipient subject under considera-
  17720. tion. Each such occasion has its one strain-locus which serves for all its
  17721. strains. The focal regions of the various strains all lie within this strain-
  17722. locus, and are in general distinct. But the strain-locus as a whole is com-
  17723. mon to all the strains. Each occasion lies in its own strain-locus.
  17724.  
  17725. The meaning of the term 'rest' is the relation of an occasion to its
  17726. strain-locus, if there be one. An occasion with no unified strain-locus has
  17727. no dominating locus with which it can have the relationship of 'rest/ An
  17728. occasion 'rests' in its strain-locus. This is why it is nonsense to ask of an
  17729. occasion in empty space whether it be 'at rest' in reference to some locus.
  17730. For, since such occasions have no strain-loci ? the relationship of 'rest' does
  17731. not apply to them. The strain-locus is the locus which is thoroughly geo-
  17732. metricized by the strain-feelings of the percipient occasion. It must have
  17733. the property of being continent of straight lines, and of flat loci of all
  17734. dimensions. Thus its boundaries will be three-dimensional t flat loci, non-
  17735. intersecting. A strain-locus approximates to a three-dimensional flat locus;
  17736. but in fact it is four-dimensional, with a time-thickness.
  17737.  
  17738. SECTION V
  17739.  
  17740. Reviewing the discussion in the preceding sections of this chapter and
  17741. of Chapter IV of Part II, we note that, in reference to any one actual
  17742. occasion M, seven (but cf. Section VHIt) distinct considerations define
  17743. loci composed of other actual occasions. In the first place, there are three
  17744. loci defined by causal efficacy, namelv, the 'causal past' of M, the 'causal
  17745. future' of M, and the 'contemporaries' of M. An actual occasion P, be-
  17746. longing to M's causal past, is objectified for M by a perspective represen-
  17747. tation of its own (i.e., P's) qualities of feeling and intensities of feeling.
  17748. There is a quantitative and qualitative vector flow of feeling from P to M;
  17749. and in this way, what P is subjectively, belongs to M objectively. An [487]
  17750. actual occasion Q, belonging to M's causal future, is in the converse rela-
  17751. tion to M, compared to P's relation. For the causal future is composed of
  17752. those actual occasions which will have M in their respective causal pasts. t
  17753.  
  17754.  
  17755.  
  17756. 320 The Theory of Extension
  17757.  
  17758. Actual occasions R and S,t which are contemporary with M, are those
  17759. actual occasions which lie neither in M's causal past, nor in M's causal
  17760. future. The peculiarity of the locus of contemporaries of M is that any two
  17761. of its members, such as R and S, need not be contemporaries of each other.
  17762. They may be mutually contemporaries, but not necessarily. It is evident
  17763. from the form of the definition of 'contemporary/ that if R be contem-
  17764. porary with M, then M is contemporary with R. This peculiarity of the
  17765. locus of JVTs contemporaries— that R and S may be both contemporaries
  17766. of M, but not contemporaries of each other— points to another set of loci.
  17767. A 'duration' is a locus of actual occasions, such that (a) any two members
  17768. of the locus are contemporaries, and (/?) that any actual occasion, not
  17769. belonging to the duration, is in the causal past or causal future of some
  17770. members of the duration.
  17771.  
  17772. A duration is a complete locus of actual occasions in 'unison of becom-
  17773. ing/ or in 'concrescent unison. 7 It is the old-fashioned 'present state of
  17774. the world/ In reference to a given duration, D, the actual world is divided
  17775. into three mutually exclusive loci. One of these loci is the duration D it-
  17776. self. Another of these loci is composed of actual occasions which lie in the
  17777. past of some members of D: this locus is the 'past of the duration D/ The
  17778. remaining locus is composed of actual occasions which lie in the future of
  17779. some members of D: this locus is the 'future of the duration D/
  17780.  
  17781. By its definition, a duration which contains an occasion Mf must lie
  17782. within the locus of the contemporaries of M. According to the classical
  17783. pre-relativistic notions of time, there would be only one duration including
  17784. M, and it would contain all M's contemporaries. According to modern
  17785. relativistic views, t we must admit that there are many durations including
  17786. M— in fact, an infinite [488] number, so that no one of them contains all
  17787. M's contemporaries.
  17788.  
  17789. Thus the past of a duration D includes the whole past of any actual
  17790. occasion belonging to D, such as M for example, and it also includes some
  17791. of ivis contemporaries. Also the future of the duration D includes the
  17792. whole future of M, and also includes some of M's contemporaries.
  17793.  
  17794. So far, starting from an actual occasion M, we find six loci, or types of
  17795. loci, defined purely in terms of notions derived from 'causal efficacy/ These
  17796. loci are, M's causal past, M's causal future, M's contemporaries, the set
  17797. of durations defined by M; and finally, taking any one such duration which
  17798. we call D as typical, there is D's past, and D's future. Thus there are the
  17799. three definite loci, the causal past, the causal future,* and the contem-
  17800. poraries, which are defined uniquely by M; and there are the set of dura-
  17801. tions defined by M, and the set of 'durational pasts' and the set of 'dura-
  17802. tional futures/ The paradox which has been introduced by the modern
  17803. theory of relativity is twofold. First, the actual occasion M does not, as a
  17804. general characteristic of all actual occasions, define a unique duration;
  17805. and secondly,! such a unique duration, if defined, does not include all the
  17806. contemporaries of M.
  17807.  
  17808.  
  17809.  
  17810. Strains 321
  17811.  
  17812. But among the set of durations, there may be one with a unique asso-
  17813. ciation with M. For the mode of presentational immediacy objectifies for
  17814. Mf the actual occasions within one particular duration. This is the 'pre-
  17815. sented duration/ Such a presented duration is an inherent factor in the
  17816. character of an 'enduring physical object.' It is practically identical with
  17817. the strain-locus. This locus is the reason why there is a certain absoluteness
  17818. in the notions of rest, velocity, and acceleration. For this presented dura-
  17819. tion is the spatialized world in which the physical object is at rest, at least
  17820. momentarily for its occasion M. This spatialized world is objectified for M
  17821. by M's own conditioned range of feeling-tones which have been inherited
  17822. from the causal past of the actual occasion [489] in question, namely, of
  17823. M. Thus the presented duration is with peculiar vividness part of the
  17824. character of the actual occasion, A historic route of actual occasions,!
  17825. each with its presented duration, constitutes a physical object.
  17826.  
  17827. Our partial consciousness of the objectifications of the presented dura-
  17828. tion constitutes our knowledge of the present world, so far as it is derived
  17829. from the senses. Remembering that objectifications constitute the objec-
  17830. tive conditions from which an actual occasion (M) initiates its successive
  17831. phases of feeling, we must admit that, in the most general sense, the ob-
  17832. jectifications express the causality by which the external world fashions
  17833. the actual occasion in question. Thus the objectifications of the presented
  17834. duration represent a recovery by its contemporaries of a very real efficacy
  17835. in the determination of M. It is true that the eternal objects which effect
  17836. this objectification belong to the feeling-tones which M derives from the
  17837. past. But it is a past which is largely common to M and to the presented
  17838. duration. Thus by the intermediacy of the past, the presented duration has
  17839. its efficacy in the production of M. This efficacy does not derogate from
  17840. the principle of the independence of contemporary occasions. For the con-
  17841. temporary occasions in the presented duration are only efficacious through
  17842. the feeling-tones of their sources, and not through their own immediate
  17843. feeling-tones.
  17844.  
  17845. Thus in so far as Bergson ascribes the 'spatialization' of the world to a
  17846. distortion introduced by the intellect, he is in error. This spatialization is
  17847. a real factor in the physical constitution of every actual occasion belong-
  17848. ing to the life-history f of an enduring physical object. For actual occasions
  17849. in so-called 'empty space/ there is no reason to believe that any duration
  17850. has been singled out for spatialization; that is to say, that physical per-
  17851. ception in the mode of presentational immediacy is negligible for such
  17852. occasions. The reality of the rest and the motion of enduring physical
  17853. objects depends on this spatializa- [490] tion for occasions in their historic
  17854. routes. The presented duration is the duration in respect to which the
  17855. enduring object is momentarily at rest. It is that duration which is the
  17856. strain-locus of that occasion in the life-history of the enduring object.
  17857.  
  17858.  
  17859.  
  17860. CHAPTER V
  17861. MEASUREMENT
  17862.  
  17863. SECTION I
  17864.  
  17865. [491] The identification of the strain-locus with a duration is only an
  17866. approximation based upon empirical evidence. Their definitions are en-
  17867. tirely different. A duration is a complete set of actual occasions, such that
  17868. all the members are mutually contemporary one with the other. This
  17869. property is expressed by the statement that the members enjoy 'unison of
  17870. immediacy/ The completeness consists in the fact that no other actual
  17871. occasion can be added to the set without loss of this unison of immediacy.
  17872. Every occasion outside the set is in the past or in the future of some
  17873. members of the set, and is contemporary with other members of the set.
  17874. According as an occasion is in the past, or the future, of some members
  17875. of a duration, the occasion is said to be in the past, or in the future, of
  17876. that duration.
  17877.  
  17878. No occasion can be both in the past and in the future! of a duration.
  17879. Thus a duration forms a barrier in the world between its past and its fu-
  17880. ture. Any route of occasions, in which adjacent members are contiguous,
  17881. and such that it includes members of the past, and members of the future,
  17882. of a duration, must also include one or more members of that duration.
  17883. This is the notion of a duration, which has already been explained (cf.
  17884. Part II, Ch. IV ? Sects. VIII and IX).
  17885.  
  17886. The definition of a strain-locus (cf. previous chapter) depends entirely
  17887. on the geometrical elements which arc the elements of geometric form in
  17888. the objectification of a nexus including the experient occasion in question.
  17889. These [492] elements are (i) a set of points, within the volume of the
  17890. regional standpoint of the experient occasion, and (ii) the set of straight
  17891. lines defined by all the pairs of these points. The set of points is the 'seat
  17892. of the strain; the set of straight lines is the set of projectors/ The com-
  17893. plete region penetrated by the 'projectors' is the strain-locus. A strain-
  17894. locus is bounded by two 'flat' three-dimensional surfaces. When some
  17895. members of the seat have a special function in the strain-feeling, the pro-
  17896. jectors which join pairs of these points may define a subordinate region
  17897. in the strain-locus; this subordinate region is termed the 'focal region/
  17898.  
  17899. The strain-loci in the present epoch seem to be confined to the con-
  17900. temporaries of their experient occasions. In fact 'strain-loci 7 occur as essen-
  17901. tial components for perception in the mode of presentational immediacy.
  17902.  
  17903. B22
  17904.  
  17905.  
  17906.  
  17907. Measurement 323
  17908.  
  17909. In this mode of perception there is a unique strain-locus for each such
  17910. experient. Rest and motion are definable by reference to real strain-loci,
  17911. and to potential strain-loci. Thus the molecules, forming material bodies
  17912. for which the science of dynamics is important, may be presumed to have
  17913. unique strain-loci associated with their prehensions.
  17914.  
  17915. This recapitulation of the theories of durations and strain-loci brings
  17916. out the entire disconnection of their definitions. There is no reason, de-
  17917. rivable from these definitions, why there should be any close association
  17918. between the strain-locus of an experient occasion and any duration includ-
  17919. ing that occasion among its members. It is an empirical fact that mankind
  17920. invariably conceives the presented world as consisting of such a duration.
  17921. This is the contemporary world as immediately perceived by the senses.
  17922. But close association does not necessarily involve unqualified identification.
  17923. It is permissible, in framing a cosmology to accord with scientific theory,
  17924. to assume that the associated pair, strain-locus and presented duration, do
  17925. not involve one and the same extensive region. From the point of view of
  17926. conscious per- [493] ception, the divergence may be negligible, though im-
  17927. portant for scientific theory.
  17928.  
  17929. SECTION II
  17930.  
  17931. Thet notions which have led to the phraseology characterizing the 'pro-
  17932. jected' sensa as 'secondary qualities' arise out of a fundamental difference
  17933. between 'strain-loci' and their associated 'presented durations.' A strain-
  17934. locus is entirely determined by the experient in question. It extends be-
  17935. yond that experient indefinitely, although defined by geometrical elements
  17936. entirely within the extensive region which is the standpoint of the ex-
  17937. perient. The 'seat' of the strain-locus, which is a set of points within this
  17938. region, is sufficient to effect this definition of the complete strain-locus by
  17939. the aid of the straight lines termed the 'projectors.' These straight lines
  17940. are nexus whose geometrical relations are forms ingredient in a strain-
  17941. feeling with these nexus as data. Presentational immediacy arises from
  17942. the integration of a strain-feeling and a 'physical purpose,' so that, by the
  17943. Category of Transmutation, the sensum involved in the 'physical purpose'
  17944. is projected onto some external focal region defined by projectors.
  17945.  
  17946. It is to be noted that this doctrine of presentational immediacy and of
  17947. the strain-locus entirely depends upon a definition of straight lines in terms
  17948. of mere extensiveness. If the definition depends upon the actual physical
  17949. occasions beyond the experient, the experient should find the actual phys-
  17950. ical structures of his environment a block, or an assistance, to his 'projec-
  17951. tion' to focal regions beyond them. The projection of sensa in presenta-
  17952. tional immediacy depends entirely upon the state of the brain and upon
  17953. systematic geometrical relations characterizing the brain. How the brain
  17954. is excited, whether by visual stimuli through the eye, or by auditory stimuli
  17955. through the ear, or by the excessive consumption of alcohol, or by hyster-
  17956.  
  17957.  
  17958.  
  17959. 324 The Theory of Extension
  17960.  
  17961. ical emotion, is completely indifferent; granted the proper excitement of
  17962. the brain, the experient will per- [494] ceive some definite contemporary
  17963. region illustrated by the projected sensa. The indifference of presentational
  17964. immediacy to contemporary actualities in the environment cannot be ex-
  17965. aggerated. It is only by reason of the fortunate dependence of the experi-
  17966. ent and of these contemporary actualities on a common past, that presen-
  17967. tational immediacy is more than a barren aesthetic display. It does display
  17968. something, namely, the real extensiveness of the contemporary world. It
  17969. involves the contemporary actualities but only objectifies them as condi-
  17970. tioned by extensive relations. It displays a system pervading the world, a
  17971. world including and transcending the experient. It is a vivid display of
  17972. systematic real potentiality, inclusive of the experient and reaching beyond
  17973. it. In so far as straight lines can only be defined in terms of measurements,
  17974. requiring particular actual occasions for their performance, the theory of
  17975. geometry lacks the requisite disengagement from particular physical fact.
  17976. The requisite geometrical forms can then only be introduced after exam-
  17977. ination of the particular actual occasions required for measurement. But
  17978. the theory of 'projection/ explained above, requires that the definition of
  17979. a complete straight line be logically prior to the particular actualities in
  17980. the extensive environment. This requisite has been supplied by the pre-
  17981. ceding theory of straight lines (cf. Ch. Hit). The projectors do depend
  17982. upon the one experient occasion. But even this dependence merely re-
  17983. quires that component feelings of that occasion should participate in
  17984. certain geometric elements, namely, a set of points, and the straight lines
  17985. defined by them, among their data. Thus, according to this explanation,
  17986. presentational immediacy is the mode in which vivid feelings of contem-
  17987. porary geometrical relations, with especial emphasis on certain 'focal' re-
  17988. gions, enter into experience.
  17989.  
  17990. This doctrine is what common sense always assumes. When we see a
  17991. coloured shape, it may be a real man, or a ghost, or an image behind a
  17992. mirror, or a hallucination; [495] but whatever it be, there it is— ex-
  17993. hibiting to us a certain region of external space. If we are gazing at a
  17994. nebula, a thousand light-years away, we are not looking backward through
  17995. a thousand years. Such ways of speaking are interpretative phrases,
  17996. diverting attention from the primary fact of direct experience, observing
  17997. the illumination of a contemporary patch of the heavens. In philosophy,
  17998. it is of the utmost importance to beware of the interpretative vagaries of
  17999. language. Further, the extent of the patch illuminated will depend en-
  18000. tirely upon the magnifying power of the telescope used. The correlation
  18001. of the patch, thus seen through the telescope, with a smaller patch, de-
  18002. fined by direct 'projection' from the observer, is again a question of scien-
  18003. tific interpretation. This smaller patch is what we are said to have seen
  18004. 'magnified' by the use of the telescope. What we do see is the bigger patch,
  18005. and we correlate it with the smaller patch by theoretical calculation. The
  18006. scientific explanation neglects the telescope and the larger patch really
  18007.  
  18008.  
  18009.  
  18010. Measurement 325
  18011.  
  18012. seen, and considers them as merely instrumental intermediaries. It con-
  18013. centrates on the contemporary smaller patch, and finally deserts even that
  18014. patch in favour of another region a thousand years in the past. This ex-
  18015. planation is only one illustration of the way in which so-called statements
  18016. of direct observation are, through and through, merely interpretative
  18017. statements of simple direct experience. When we say that we have seen
  18018. a man, we may mean that we have seen a patch which we believe to be a
  18019. man. In this case, our total relevant experience may be more than that
  18020. of bare sight. In Descartes' phraseology, our experience of the external
  18021. world embraces not only an 'inspectio' of the 'realitas objective' in the pre-
  18022. hensions in question, but also a 'judicium' which calls into play the totality
  18023. of our experience beyond those prehensions. The objection to this doctrine
  18024. of 'presentational immediacy'— that it presupposes a definition of straight
  18025. lines, freed from dependence on external actualities— has been removed
  18026. by the production of such a definition in Ch. III.* [496] Of course the
  18027. point of the definition is to demonstrate that the extensive continuum,
  18028. apart from the particular actualities into which it is atomized, includes in
  18029. its systematic structure the relationships of regions expressed by straight
  18030. lines. These relationships are there for perception.
  18031.  
  18032. SECTION III
  18033.  
  18034. The Cartesian doctrine of the 'realitas objective attaching to presenta-
  18035. tional immediacy is entirely denied by the modern doctrine of private
  18036. psychological fields. Locke's doctrine of 'secondary qualities' is a halfway
  18037. house to the modern position, and indeed so is Descartes' own position
  18038. considered as a whole. Descartes' doctrine on this point is obscure, and
  18039. is interpretable as according with that of the philosophy of organism. But
  18040. Locke conceives the sensa as purely mental additions to the facts of physi-
  18041. cal nature. Both philosophers conceive the physical world as in essential
  18042. independence of the mental world, though the two worlds have ill-defined
  18043. accidental relationships. According to the philosophy of organism, physical
  18044. and mental operations are inextricably intertwined; also we find the sensa
  18045. functioning as forms participating in the vector prehensions of one occa-
  18046. sion by another; and finally in tracing the origin of presentational im-
  18047. mediacy, we find mental operations transmuting the functions of sensa
  18048. so as to transfer them from being participants in causal prehensions into
  18049. participants in presentational t prehensions. But throughout the whole
  18050. story, the sensa are participating in nature as much as anything else. It is
  18051. the function of mentality to modify the physical participation of eternal
  18052. objects: the case of presentational prehensions is only one conspicuous
  18053. example. The whole doctrine of mentality— from the case of God down-
  18054. wards—is that it is a modifying agency. But Descartes and Locke aban-
  18055. don the 'realitas objectiva' so far as sensa are concerned (but for Descartes,
  18056. cf. Meditation f,t "it is certain all the same that the colours of [497] which
  18057.  
  18058.  
  18059.  
  18060. 326 The Theory of Extension
  18061.  
  18062. this is composed are necessarily real"), and hope to save it so far as ex-
  18063. tensive relations are concerned. This is an impossible compromise. It was
  18064. easily swept aside by Berkeley and Hume. (Cf. Enquiry , Sect. XII, Part I.f
  18065. Hume,t with obvious truth, refers to Berkeley as the originator of this
  18066. train of argument.) The modern doctrine of 'private psychological fields'
  18067. is the logical result of Hume's doctrine, though it is a result which Hume
  18068. 'as an agent' refused to accept. This modern doctrine raises a great diffi-
  18069. culty in the interpretation of modern science. For all exact observation is
  18070. made in these private psychological fields. It is then no use talking about
  18071. instruments and laboratories and physical energy. What is really being
  18072. observed are narrow bands of colour-sensa in the private psychological
  18073. space of colour- vis ion. The impressions of sensation which collectively
  18074. form this entirely private experience 'arise in the soul from unknown
  18075. causes/ The spectroscope is a myth, the radiant energy is a myth, the ob-
  18076. server's eye is a myth, the observer's brain is a myth, and the observer's
  18077. record of his experiment on a sheet of paper is a myth. When,f some
  18078. months later, he reads his notes to a learned society, he has a new visual
  18079. experience of black marks on a white background in a new private psycho-
  18080. logical field. And again, these experiences arise in his soul 'from unknown
  18081. causes.' It is merely 'custom' which leads him to connect his earlier with
  18082. his later experiences.
  18083.  
  18084. AH exact measurements are, on this theory, observations in such private
  18085. psychological fields.
  18086.  
  18087. Hume himself 'as an agent' refused to accept this doctrine. The con-
  18088. clusion is that Hume's account of experience is unduly simplified. This is
  18089. the conclusion adopted by the philosophy of organism.
  18090.  
  18091. But one important fact does emerge from the discussion: that all exact
  18092. measurements concern perceptions in the mode of presentational imme-
  18093. diacy; and that such observations purely concern the systematic geometric
  18094. forms of the environment, forms defined by projectors [498] from the
  18095. 'seat' of the strain and irrespective of the actualities which constitute the
  18096. environment. The contemporary actualities of the world are irrelevant to
  18097. these observations. AH scientific measurements merely concern the sys-
  18098. tematic real potentiality out of which these actualities arise. This is the
  18099. meaning of the doctrine that physical science is solely concerned with the
  18100. mathematical relations of the world.
  18101.  
  18102. These mathematical relations belong to the systematic order of exten-
  18103. siveness which characterizes the cosmic epoch in which we live. The
  18104. societies of enduring objects— electrons, protons, molecules, material bodies
  18105. —at once sustain that order and arise out of it The mathematical rela-
  18106. tions involved in presentational immediacy thus belong equally to the
  18107. world perceived and to the naturef of the percipient They are, at the
  18108. same time, public fact and private experience.
  18109.  
  18110. The perceptive mode of presentational immediacy is in one sense bar-
  18111. ren. So far as— apart from symbolic transference— it discloses the con-
  18112.  
  18113.  
  18114.  
  18115. Measurement 327
  18116.  
  18117. temporary world, that world, thus objectified, is devoid of all elements
  18118. constitutive of subjective form, elements emotional, appreciative, pur-
  18119. posive. The bonds of the objectified nexus only exhibit the definiteness
  18120. of mathematical relations.
  18121.  
  18122. But in another sense this perceptive mode has overwhelming signifi-
  18123. cance. It exhibits that complex of systematic mathematical relations which
  18124. participate in all the nexus of our cosmic epoch, in the widest meaning of
  18125. that term. These relations only characterize the epoch by reason of their
  18126. foundation in the immediate experience of the society of occasions domi-
  18127. nating that epoch. Thus we find a special application of the doctrine of
  18128. the interaction between societies of occasions and the laws of nature. The
  18129. perceptive mode in presentational immediacy is one of the defining char-
  18130. acteristics of the societies which constitute the nexus termed material
  18131. bodies. Also in some fainter intensity it belongs to the electromagnetic
  18132. occasions in empty space. From the point of view of a [499] single experi-
  18133. ent, that mode discloses systematic relations which dominate the environ-
  18134. ment. But the environment is dominated by these relationships by reason
  18135. of the experiences of the individual occasions constituting the societies.
  18136.  
  18137. It is by reason of this disclosure of ultimate system that an intellectual
  18138. comprehension of the physical universe is possible. There is a systematic
  18139. framework permeating all relevant fact. By reference to this framework the
  18140. variant, various, vagrant, evanescent details of the abundant world can
  18141. have their mutual relations exhibited by their correlation to the common
  18142. terms of a universal system. Sounds differ qualitatively among themselves,
  18143. sounds differ qualitatively from colours, colours differ qualitatively from
  18144. the rhythmic throbs of emotion and of pain; yet all alike are periodic
  18145. and have their spatial relations and their wave-lengths. The discovery of
  18146. the true relevance of the mathematical relations disclosed in presentational
  18147. immediacy was the first step in the intellectual conquest of nature. Accu-
  18148. rate science was then born. Apart from these relations as facts in nature,
  18149. such science is meaningless, a tale told by an idiot and credited by fools.
  18150. For example, the conjecture by an eminent astronomer, based on measure-
  18151. ments of photographic plates, that the period of the revolution of our
  18152. galaxy of stars is about three hundred million years can only derive its
  18153. meaning from the systematic geometrical relations which permeate the
  18154. epoch. But he would have required the same reference to system, if he
  18155. had made an analogous statement about the period of revolution of a
  18156. child's top. Also the two periods are comparable in terms of the system.
  18157.  
  18158. SECTION IV
  18159.  
  18160. Measurement depends upon counting and upon permanence. The ques-
  18161. tion is, what is counted, and what is permanent? The things that are
  18162. counted are the inches on a straight metal rod, a yard-measure. Also the
  18163. thing [500] that is permanent is this yard-measure in respect both to its
  18164.  
  18165.  
  18166.  
  18167. 328 The Theory of Extension
  18168.  
  18169. internal relations and in respect to some of its extensive relations to the
  18170. geometry of the world. In the first place, the rod is straight. Thus the
  18171. measurement depends on the straightness and not the straightness upon
  18172. the measurement. The modern answer to this statement is that the
  18173. measurement is a comparison of infinitesimals, or of an approximation to
  18174. infinitesimals. The answer to this answer is that there are no infinitesimals,
  18175. and that therefore there can be no approximation to them. In mathe-
  18176. matics,! all phraseology about infinitesimals is merely disguised statement
  18177. about a class of finites. This doctrine has been conclusive mathematical
  18178. theory since the time of Weierstrass in the middle of the nineteenth
  18179. century. Also all the contortions of curvature are possible for a segment
  18180. between any end-points.
  18181.  
  18182. Of course, in all measurement there is approximation in our supposi-
  18183. tions as to the yard-measure, t But it is approximation to straightness. Also
  18184. having regard to the systematic geometry of straight lines, and to the
  18185. type of approximation exhibited by the rod, the smaller the portion used,
  18186. the more negligible are the percentage errors introduced by the defects
  18187. from straightness. But unless the notion of straightness has a definite
  18188. meaning in reference to the extensive relations, this whole procedure in
  18189. practical measurement is meaningless. There is nothing to distinguish one
  18190. contorted segment between end-points from another contorted segment
  18191. between those end-points. One is no straighter than another. Also any
  18192. percentage differences between their lengths can exist.
  18193.  
  18194. Again, the inches are counted because they are congruent and are end-
  18195. on along the straight rod. No one counts coincident inches. The counting
  18196. essentially is concerned with non-coincident straight segments. The nu-
  18197. merical measure of length is the indication of the fact that the yard-
  18198. measure is a straight rod divisible into thirty-six congruent inch-long
  18199. segments.
  18200.  
  18201. [50 J] There is a modern doctrine that 'congruence' means the possibility
  18202. of coincidence. If this be the case, then the importance of congruence
  18203. would arise when the possibility is realized. Alternatively, the possibility
  18204. could be of importance as a lure entering into the subjective aim. If the
  18205. latter alternative were true, congruence would play its part in the form of
  18206. a tendency of congruent bodies to coalesce, or to resist coalescence. In
  18207. fact, there would be adversion to, or aversion from,t coalescence. Of course
  18208. the suggestion is fantastic. Recurring to the former alternative, the inv
  18209. portance of the thirty-six inches along the yard-measure depends on the
  18210. fact that they are not coincident and, until the destruction of the rod,
  18211. never will be coincident. There is a realized property of the rod that it is
  18212. thirty-six inches in length. Thus although 'coincidence' is used as a test
  18213. of congruence, it is not the meaning of congruence.
  18214.  
  18215. We must now consider the use of 'coincidence' as a test. Congruence is
  18216. tested either by the transference of a steel yard-measure from coincidence
  18217.  
  18218.  
  18219.  
  18220. Measurement 329
  18221.  
  18222. with one body to coincidence with another body, or by some optical means
  18223. dependent on the use of an optical instrument and on the congruence of
  18224. successive wave-lengths t in a train of waves, or by some other vibratory
  18225. device dependent on analogous principles.
  18226.  
  18227. It is at once evident that all these tests aref dependent on a direct in-
  18228. tuition of permanence. This 'permanence' means 'permanence in respect
  18229. to congruence'! for the various instruments employed, namely, the yard-
  18230. measure, or the optical instruments, or analogous instruments. For exam-
  18231. ple, the yard-measure is assumed to remain congruent to its previous self,
  18232. as it is transferred from one setting to another setting. It is not sufficient
  18233. to intuit that it remains the same body. Substances that are very deform-
  18234. able preserve that sort of self-identity. The required property is that of
  18235. self-congruence. Minute variations of physical conditions will make the
  18236. rod vary slightly; also sense-perception is never absolutely exact. [502] But
  18237. unless there be a meaning to 'exactitude/ the notions of a 'slight variation'
  18238. and of a 'slight defect from exactitude' are nonsense. Apart from such a
  18239. meaning the two occasions of the rod's existence are incomparable, except
  18240. by another experiment depending upon the same principles. There can
  18241. only be a finite number of such experiments; so ultimately we are reduced
  18242. to these direct judgments.
  18243.  
  18244. However far the testing of instruments and the corrections for changes
  18245. of physical factors, such as temperature, are carried, there is always a final
  18246. dependence upon direct intuitions that relevant circumstances are un-
  18247. changed. Instruments are used from minute to minute, from hour to hour,
  18248. and from day to day, with the sole guarantee of antecedent tests and of
  18249. the appearance of invariability of relevant circumstances.
  18250.  
  18251. This 'appearance' is always a perception in the mode of presentational
  18252. immediacy. If such perception be in any sense 'private' in contradistinction
  18253. to a correlative meaning for the term 'public/ then the perceptions, on
  18254. which scientific measurement depends, t merely throw light upon the pri-
  18255. vate psychology of the particular observer, and have no 'public' import.
  18256.  
  18257. Such a conclusion is so obviously inconsistent with our beliefs as to
  18258. the intercommunication of real actualities in a public world, that it may
  18259. be dismissed as a reductio ad absurdum, having regard to the groundwork
  18260. of common experience which is the final test of all science and philosophy.
  18261. A great deal of modern scientific philosophy consists in recurrence to the
  18262. theory of 'privacy' when such statements seem to afford a short cut to
  18263. simplicity of statement, and— on the other hand—of employment of the
  18264. notion of observing a public world when that concept is essential for ex-
  18265. pressing the status of science in common experience. Science is either an
  18266. important statement of systematic theory correlating observations of a
  18267. common world, or is the daydream oi a solitary intelligence with a taste
  18268. for the daydream of publication. But [503] it is not philosophy to vacillate
  18269. from one point of view to the other.
  18270.  
  18271.  
  18272.  
  18273. 330 The Theory of Extension
  18274.  
  18275.  
  18276.  
  18277. SECTION V
  18278.  
  18279. Finally, thet meaning of 'congruence' as a relation between two geo-
  18280. metrical elements in a strain-locus must be considered. It will be sufficient
  18281. to consider this meaning in reference to two segments of straight lines,
  18282. and to treat all other meanings as derivative from this.
  18283.  
  18284. A strain-locus is defined by the 'projectors 7 which penetrate any one
  18285. finite region within it. Such a locus is a systematic whole, independently
  18286. of the actualities which may atomize it. In this it is to be distinguished
  18287. from a 'duration* which does depend on its physical content. A strain-
  18288. locus depends merely upon its geometrical content. This geometrical con-
  18289. tent is expressed by any adequate set of 'axioms* from which the systematic
  18290. interconnections t of its included straight lines and points can be deduced.
  18291. This conclusion requires the systematic uniformity of the geometry of a
  18292. strain-locus, but refers to further empirical observation for the discovery
  18293. of the particular character of this uniform system. For example, the ques-
  18294. tion as to whether a complete straight line be a 'closed' serial locus of
  18295. points or an 'open* serial locus, is entirely a question for such discovery.
  18296. The only decision is to be found by comparing the rival theories in re-
  18297. spect to their power of elucidating observed facts.
  18298.  
  18299. The only relevant properties of straight lines are (i) their completeness,
  18300. (ii) their inclusion of points, (iii) their unique definition by any pair of
  18301. included points, (iv) their possibility of mutual intersection in a single
  18302. point. The additional axioms which express the systematic geometrical
  18303. theory must not have reference to length or to congruence. For these no-
  18304. tions are to be derived from the theory. Thus the axioms must have ex-
  18305. clusive reference to the intersection of straight lines, and to their inclusion
  18306. or exclusion of points indicated by the intersections of other lines. Such
  18307. sets of axioms are [504] well known to mathematicians. There are many
  18308. such sets which respectively constitute alternative geometrical theories.
  18309. Also given one set of axioms constituting a definite geometrical theory,
  18310. different sets of axioms can easily be obtained which are equivalent to each
  18311. other in the sense that all the other sets can be deduced from any one of
  18312. them. AH such equivalent sets produce the same geometrical theory. Equiv-
  18313. alent sets have their importance, but not for the present investigation. We
  18314. can therefore neglect them, and different sets of axioms will mean sets of
  18315. axioms which constitute incompatible geometrical theories.
  18316.  
  18317. There are many such sets, with a great variety of peculiar properties.
  18318. There are, however, three such sets which combine a peculiar simplicity
  18319. with a very general conformation to the observed facts. These sets give
  18320. the non-metrical properties of the three geometrical theories respectively
  18321. known to mathematicians as the theory of Elliptic Geometry, of Euclidean
  18322. Geometry, and of Hyperbolic Geometry.* It will serve no purpose to give
  18323. the three sets of axioms. But it is very easy to explain the main point of
  18324.  
  18325.  
  18326.  
  18327. Measurement 331
  18328.  
  18329. difference between the theories, without being led too far from the philo-
  18330. sophical discussion.
  18331.  
  18332. In the first place, a definition of a 'plane' can be given which is com-
  18333. mon to all the three theories. The definition already given in Chapter III
  18334. of this Part will suffice. But an alternative definition can be stated thus:
  18335. If A, B, C be any three non-collinear points, and AB, BC, CA denote the
  18336. three complete straight lines containing,! respectively, A and B, B and C,
  18337. C and A, then the straight lines which respectively intersect both members
  18338. of any pair of these three lines, not both lines at one of the corners A or
  18339. B or C, pass through all the points constituting one plane, and all their
  18340. incident points are incident in the plane.
  18341.  
  18342. Thus a plane is defined to be the locus of all the points incident in at
  18343. least one of such a group of straight lines. The axioms are such that this
  18344. definition is equivalent to [505] the definition in Chapter III. Also the
  18345. axioms secure that any straight line, passing through two points in a plane,
  18346. is itselft wholly incident in that plane. Also it follows from the definition
  18347. of a plane that a line I and a point P, not incident in I, are coplanar.
  18348.  
  18349. The distinction between the three geometrical theories can now be ex-
  18350. plained by the aid of such a triplet, a point P, a line I not passing through
  18351. P, and the plane n in which P and I are both incident. Consider all the
  18352. lines through P and incident in the plane jr.. Then in the Elliptic Geo-
  18353. metrical Theory, all these lines intersect the line I; in the Euclidean Geo-
  18354. metrical Theory, all these lines intersect the line f, with the exception of
  18355. one and only one line— the unique parallel to I through P; in the Hyper-
  18356. bolic Geometrical Theory the lines through P in the plane are divisible
  18357. into two classes, one class consisting of the lines intersecting f, the other
  18358. class consisting of the lines not intersecting I, and each class with an in-
  18359. finite number of members. Then it has been shown by Cayley and von
  18360. Staudt 1 that the congruence of segments and the numerical measures of
  18361. the distances involved are definable. The simplest case is that of Euclidean
  18362. Geometry, In that case the basic fact is that the opposite sides of parallelo-
  18363. grams are equal. A further complication is required to define congruence
  18364. between segments which are not parallel. But it would serve no purpose to
  18365. enter into the detailed solutions of this mathematical problem.
  18366.  
  18367. But the illustration afforded by the particular case of the congruence of
  18368. the opposite sides of parallelograms! enables the general principle under-
  18369. lying the notion of congruence to be explained. Two segments are congru-
  18370. ent when there is a certain analogy between their functions in a systematic
  18371. pattern of straight lines, which includes both of them.
  18372.  
  18373. The definition of this analogy is the definition of con- [5061 gruence in
  18374. terms of non-metrical geometry. It is possible to discover diverse analogies
  18375. which give definitions of congruence which are inconsistent with each
  18376.  
  18377. 1 Cf. Cayley's "Sixth Memoir On Quantics," Transactions of the Royal So-
  18378. ciety, 1859; vonf Staudt's Geometrie der Lage, 1847; and Beitrage zur Geom-
  18379. etrie der Lage, 1856.
  18380.  
  18381.  
  18382.  
  18383. 332 The Theory of Extension
  18384.  
  18385. other. That definition which enters importantly into the internal consti-
  18386. tutions of the dominating social entities is the important definition for the
  18387. cosmic epoch in question.
  18388.  
  18389. Measurement is now possible throughout the extensive continuum. This
  18390. measurement is a systematic procedure dependent on the dominant so-
  18391. cieties of the cosmic epoch. When one form of measurement has been
  18392. given, alternative forms with assigned mathematical relations to the initial
  18393. form can be defined. One such system is as good as any other, so far as
  18394. mathematical procedure is concerned. The only point to be remembered is
  18395. that each system of 'coordinates' must have its definable relation to the
  18396. analogy which constitutes congruence.
  18397.  
  18398. SECTION VI
  18399.  
  18400. Physical measurement is now possible. The modern procedure, intro-
  18401. duced by Einstein, is a generalization of the method of least action/ It
  18402. consists in considering any continuous line between any two points in
  18403. the spatio-temporal continuum and seeking to express the physical prop-
  18404. erties of the field as an integral along it. The measurements which are
  18405. presupposed are the geometrical measurements constituting the coordi-
  18406. nates of the various points involved. Various physical quantities enter as
  18407. the 'constants' involved in the algebraic functions concerned. These con-
  18408. stants depend on the actual occasions which atomize the extensive con-
  18409. tinuum. The physical properties of the medium are expressed by various
  18410. conditions satisfied by this integral.
  18411.  
  18412. It is usual to term an 'infinitesimal' element of this integral by the name
  18413. of an element of distance. But this name, though satisfactory as a technical
  18414. phraseology, is entirely misleading. There can be no theory of the con-
  18415. gruence of different elements of the path. The notion of coincidence does
  18416. not apply. There is no systematic [507] theory possible, since the so-called
  18417. 'infinitesimal* distance depends on the actual entities throughout the en-
  18418. vironment. The only way of expressing such so-called distance is to make
  18419. use of the presupposed geometrical measurements. The mistake arises
  18420. because, unconsciously, the minds of physicists are infected by a presup-
  18421. position which comes down from Aristotle through Kant. Aristotle placed
  18422. 'quantity' among his categories, and did not distinguish between extensive
  18423. quantity and intensive quantity. Kant made this distinction, but consid-
  18424. ered both of them as categoreal notions. It follows from Cayley's and von
  18425. Staudt's work (cf. loc. cit.) that extensive quantity is a construct. The
  18426. current physical theory presupposes a comparison of so-called lengths
  18427. among segments without any theory as to the basis on which this com-
  18428. parison is to be made, and in ignoration of the fact that all exact observa-
  18429. tion belongs to the mode of presentational immediacy. Further, the fact is
  18430. neglected that there are no infinitesimals, and that a comparison of finite
  18431. segments is thus required. For this reason, it would be better— so far as
  18432.  
  18433.  
  18434.  
  18435. Measurement 333
  18436.  
  18437. explanation is concerned — to abandon the term 'distance' for this integral,
  18438. and to call it by some such name as 'impetus/ suggestive of its physical
  18439. import. 2
  18440.  
  18441. It is to be noted, however, that the conclusions of this discussion involve
  18442. no objection to the modern treatment of ultimate physical laws in the
  18443. guise of a problem in differential geometry. The integral impetus is an
  18444. extensive quantity, a length/ The differential element of impetus is
  18445. the differential element of systematic length weighted with the individual
  18446. peculiarities of its relevant environment. The whole theory of the physical
  18447. field is the interweaving of the individual peculiarities of actual occasions
  18448. upon the background of systematic geometry. This systematic geometry ex-
  18449. presses the most general 'substantial form' inherited throughout the vast
  18450. cosmic society which \508] constitutes the primary real potentiality condi-
  18451. tioning concrescence. 3 In this doctrine, the organic philosophy is very near
  18452. to the philosophy of Descartes.
  18453.  
  18454. The whole argument can be summarized thus:
  18455.  
  18456. (i) Actual occasions are immovable, so that the doctrine of coincidence
  18457. is nonsense.
  18458.  
  18459. (ii) Extensive quantity is a logical construct, expressing the number of
  18460. congruent units which are (a) non-overlapping, and (b) exhaustive of the
  18461. nexus in question.
  18462.  
  18463. (iii) Congruence is only definable as a certain definite analogy of func-
  18464. tion in a systematic complex which embraces both congruent elements.
  18465.  
  18466. (iv) That all experimental measurement involves ultimate intuitions of
  18467. congruence between earlier and later states of the instruments employed.
  18468.  
  18469. (v) That all exact observation is made by perception in the mode of
  18470. presentational immediacy.
  18471.  
  18472. (vi) That if such perception merely concerns a private psychological
  18473. field, science is the daydream of an individual without any public import.
  18474.  
  18475. (vii) That perception in the mode of presentational immediacy solely
  18476. depends upon the 'withness' of the 'body/ and only exhibits the external
  18477. contemporary world in respect to its systematic geometrical relationship
  18478. to the 'body/
  18479.  
  18480.  
  18481.  
  18482. 2 Cf. my book, The Principle of Relativity, University Press, Cambridge, 1922.
  18483.  
  18484. 3 This theory of the derivation of the basic uniformity requisite for congruence,
  18485. and thence for measurement, should be compared with that of two deeply in-
  18486. teresting articles: (i) "The Theory of Relativity and The First Principles of Sci-
  18487. ence/* and (ii) "The Macroscopic Atomic Theory/' Journal of Philosophy , Vol.
  18488. XXV, f by Professor F. S. C. Northrop of Yale. I cannot adjust his doctrine of
  18489. a 'macroscopic atom' to my cosmological outlook. Nor does this norion seem
  18490. necessary if my doctrine of 'microscopic atomic occasions' be accepted. But
  18491. Professor Northrop's theory does seem to be the only alternative if this doctrine
  18492. be abandoned. I regret that the articles did not come under my notice till this
  18493. work had been finally revised for publication.
  18494.  
  18495.  
  18496.  
  18497. PART V
  18498. FINAL INTERPRETATION
  18499.  
  18500.  
  18501.  
  18502. CHAPTER I
  18503. THE IDEAL OPPOSITES
  18504.  
  18505. SECTION I
  18506.  
  18507. [512] The chief danger to philosophy is narrowness in the selection of
  18508. evidence. This narrowness arises from the idiosyncrasies and timidities of
  18509. particular authors, of particular social groups, of particular schools of
  18510. thought, of particular epochs in the history of civilization. The evidence
  18511. relied upon is arbitrarily biased by the temperaments of individuals, by
  18512. the provincialities of groups, and by the limitations of schemes of thought.
  18513.  
  18514. The evil, resulting from this distortion of evidence, is at its worst in the
  18515. consideration of the topic of the final part of this investigation— ultimate
  18516. ideals. We must commence this topic by an endeavour to state impartially
  18517. the general types of the great ideals which have prevailed at sundry sea-
  18518. sons and places. Our test in the selection,! to be impartial, must be prag-
  18519. matic: the chosen stage of exemplification must be such as to compel at-
  18520. tention, by its own intrinsic interest, or by the intrinsic interest of the
  18521. results which flow from it. For example, the stern self-restraint of the Ro-
  18522. man farmers in the early history of the Republic issued in the great epoch
  18523. of the Roman Empire; and the stern self-restraint of the early Puritans in
  18524. New England issued in the flowering of New England culture. The epoch
  18525. of the Covenanters has had for its issue the deep impression which mod-
  18526. ern civilization owes to Scotland. Neither the Roman farmers, nor the
  18527. American Puritans, nor the Covenanters, can wholly command allegiance.
  18528. Also they differ from each other. But in either case, there is greatness there,
  18529. greatly exemplified. In contrast to this example, we find the flowering time
  18530. of the aesthetic culture of ancient Greece, the Augustan epoch in Rome,
  18531. the Italian Renaissance, the Elizabethan epoch in England, the Restora-
  18532. tion epoch in England, \513) French and Teutonic civilization throughout
  18533. the centuries of the modern world, Modern Paris, and Modern New York.
  18534. Moralists have much to say about some of these societies. Yet, while there
  18535. is any critical judgment in the lives of men, such achievements can never
  18536. be forgotten. In the estimation of either type of these contrasted examples,
  18537. sheer contempt betokens blindness. In each of these instances, there are
  18538. elements which compel admiration. There is a greatness in the lives of
  18539. those who build up religious systems, a greatness in action, in idea and in
  18540. self-subordination, embodied in instance after instance through centuries
  18541. of growth. There is a greatness in the rebels who destroy such systems:
  18542.  
  18543. 337
  18544.  
  18545.  
  18546.  
  18547. 338 Final Interpretation
  18548.  
  18549. they are the Titans who storm heaven, armed with passionate sincerity. It
  18550. may be that the revolt is the mere assertion by youth of its right to its
  18551. proper brilliance, to that final good of immediate joy. Philosophy may not
  18552. neglect the multifariousness of the world— the fairies dance, and Christ is
  18553. nailed to the cross.
  18554.  
  18555.  
  18556.  
  18557. SECTION II
  18558.  
  18559. There are various contrasted qualities of temperament, which control the
  18560. formation of the mentalities of different epochs. In a previous chapter
  18561. (Part II, Ch. X) attention has already been drawn to the sense of perma-
  18562. nence dominating the invocation 'Abide with Me/ and the sense of flux
  18563. dominating the sequel 'Fast Falls the Eventide/ Ideals fashion themselves
  18564. round these two notions, permanence and flux. In the inescapable flux,
  18565. there is something that abides; in the overwhelming permanence, there is
  18566. an element that escapes into flux. Permanence can be snatched only out of
  18567. flux; and the passing moment can find its adequate intensity only by its
  18568. submission to permanence. Those who would disjoin the two elements
  18569. can find no interpretation of patent facts.
  18570.  
  18571. The four symbolic figures in the Medici chapel in Florence— Michel-
  18572. angelo's masterpieces of statuary, Day [514] and Night, Evening and
  18573. Dawn— exhibit the everlasting elements in the passage of fact. The figures
  18574. stay there, reclining in their recurring sequence, forever showing the es-
  18575. sences in the nature of things. The perfect realization is not merely the
  18576. exemplification of what in abstraction is timeless. It does more: it implants
  18577. timelessness on what in its essence is passing. The perfect moment is fade-
  18578. less in the lapse of time. Time has then lost its character of 'perpetual
  18579. perishing'; it becomes the 'moving image of eternity/
  18580.  
  18581.  
  18582.  
  18583. SECTION III
  18584.  
  18585. Another contrast is equally essential for the understanding of ideals— the
  18586. contrast between order as the condition for excellence, and order as stifling
  18587. the freshness of living. This contrast is met with in the theory of educa-
  18588. tion. The condition for excellence is a thorough training in technique.
  18589. Sheer skill must pass out of the sphere of conscious exercise, and must
  18590. have assumed the character of unconscious habit. The first, the second,
  18591. and the third condition for high achievement is scholarship, in that en-
  18592. larged sense including knowledge and acquired instinct controlling action.
  18593.  
  18594. The paradox which wrecks so many promising theories of education is
  18595. that the training which produces skill is so very apt to stifle imaginative
  18596. zest. Skill demands repetition, and imaginative zest is tinged with impulse.
  18597. Up to a certain point each gain in skill opens new paths for the imagina-
  18598. tion. But in each individual formal training has its limit of usefulness. Be-
  18599.  
  18600.  
  18601.  
  18602. Ideal Opposites 339
  18603.  
  18604. yond that limit there is degeneration: The lilies of the field toil not,
  18605. neither do they spin/
  18606.  
  18607. The social history of mankind exhibits great organizations in their al-
  18608. ternating functions of conditions for progress, and of contrivances for
  18609. stunting humanity. The history of the Mediterranean lands, and of west-
  18610. ern Europe, is the history of the blessing and the curset of political or-
  18611. ganizations, of religious organizations, of [SIS] schemes of thought, of so-
  18612. cial agencies for large purposes. The moment of dominance, prayed for,
  18613. worked for, sacrificed for, by generations of the noblest spirits, marks the
  18614. turning point where the blessing passes into the curse. Some new principle
  18615. of refreshment is required. The art of progress is to preserve order amid
  18616. change, and to preserve change amid order. Life refuses to be embalmed
  18617. alive. The more prolonged the halt in some unrelieved system of order, the
  18618. greater the crash of the dead society.
  18619.  
  18620. The same principle is exhibited by the tedium arising from the unre-
  18621. lieved dominance of a fashion in art. Europe, having covered itself with
  18622. treasures of Gothic architecture, entered upon generations of satiation.
  18623. These jaded epochs seem to have lost all sense of that particular form of
  18624. loveliness. It seems as though the last delicacies of feeling require some
  18625. element of novelty to relieve their massive inheritance from bygone sys-
  18626. tem. Order is not sufficient. What is required, is something much more
  18627. complex. It is order entering upon novelty; so that the massiveness of
  18628. order does not degenerate into mere repetition; and so that the novelty
  18629. is always reflected upon a background of system.
  18630.  
  18631. But the two elements must not really be disjoined. It belongs to the
  18632. goodness of the world, that its settled order should deal tenderly with the
  18633. faint discordant light of the dawn of another age. Also order, as it sinks
  18634. into the background before new conditions, has its requirements. The old
  18635. dominance should be transformed into the firm foundations, upon which
  18636. new feelings arise, drawing their intensities from delicacies of contrast be-
  18637. tween system and freshness. In either alternative of excess, whether the
  18638. past be lost, or be dominant, the present is enfeebled. This is only an
  18639. application of Aristotle's doctrine of the 'golden mean/ The lesson of the
  18640. transmutation of causal efficacy into presentational immediacy is that great
  18641. ends are reached by life in the present; life novel and immediate, but
  18642. deriving its richness by its full inheritance from the rightly organized [S16]
  18643. animal body. It is by reason of the body, with its miracle of order, that
  18644. the treasures of the past environment are poured into the living occasion.
  18645. The final percipient route of occasions is perhaps some thread of happen-
  18646. ings wandering in 'empty' space amid the interstices of the brain. It toils
  18647. not, neither does it spin. It receives from the past; it lives in the present. It
  18648. is shaken by its intensities of private feeling, adversion or aversion. In its
  18649. turn, this culmination of bodily life transmits itself as an element of
  18650. novelty throughout the avenues of the body. Its sole use to the body is its
  18651. vivid originality: it is the organ of novelty.
  18652.  
  18653.  
  18654.  
  18655. 340 Final Interpretation
  18656.  
  18657. SECTION IV
  18658.  
  18659. The world is thus faced by the paradox that, at least in its higher ac-
  18660. tualities, it craves for novelty and yet is haunted by terror at the loss of the
  18661. past, with its familiarities and its loved ones. It seeks escape from time in
  18662. its character of 'perpetually perishing/ Part of the joy of the new years is
  18663. the hope of the old round of seasons, with their stable facts— of friendship,
  18664. and love, and old association. Yet conjointly with this terror, the present
  18665. as mere unrelieved preservation of the past assumes the character of a
  18666. horror of the past, rejection of it, revolt:
  18667.  
  18668. To die be given, or attain,
  18669. Fierce work it were to do again.*
  18670.  
  18671. Each new epoch enters upon its career by waging unrelenting war upon
  18672. the aesthetic gods of its immediate predecessor. Yet the culminating fact of
  18673. conscious, rational life refuses to conceive itself as a transient enjoyment,
  18674. transiently useful. In the order of the physical world its role is defined by
  18675. its introduction of novelty. But, just as physical feelings are haunted by
  18676. the vague insistence of causality, so the higher intellectual feelings are
  18677. haunted by the vague insistence of another order, where there is no un-
  18678. rest, no travel, no shipwreck: There shall be no more sea/
  18679.  
  18680. [517] This is the problem which gradually shapes itself as religion
  18681. reaches its higher phases in civilized communities. The most general
  18682. formulation of the religious problem is the question whether the process of
  18683. the temporal world passes into the formation of other actualities, bound
  18684. together in an order in which novelty does not mean loss.
  18685.  
  18686. The ultimate evil in the temporal world is deeper than any specific evil.
  18687. It lies in the fact that the past fades, that time is a 'perpetual perishing/
  18688. Objectification involves elimination. The present fact has not the past
  18689. fact with it in any full immediacy. The process of time veils the past be-
  18690. low distinctive feeling. There is a unison of becoming among things in
  18691. the present. Why should there not be novelty without loss of this direct
  18692. unison of immediacy among things? In the temporal world, it is the em-
  18693. pirical fact that process entails loss: the past is present under an abstrac-
  18694. tion. But there is no reason, of any ultimate metaphysical generality, why
  18695. this should be the whole story. The nature of evil is that the characters of
  18696. things are mutually obstructive. Thus the depths of life require a process of
  18697. selection. But the selection is elimination as the first step towards another
  18698. temporal order seeking to minimize obstructive modes. Selection is at once
  18699. the measure of evil, and the process of its evasion. It means t discarding
  18700. the element of obstructiveness in fact. No element in fact is ineffectual:
  18701. thus the straggle with evil is a process of building up a mode of utilization
  18702. by the provision of intermediate elements introducing a complex structure
  18703. of harmony. The triviality in some initial reconstruction of order expresses
  18704. the fact that actualities are being produced, which, trivial in their own
  18705.  
  18706.  
  18707.  
  18708. Ideal Opposites 341
  18709.  
  18710. proper character of immediate 'ends/ are proper 'means' for the emergence
  18711. of a world at once lucid, and intrinsically of immediate worth.
  18712.  
  18713. The evil of the world is that those elements which are translucent so far
  18714. as transmission is concerned, in themselves are of slight weight; and that
  18715. those elements [518] with individual weight, by their discord, impose upon
  18716. vivid immediacy the obligation that it fade into night. 'He giveth his be-
  18717. loved—sleep/
  18718.  
  18719. In our cosmological construction we are, therefore, f left with the final
  18720. opposites, joy and sorrow, good and evil, disjunction and conjunction—
  18721. that is to say, the many in one—flux and permanence, greatness and
  18722. triviality, freedom and necessity, God and the World. In this list, the pairs
  18723. of opposites are in experience with a certain ultimate directness of in-
  18724. tuition, except in the case of the last pair. God and the World introduce
  18725. the note of interpretation. They embody the interpretation of the cos-
  18726. mological problem in terms of a fundamental metaphysical doctrine as to
  18727. the quality of creative origination, namely, conceptual appetition and
  18728. physical realization. This topic constitutes the last chapter of Cosmology.
  18729.  
  18730.  
  18731.  
  18732. 344 Final Interpretation
  18733.  
  18734. Thus, when we make a distinction of reason, and con- [522] sider God in
  18735. the abstraction of a primordial actuality, we must ascribe to him neither
  18736. fulness of feeling, nor consciousness. He is the unconditioned actuality of
  18737. conceptual feeling at the base of things; so that, by reason of this pri-
  18738. mordial actuality, there is an order in the relevance of eternal objects to
  18739. the process of creation. His unity of conceptual operations is a free crea-
  18740. tive act, untrammelled by reference to any particular course of things. It
  18741. is deflected neither by love, nor by hatred, for what in fact comes to pass.
  18742. The particularities of the actual world presuppose it; while it merely pre-
  18743. supposes the general metaphysical character of creative advance, of which
  18744. it is the primordial exemplification. The primordial nature of God is the
  18745. acquirement by creativity of a primordial character.
  18746.  
  18747. His conceptual actuality at once exemplifies and establishes the cate-
  18748. goreal conditions. The conceptual feelings, which compose his primordial
  18749. nature, exemplify in their subjective forms their mutual sensitivity and
  18750. their subjective unity of subjective aim. These subjective forms are valua-
  18751. tions determining the relative relevance of eternal objects for each occa-
  18752. sion of actuality.
  18753.  
  18754. He is the lure for feeling, the eternal urge of desire. His particular
  18755. relevance to each creative act,f as it arises from its own conditioned stand-
  18756. point in the world, constitutes him the initial 'object of desire' establish-
  18757. ing the initial phase of each subjective aim. A quotation from Aristotle's
  18758. Metaphysics 1 expresses some analogies to, and some differences from, this
  18759. line of thought:
  18760.  
  18761. And since that which is moved and moves f is intermediate, there is
  18762. something! which moves without being moved, being eternal, sub-
  18763. stance, and actuality. And the object of desire and the object of thought
  18764. move in this way; they move without being moved. The primary objects
  18765. of desire and of thoughts are the same. For the apparent good is the
  18766. object of appetite, and the real good is the primary object of rational
  18767. wish.f But desire is conse- [523] quent on opinion rather than opinion
  18768. on desire; for the thinking is the starting-point. And thought is moved
  18769. by the object of thought, and one of the two columns t of op-
  18770. posites is in itself the object of thought; . . .
  18771. Aristotle had not made the distinction between conceptual feelings and
  18772. the intellectual feelings which alone involve consciousness. But if 'con-
  18773. ceptual feeling/ with its subjective form of valuation, be substituted for
  18774. 'thought/ 'thinking/ and 'opinion/ in the above quotation, the agreement
  18775. is exact.
  18776.  
  18777. SECTION III
  18778.  
  18779. There is another side to the nature of God which cannot be omitted.
  18780. Throughout this exposition of the philosophy of organism we have been
  18781.  
  18782. 1 Metaphysics 1072a 23-32, t trans, by Professor W. D. Ross. My attention
  18783. was called to the appositeness of this particular quotation by Mr. F. J. Carson.
  18784.  
  18785.  
  18786.  
  18787. 346 Final Interpretation
  18788.  
  18789. In it there is no loss, no obstruction. The world is felt in a unison of im-
  18790. mediacy. The property of combining creative advance with [525} the re-
  18791. tention of mutual immediacy is what in the previous section is meant by
  18792. the term 'everlasting/
  18793.  
  18794. The wisdom of subjective aim prehends every actuality for what it can be
  18795. in such a perfected system— its sufferings, its sorrows, its failures, its tri-
  18796. umphs, its immediacies of joy— woven by Tightness of feeling into the har-
  18797. mony of the universal feeling, which is always immediate, always many,
  18798. always one, always with novel advance, moving onward and never perish-
  18799. ing. The revolts of destructive evil, purely self-regarding, are dismissed into
  18800. their triviality of merely individual facts; and yet the good they did achieve
  18801. in individual joy, in individual sorrow, in the introduction of needed con-
  18802. trast, is yet saved by its relation to the completed whole. The image— and
  18803. it is but an image— the image under which this operative growth of God's
  18804. nature is best conceived, is that of a tender care that nothing be lost.
  18805.  
  18806. The consequent nature of God is his judgment on the world. He saves
  18807. the world as it passes into the immediacy of his own life. It is the judgment
  18808. of a tenderness which loses nothing that can be saved. It is also the judg-
  18809. ment of a wisdom which uses what in the temporal world is mere wreckage.
  18810.  
  18811. Another image which is also required to understand his consequent na-
  18812. turet is that of his infinite patience. The universe includes a threefold
  18813. creative act composed of (i) the one infinite conceptual realization, (ii)
  18814. the multiple solidarity of free physical realizations in the temporal world,
  18815. (iii) the ultimate unity of the multiplicity of actual fact with the pri-
  18816. mordial conceptual fact. If we conceive the first term and the last term in
  18817. their unity over against the intermediate multiple freedom of physical
  18818. realizations in the temporal world, we conceive of the patience of God,
  18819. tenderly saving the turmoil of the intermediate world by the completion of
  18820. his own nature. The sheer force of things lies in the intermediate physical
  18821. process: this is the energy of physical production, God's r61e is not the
  18822. combat of productive force [526] with productive force, of destructive
  18823. force with destructive force; it lies in the patient operation of the over-
  18824. powering rationality of his conceptual harmonization. He does not create
  18825. the world, he saves it: or, more accurately, he is the poet of the world, with
  18826. tender patience leading** it by his vision of truth, beauty, and goodness.
  18827.  
  18828. SECTION V
  18829.  
  18830. The vicious separation of the flux from the permanence leads to the
  18831. concept of an entirely static God, with eminent reality, in relation to an
  18832. entirely fluent world, with deficient reality. But if the opposites, static and
  18833. fluent, have once been so explained as separately to characterize diverse
  18834. actualities, the interplay between the thing which is static and the things
  18835. which are fluent involves contradiction at every step in its explanation.
  18836. Such philosophies must include the notion of 'illusion' as a fundamental
  18837.  
  18838.  
  18839.  
  18840. 348 Final Interpretation
  18841.  
  18842. mary can [528] only be expressed in terms of a group of antitheses, whose
  18843. apparent self-contradictions depend f on neglect of the diverse categories of
  18844. existence. In each antithesis there is a shift of meaning which converts the
  18845. opposition into a contrast.
  18846.  
  18847. It is as true to say that God is permanent and the World fluent, as that
  18848. the World is permanent and God is fluent.
  18849.  
  18850. It is as true to say that God is one and the World many, as that the
  18851. World is one and God many.
  18852.  
  18853. It is as true to say that, in comparison with the World, God is actual
  18854. eminently, as that, in comparison with God, the World is actual eminently.
  18855.  
  18856. It is as true to say that the World is immanent in God, as that God is
  18857. immanent in the World.
  18858.  
  18859. It is as true to say that God transcends the World, as that the World
  18860. transcends God.
  18861.  
  18862. It is as true to say that God creates the World, as that the World
  18863. creates God.
  18864.  
  18865. God and the World are the contrasted opposites in terms of which
  18866. Creativity achieves its supreme task of transforming disjoined multiplicity,
  18867. with its diversities in opposition, into concrescent unity, with its diver-
  18868. sities in contrast. In each actuality theref are two concrescent poles of
  18869. realization— 'enjoyment' and 'appetition/ that is, the 'physical' and the
  18870. 'conceptual.' For God the conceptual is prior to the physical, for the
  18871. World the physical poles are prior to the conceptual poles.
  18872.  
  18873. A physical pole is in its own nature exclusive, bounded by contradiction:
  18874. a conceptual pole is in its own nature all-embracing, unbounded by con-
  18875. tradiction. The former derives its share of infinity from the infinity of ap-
  18876. petition; the latter derives its share of limitation from the exclusiveness of
  18877. enjoyment. Thus, by reason of his priority of appetition, there can be but
  18878. one primordial nature for God: and, by reason of their priority of enjoy-
  18879. ment, there must be one history of many actualities in the physical world.
  18880.  
  18881. [529] God and the World stand over against each other, expressing the
  18882. final metaphysical truth that appetitive vision and physical enjoyment have
  18883. equal claim to priority in creation. But no two actualities can be torn
  18884. apart: each is all in all. Thus each temporal occasion embodies God, and
  18885. is embodied in God. In God's nature, permanence is primordial and flux
  18886. is derivative from the World: in the World's nature, flux is primordial and
  18887. permanence is derivative from God. Also the World's nature is a pri-
  18888. mordial datum for God; and God's nature is a primordial datum for the
  18889. World. Creation achieves the reconciliation of permanence and flux when
  18890. it has reached its final term which is everlastingness— the Apotheosis of
  18891. the World.
  18892.  
  18893. Opposed elements stand to each other in mutual requirement. In their
  18894. unity, they inhibit or contrast. God and the World stand to each other in
  18895. this opposed requirement. God is the infinite ground of all mentality, the
  18896. unity of vision seeking physical multiplicity. The World is the multiplicity
  18897.  
  18898.  
  18899.  
  18900. 350 Final Interpretation
  18901.  
  18902. existence. The function of being a means is not disjoined from the func-
  18903. tion of being an end. The sense of worth beyond itself is immediately
  18904. enjoyed as an overpowering element in the individual self-attainment. It
  18905. is in this way that the immediacy of sorrow and pain is transformed into
  18906. an element of triumph. This is the notion of redemption through suffer-
  18907. ingf which haunts the world. It is the generalization of its very minor
  18908. exemplification as the aesthetic value of discords in art.
  18909.  
  18910. Thus the universe is to be conceived as attaining the active self-expres-
  18911. sion of its own variety of opposites— of its own freedom and its own
  18912. necessity, of its own multiplicity and its own unity, of its own imperfection
  18913. and its own perfection. All the 'opposites' are elements in the nature of
  18914. things, and are incorrigibly there. The concept of 'God' is the way in
  18915. which we understand this incredible fact— that what cannot be, yet is.
  18916.  
  18917. SECTION VII
  18918.  
  18919. Thus the consequent nature of God is composed of a multiplicity of
  18920. elements with individual self-realization. It is just as much a multiplicity
  18921. as it is a unity; it is just as much one immediate fact as it is an unresting
  18922. advance beyond itself. Thus the actuality of God must also be understood
  18923. as a multiplicity of actual components in process of creation. This is God
  18924. in his function of the kingdom of heaven.
  18925.  
  18926. Each actuality in the temporal world has its reception into God's na-
  18927. ture. The corresponding element in God's nature is not temporal ac-
  18928. tuality, but is the transmutation of that temporal actuality into a living,
  18929. ever-present fact. An enduring personality in the temporal world is a route
  18930. of occasions in which the successors with some peculiar completeness sum
  18931. up their predecessors. The correlate fact in God's nature is an even more
  18932. complete unity of life in a chain of elements for which succession does not
  18933. mean loss of immediate unison. This element in God's nature inherits
  18934. from the temporal counterpart [532] according to the same principle as in
  18935. the temporal world the future inherits from the past. Thus in the sense in
  18936. which the present occasion is the person now, and yet with his own past,
  18937. so the counterpart in God is that person in God.
  18938.  
  18939. But the principle of universal relativity is not to be stopped at the con-
  18940. sequent nature of God. This nature itself passes into the temporal world
  18941. according to its gradation of relevance to the various concrescent occasions.
  18942. There are thus four creative phases in which the universe accomplishes its
  18943. actuality. There is first the phase of conceptual origination, deficient in
  18944. actuality, but infinite in its adjustment of valuation. Secondly, there is the
  18945. temporal phase of physical origination, with its multiplicity of actualities.
  18946. In this phase full actuality is attained; but there is deficiency in the soli-
  18947. darity of individuals with each other. This phase derives its determinate
  18948. conditions from the first phase. Thirdly, there is the phase of perfected
  18949. actuality, in which the many are one everlastingly, without the qualifica-
  18950.  
  18951.  
  18952.  
  18953. 356
  18954.  
  18955.  
  18956.  
  18957. Index
  18958.  
  18959.  
  18960.  
  18961. Actual occasion (cont.)
  18962.  
  18963. tity, 18, 22, 73, 77, HI, 211; used to
  18964. stress extensiveness, 77; excludes God,
  18965. 88
  18966.  
  18967. Actual world, 4, 25, 27, 33, 46, 59, 286:
  18968. as datum, 4, 16, 65, 69, 72, 65, 87,
  18969. 154, 158, 211, 212, 230, 233, 286; and
  18970. propositions, 11, 194-95, 204, 265; as
  18971. process, 22; definition of, 23, 28, 150;
  18972. and efficient causation, 24-25, 169,
  18973. 178, 277; as determinate, 45; and God,
  18974. 47, 65, 93, 220; as relative, 59, 65-66,
  18975. 93, 210-11, 226, 284; conditions po-
  18976. tentiality, 65, 129; as atomic, 67, 286;
  18977. as nexus, 73, 77, 230, 238; as mine,
  18978. 76, 81; withness of, 81; knowledge of,
  18979. 81; order and chaos in, 86, 110-11;
  18980. givenness of, 129; as ground of proba-
  18981. bility judgments, 203; perspective of,
  18982. 210; objective immortality of, 230; inde-
  18983. termination of, 284; divisibility of, 285-
  18984. 86
  18985.  
  18986. Adaptation, 83, 107, 163
  18987.  
  18988. Adequacy, xi, xii, xiv, 3, 6, 9, 11, 13, 15,
  18989. 239, 343
  18990.  
  18991. Adventure, 9, 14, 42, 78, 80
  18992.  
  18993. Adversion and aversion (valuation up and
  18994. down), 24, 32, 184, 234, 241, 247,
  18995. 248, 254, 261, 266, 277, 278, 291,
  18996. 328, 339
  18997.  
  18998. Aesthetic, 5, 39: interests, xii; emphasis,
  18999. 102; experience, 62, 183, 185, 212,
  19000. 279; supplement, 213; harmony, cate-
  19001. gory of, 255; fact, 279; laws, 280; cul-
  19002. ture, 337; gods, 340
  19003.  
  19004. Affirmation, 191, 243, 270, 273-74
  19005.  
  19006. Affirmation- negation contrast, 24, 243,
  19007. 256, 261, 267
  19008.  
  19009. Aggregates, 173, 286
  19010.  
  19011. Aim: at unity, 224; at contrast, 249;
  19012. private, 290. See also Initial aim; Sub-
  19013. jective aim
  19014.  
  19015. Alexander, Samuel, 28, 41
  19016.  
  19017. Algebra, 332
  19018.  
  19019. All, 208
  19020.  
  19021. All things flow, 208
  19022.  
  19023. Alternation, 187
  19024.  
  19025. Alternatives, II, 148, 161, 249, 278
  19026.  
  19027. Analogous occasions, 99, 250, 251-53
  19028.  
  19029. Analogy: and probability, induction, 49,
  19030. 201, 204, 205, 206-07; and congruence,
  19031. 97, 331, 333
  19032.  
  19033. Analysis, 4, 19, 22, 23, 51, 153, 160, 166,
  19034. 211, 235. See also Division
  19035.  
  19036.  
  19037.  
  19038. Animal body, 106: in perception, 63, 1 18—
  19039. 19, 169-70, 178-79, 311, 315; as part
  19040. of environment, 64, 76, 119, 170, 234;
  19041. theory of, 103; cell as, 103, 104; life of,
  19042. 108; order of, 180, 339. See also Body;
  19043. Bodily
  19044.  
  19045. Animal faith, 48, 52, 54, 81, 142, 152
  19046.  
  19047. Animals, 107, 181
  19048.  
  19049. Anticipation, 27, 179, 204, 205, 278
  19050.  
  19051. Antitheses, 348
  19052.  
  19053. Any, 114, 162, 256, 257, 261
  19054.  
  19055. Appearance: mere, 18, 54, 152, 229, 347;
  19056. world as, 49; and reality, 72
  19057.  
  19058. Appetition, 32-33, 51, 72, 83, 102, 150,
  19059. 154, 163, 184, 212, 341, 348: in God,
  19060. 48, 105, 207, 316, 347, 348
  19061.  
  19062. Applicability, 3, 5, 6, 8, 9, 10, 14, 20, 93
  19063.  
  19064. Appreciation, 27, 47, 85, 212, 213, 311,
  19065. 327
  19066.  
  19067. A priori figleaf, 146
  19068.  
  19069. Aquinas, Thomas, 11, 108
  19070.  
  19071. Arbitrariness, 6, 7, 71, 91
  19072.  
  19073. Aristotelian: (primary) substance, xiii, 21,
  19074. 30, 50, 59, 79, 138, 157, 158; matter
  19075. (primary substance) and creativity, 21,
  19076. 31; substantial form. 34
  19077.  
  19078. Aristotle, 10, 39: influence of, xi, 51, 84,
  19079. 159; and Aristotelian logic, 30, 51, 209;
  19080. and substance-quality (subject-predicate)
  19081. thought, 30, 137, 2Q9; and ontological
  19082. principle, 40; and entities present in
  19083. others, 50; and final causes, 84; and
  19084. forms, 96; and fluency, 209; and
  19085. Platonism, 209; on generation, 209;
  19086. and quantity, 332; and golden mean,
  19087. 339; on God, 342, 343, 344
  19088.  
  19089. Arithmetic, as metaphysical, 198-99
  19090.  
  19091. Art, 9, 162-63 228, 280, 317, 339, 350:
  19092. and God, 189; and morality, 317
  19093.  
  19094. Asiatic thought, 7
  19095.  
  19096. Association, 129, 175, 299
  19097.  
  19098. Ate, goddess of mischief, 244, 351
  19099.  
  19100. Atomicity, atomism, 27, 117, 235, 237:
  19101. and final causation, 19; and continuity,
  19102. extension, 36, 67, 72, 73, 123, 292; of
  19103. actuality, 35-36, 45, 61, 62, 77, HO,
  19104. 227, 235, 286, 307; of quantum theory,
  19105. 238, 309; and Zeno, 307
  19106.  
  19107. Atoms, 78, 95, 286, 333n
  19108.  
  19109. Attribute, 40, 77, 78, 159, 288, 309
  19110.  
  19111. Augustine, 14
  19112.  
  19113. Authentic perceptive feelings, 262, 264,
  19114. 269, 270 1
  19115.  
  19116. Authority, 39
  19117.  
  19118.  
  19119.  
  19120. 358
  19121.  
  19122.  
  19123.  
  19124. Index
  19125.  
  19126.  
  19127.  
  19128. Change (cont.)
  19129.  
  19130. ventures of, 35, 55; meaning of, 73,
  19131. 79, 80; of molecule, 80; in Cartesian-
  19132. ism, 144; always obtains, 238; and
  19133. order, 339. See also Motion
  19134.  
  19135. Chaos: as non-social nexus, 72; absolute,
  19136. 92; creation out of, 95-96, 199; pure,
  19137. 111; borders of, 111; and triviality, 110,
  19138. 199; not evil, 112; of diverse epochs,
  19139. 112; zero, 115; arithmetic in, 199;
  19140. occasions in, 199; of data, 248. See also
  19141. Disorder
  19142.  
  19143. Chemical, 95, 106
  19144.  
  19145. Christianity, 342-43, 347
  19146.  
  19147. Civilization, xi, 9, 17, 337, 340
  19148.  
  19149. Clarity and distinctness, 8, 162, 173-74,
  19150. 236
  19151.  
  19152. Class, 46, 89, 228, 229
  19153.  
  19154. Coalescence, 26, 225
  19155.  
  19156. Cogredience, 125
  19157.  
  19158. Coherence: as ideal, 3, 5, 6, 128, 225,
  19159. 257, 349; theory, 190-91, 271; in
  19160. actual entity, 224, 226
  19161.  
  19162. Coincidence, 328, 333
  19163.  
  19164. Colours, 44, 61, 64, 78, 162, 194, 326,
  19165. 327
  19166.  
  19167. Common sense: repressive, 9; and spe-
  19168. cialism, imagination, 17; on experience,
  19169. 50; Locke's expression of, 51, 52; no-
  19170. tions presupposed by, 52, 128, 129; on
  19171. space and time, 70, 72; objectivism of,
  19172. 72, 144, 158, 160; on knowledge in
  19173. experience, 161; on cause of sensa, 171;
  19174. on presentational immediacy, 311, 324
  19175.  
  19176. Communication, 4
  19177.  
  19178. Comparative feelings, 254, 266, 270, 275-
  19179. 76
  19180.  
  19181. Comparison, 146, 164, 166
  19182.  
  19183. Compatibility: and contrariety, 148; for
  19184. synthesis, 148, 154, 223, 224, 240;
  19185. judgment of, 274
  19186.  
  19187. Complete locus, 307
  19188.  
  19189. Complexity, 8, 80, 161, 227, 246: and
  19190. atomism, 36; and intensity, 100, 279;
  19191. of givenness and order, 100; and sim-
  19192. plicity, 133; and knowledge, 161; of
  19193. universe, 166; of data, 232; and auton-
  19194. omy, 255; definition of, 278
  19195.  
  19196. Composition, 58, 147
  19197.  
  19198. Compulsion, 175
  19199.  
  19200. Concavity and convexity, 307
  19201.  
  19202. Concept of Nature, The, 125«, 128n,
  19203. 243n, 287n
  19204.  
  19205. Concepts, 16, 55, 194, 242
  19206.  
  19207.  
  19208.  
  19209. Conceptual analysis, 247
  19210.  
  19211. Conceptual imagination, 248
  19212.  
  19213. Conceptualism, 40
  19214.  
  19215. Conceptual origination, 247
  19216.  
  19217. Conceptual Pole. See Mental pole
  19218.  
  19219. Conceptual prehension (feeling, valua-
  19220. tion, reproduction, registration, recog-
  19221. nition), 32-34, 44, 45, 49, 87, 164-65,
  19222. 189, 214, 239, 240-43, 248: definition
  19223. of, 23, 184, 232, 239, 240, 243; cate-
  19224. gory of, 26, 33, 53, 101, 225, 246,
  19225. 248-49, 250, 251-52, 254, 260, 271,
  19226. 276, 277, 316; derived from physical
  19227. feelings, 26, 247, 250, 260; mutual de-
  19228. termination (sensitivity) of, 27, 221,
  19229. 235, 344; unconditioned, complete, 31,
  19230. 32-34, 247, 344, 345; as appetition,
  19231. 32, 33, 184, 341; connotations of, 33;
  19232. pure and impure, 63, 184, 241, 313;
  19233. originality in, 102, 105; negligible, 115;
  19234. and Humian impressions, 160-63;
  19235. blind, 161, 214, 241, 247, 343-44; and
  19236. internal determination, 164; conscious-
  19237. ness not necessary for, 165, 241, 344:
  19238. as source of emotion, 212; of subjective
  19239. aim, 224; basic, 224, 244; 256; objecti-
  19240. fi cation by, 225; negative, 226-27, 240;
  19241. as primary feelings, 232, 239; as primary
  19242. mental operations, 239, 240; as feelings
  19243. of negation, 243; novel, 244-45; derived
  19244. from other conceptual feelings, 247,
  19245. 248, 254 (see also Reversion); as pur-
  19246. posive, 254; efficacy of, 254; and actual
  19247. world, 256; generality of datum, 257,
  19248. 275; concerns entire region, 285. See
  19249. also Mental prehension; Valuation
  19250.  
  19251. Concern. 55
  19252.  
  19253. Concordance, 252
  19254.  
  19255. Concrescence, 7, 26, 41-42, 49, 84, 108,
  19256. 219, 220, 224-25, 232, 283, 316: as
  19257. production of novel togetherness, 21;
  19258. components of, 21, 47, 84; actual
  19259. entity as, 22, 211, 212; eliminates inde-
  19260. termination, 23, 85, 88; and final causa-
  19261. tion, 24, 210; pre-established harmony
  19262. of, 27; freedom of, 47-48; as indi-
  19263. vidualization of universe, 51, 165, 316;
  19264. and subjective aim, 69, 87, 167, 245;
  19265. absorbs data into privacy, 85; responsi-
  19266. bility of, 88; as process of addition,
  19267. 151; as selective, 153-54; problem for,
  19268. 154, 283; cosmology in description of,
  19269. 167; one kind of fluency, 210; cate-
  19270. goreal demands of, 237; dipolarity of,
  19271.  
  19272.  
  19273.  
  19274. 360
  19275.  
  19276.  
  19277.  
  19278. Index
  19279.  
  19280.  
  19281.  
  19282. Cosmic epoch (cont.)
  19283. ing characteristic of, 293, 332; straight
  19284. and flat "loci in, 310; strain-loci in, 322
  19285.  
  19286. Cosmological argument, 93
  19287.  
  19288. Cosmology: motives of, xi; satisfactory,
  19289. xii, 128, 143, 290, 316; seventeenth-
  19290. century, xiv; Plato's, xiv, 93, 94; one-
  19291. substance, 19, 110; monadic, 27; and
  19292. unique seriality, 35; speculations of, 71
  19293. and arbitrary factors in geometry, 91
  19294. Newton's, 93, 94; general doctrine of
  19295. 94; of philosophy of organism, 103
  19296. three misconceptions hampering, 156
  19297. and concrescence, 167; Kant's, 190
  19298. based on simple physical feelings, 238
  19299. and physical purposes, 276; and vacuous
  19300. actuality, 309; and scientific theory,
  19301. 323; last chapter of, 341; interpretation
  19302. in, 341; as basis of religion, 349
  19303.  
  19304. Counting and measurement, 327
  19305.  
  19306. Creation, 85, 95-96, 223, 341, 348, 349
  19307.  
  19308. Creative act, 245, 247, 250
  19309.  
  19310. Creative advance, xiv, 21, 28, 45, 227, 277,
  19311. 346: into novelty, 35, 128, 222, 349;
  19312. God's purpose in, 105; propositions
  19313. grow with, 188, 259; nexus not de-
  19314. stroyed in, 238; general notion of, 289;
  19315. relation of nature as extensive com-
  19316. munity to, 289; metaphysical character
  19317. of, 344; re-establishes itself, 347
  19318.  
  19319. Creativity: as ultimate, 7, 20; as inexplica-
  19320. ble by forms, 20; as conditioned (char-
  19321. acterized, qualified) by actuality, 20,
  19322. 29, 43, 84, 85, 87-88, 108, 164, 220,
  19323. 222, 225, 237, 244; universal of uni-
  19324. versals, 21; as principle of novelty, 21;
  19325. discussion of, 21; transcendence of,
  19326. 26, 43, 85, 87, 102, 237, 280; defini-
  19327. tion of, 31-32; God and, 88, 225, 244,
  19328. 344; as universal throughout actuality,
  19329. 164; as fundamental fact, 211; transi-
  19330. tion as, 211; as passing on, 213; as
  19331. abstract possibility, 220; not an external
  19332. agency, 222; meaningless without crea-
  19333. tures, 225; new impersonation of, 237;
  19334. transition of, 244; effect of adversion
  19335. and aversion on, 277; has character of
  19336. final and efficient causation, 277; su-
  19337. preme task of, 348
  19338.  
  19339. Creatures, 20, 22, 32, 69, 80, 225, 227,
  19340. 255, 345, 351
  19341.  
  19342. Critical judgment, 178
  19343.  
  19344. Critical philosophy, 50, 173, 174, 175
  19345.  
  19346. Criticism, 10, 151, 268
  19347.  
  19348.  
  19349.  
  19350. Critique of pure feeling, 113
  19351. Cumulation, 237, 238
  19352. Custom, 326
  19353.  
  19354. Daily life, 156, 174
  19355.  
  19356. Datum (data), 23, 47, 52, 58, 86, 106,
  19357. 165, 203, 224, 230-31, 248: and pri-
  19358. mary phase, 16, 104, 144, 154-55, 206;
  19359. objectivity of, 40; primary, 44, 49, 159;
  19360. as potentiality, 65, 113; as absorbed into
  19361. subject, 85, 153, 154, 164; order in,
  19362. 100, 106, 113; inherited from past,
  19363. 104, 116; limits and supplies, 110; and
  19364. freedom, 110, 115, 203; character of,
  19365. 110, 157; vector character of, 116, 117,
  19366. 120; includes bodily organs, 117-19;
  19367. analytic consciousness of, 120; intui-
  19368. tions as, 142; as decisions received,
  19369. 149-50; as objective content, 150, 152;
  19370. found in past, 150, 233; involves actual
  19371. entities (world), 153, 154, 211, 224,
  19372. 233, 235; as perspective, 154; com-
  19373. plexity of, 153, 185, 246; as universal,
  19374. 159; modification of, 164; dead, 164;
  19375. as environment under abstraction, 203;
  19376. finitude of relevant, 206; as in being,
  19377. 233; as public side of prehension, 290.
  19378. See also Initial datum; Objective datum
  19379.  
  19380. Dead, appropriation of, xiii
  19381.  
  19382. Decay, 188
  19383.  
  19384. Decision, 43: of subject-superject, 28;
  19385. meaning of, 43; as meaning of actuality,
  19386. 43; as basis of givenness, 43, 47, 62;
  19387. as basis of explanation, 46; and onto-
  19388. logical principle, 46; as modification
  19389. of subjective aim, 47; God's, 47, 164;
  19390. satisfaction as, 60; transcendent, 150.
  19391. 164; transmitted, 150, 154; received,
  19392. 150, 277, 284; immanent (immedi-
  19393. ate), 163-64, 284; successive, 224; and
  19394. indeterminations in initial aim, 224;
  19395. adversion and aversion as, 254; in sub-
  19396. jective aim, 277; and freedom, 284;
  19397. relevance to contemporaries, 318
  19398.  
  19399. Deduction, 8, 10, 343
  19400.  
  19401. Definiteness: of experience, 4, 29, 240;
  19402. of statement, 9; forms (potentialities,
  19403. universal) of, 14, 20, 22, 34, 40, 158;
  19404. definition of, 25; as exclusive limitation,
  19405. 45, 240; as final cause, 223; private, 290
  19406.  
  19407. Definition: of constructs, 3; of proposi-
  19408. tions, II; of verbal expressions, 13; as
  19409. soul of actuality, 223
  19410.  
  19411. Deity, divine, 40, 93, 94, 343
  19412.  
  19413.  
  19414.  
  19415. 362
  19416.  
  19417.  
  19418.  
  19419. Index
  19420.  
  19421.  
  19422.  
  19423. Emotion (cont)
  19424.  
  19425. fied, 28, 106; transmission of, 114, 115;
  19426. sensa as definiteness of, 114; quantita-
  19427. tive, 116, 233-35; and sensation, 115,
  19428. 141, 162; and physical energy, 116,
  19429. 315; pulses (throbs) of, 116, 163, 327;
  19430. blind, 162-63; as public and private,
  19431. 212-13, 290; and struggle for existence,
  19432. 226; qualitative, 233-34; pattern of,
  19433. 237, 273, 275
  19434.  
  19435. Emphasis, 47, 48, 102, 108, 110, 146,
  19436. 163, 313
  19437.  
  19438. Empiricism, 285: one side of philosophy,
  19439. 3-4; Lockian, Humian, sensationalist,
  19440. 50, 57, 145, 151, 153, 167, 171, 174,
  19441. 316; ultimate ground of, 256
  19442.  
  19443. Empty space: actual occasions in, 56, 92,
  19444. 99, 177, 199, 314, 319; and material
  19445. ether, 78; within cell, 99, 105, 106; and
  19446. strains, strain-loci, 311, 319; and rest,
  19447. 319; and presentational immediacy,
  19448. 321; in brain, 339
  19449.  
  19450. End(s), 40, 83, 222, 224, 339, 349-50
  19451.  
  19452. Endurance: and Zeno, 68-69; undifferen-
  19453. tiated, 77-79, 187; as repetition, 104,
  19454. 128, 136-37: and rhythm, vibration,
  19455. 279; passive, 309
  19456.  
  19457. Enduring: substance, 79; soul, 104; per-
  19458. sonality, 119, 350-51; percipient, 270
  19459.  
  19460. Enduring objects, 99: definition of, 34-
  19461. 35, 109, 161; self-identity of, 55; rele-
  19462. vance of power to, 56; distinct from
  19463. other societies, actual entities, 72; as
  19464. referent of personal pronoun, 75; elec-
  19465. trons as, 92, 326; humans as, 92, 161;
  19466. as restricted corpuscular society, 92,
  19467. 104; molecule as, 99, 326; living, 107,
  19468. 109, 177; transition of matter or char-
  19469. acter, 109; with consciousness, knowl-
  19470. edge, 161, 177, 270; inorganic, non-
  19471. living, 173, 177; subjective aims or
  19472. physical purposes in, 187-88, 276, 279;
  19473. simple, 198; intersection of, 199; and
  19474. strains, 311; contemporary occasions of,
  19475. 318; and strain-locus, 319; and pre-
  19476. sented duration, 321; protons as, 326;
  19477. material bodies as, 326
  19478.  
  19479. Energy: radiant, 109; forms of, 116, 120,
  19480. 239, 254; and emotion, 116, 315;
  19481. transference of, 116-17, 238-39, 246;
  19482. vector marks of, 117; quantity of, 117,
  19483. 238-39; origination of, 246, 285: physi-
  19484. cal theory of, 254; complexity deter-
  19485.  
  19486.  
  19487.  
  19488. mines degree of, 255; fluent, 309; struc-
  19489. ture of, 309
  19490.  
  19491. Enjoyment, 9, 41, 49, 51, 85, 159, 166,
  19492. 178, 262, 289, 340, 348, 350
  19493.  
  19494. Entirely living nexus, 103-5, 107
  19495.  
  19496. Entity (-ies ) : cannot be considered in iso-
  19497. lation, 3, 28; synonymous with being,
  19498. thing, 21, 211; and categories of exis-
  19499. tence, 20; meaning of, 28, 43, 211, 243,
  19500. 224; use of term, 30; proper, 30, 247,
  19501. 224, 228; as felt by actualities, 41;
  19502. self -identity of, 57, 225; two primary
  19503. types of, 188; two pure types of, 188;
  19504. impure types of, 188; two hybrid types
  19505. of, 188-89; four main types of, 188;
  19506. originating in concrescence, 211; not
  19507. abstractable from creativity, 213, 243;
  19508. categoreal types of, 219; objective func-
  19509. tioning of, 222-23; temporal, 276. See
  19510. also Actual entity; Thing
  19511.  
  19512. Environment, 89, 90, 99, 110, 203-06,
  19513. 207, 234, 254, 264-65
  19514.  
  19515. Envisagement, 34, 44, 189
  19516.  
  19517. Epiphenomenal, 292
  19518.  
  19519. Epistemology, xii, 48-50, 52, 54, 73, 117
  19520.  
  19521. Epochal theory of time, 68, 283
  19522.  
  19523. Epochs, historical, 14, 15, 17, 338, 339,
  19524. 340. See also Cosmic epoch
  19525.  
  19526. Equations, 311
  19527.  
  19528. Error: logical, 30; in higher organisms,
  19529. 113, 168; and theory, 161; impossible
  19530. in pure perceptive modes, 168; in sym-
  19531. bolic reference, 168, 172, 183; and
  19532. progress, 168, 187; arising below con-
  19533. sciousness, 180, 271-72; God as source
  19534. of, 189; in derivative judgment, 192;
  19535. colour-blindness as, 253; some novelty
  19536. in, 253; in conscious perceptions, 262,
  19537. 268, 269; consciousness of, 270
  19538.  
  19539. Essence: of actual entity, 41; Critical
  19540. Realists' use of, 44; real, 53, 59-60,
  19541. 193; nominal, 60; abstract, 60; of
  19542. eternal objects, 115, 165, 315; specific,
  19543. 148
  19544.  
  19545. Eternal, 40, 189, 248, 345, 347
  19546.  
  19547. Eternal object (s), 40: as (pure) potential
  19548. (for ingression), 22, 23, 40, 44, 164,
  19549. 184, 188, 214, 239, 290; as forms
  19550. (determinants) of definiteness, 22, 23,
  19551. 26, 40, 149, 154, 158, 227, 238, 239,
  19552. 240, 241, 291, 312; as ultimate ele-
  19553. ments. 22. 219: no novel. 22; ingression
  19554. of, 23, 31, 41, 45, 52, 59, 64, 86, 114,
  19555.  
  19556.  
  19557.  
  19558. 364
  19559.  
  19560.  
  19561.  
  19562. Index
  19563.  
  19564.  
  19565.  
  19566. Experience (cont.)
  19567.  
  19568. 143, 167; obvious facts of, 145; naked
  19569. and unashamed, 146; as primary meta-
  19570. physical fact, 160; topsy-turvy explana-
  19571. tion of, 162; purposeful, 162, 163;
  19572. emotional, 162-63; and everlastingness,
  19573. 163; nothing apart from, 167; blind,
  19574. 178; of being one among others, 178;
  19575. togetherness in, 189-90; occasion of,
  19576. 189, 190; stream of, 189, 190; throb
  19577. of, 190; concordant, 206; integral, 208;
  19578. elucidation of, 208; ultimate, 208; of
  19579. future, 215; complexity of, 267; objec-
  19580. tive and subjective sides of, 277;
  19581. aesthetic, 280; depth of, 318; direct,
  19582.  
  19583. 16, 324-25
  19584.  
  19585. Explanation, 7, 96: as explaining away,
  19586.  
  19587. 17, 145; of abstract from concrete, 20;
  19588. categories of, 20, 22-26, 28, 166; and
  19589. decision, 46; based on vera causa, 77-
  19590. 78; scientific, 77-78, 324; philosophi-
  19591. cal, 129, 250; elements in, 153; as ana-
  19592. lysis of coordination, 153; make-believe,
  19593. 201
  19594.  
  19595. Expression, 96, 209
  19596.  
  19597. Extension, lower limit to, 206
  19598.  
  19599. Extensive abstraction, 97, 287
  19600.  
  19601. Extensive connection, 294-301: defining
  19602. characteristic of extensive continuum,
  19603. 97-98; and perception, 168-69; one
  19604. scheme of, 286-87; as starting-point,
  19605. 287; sui generis, 288; formal properties
  19606. of, 288; primary relationship of physical
  19607. world, 288-89; elimination of atomicity
  19608. in, 292
  19609.  
  19610. Extensive continuum, xii, 61-82: Des-
  19611. cartes and Newton on, xii, 76; not in-
  19612. volve continuity of becoming, 35; as
  19613. datum, 62, 72-73, 76, 123; as real
  19614. potentiality, 62, 66, 67, 76; not prior to
  19615. world, 66; underlies whole world, 66,
  19616. 72; exemplified in all actualities, 67; as
  19617. basic limitation on abstract potentiality,
  19618. 80; as physical field, 80; quantum of,
  19619. 80; defining characteristic of, 97; atomi-
  19620. zation of, 123, 124, 128; reason for
  19621. careful discussion of, 167; limitation to
  19622. finite region of, 206; standpoint in,
  19623. 283; as order of this epoch, 293; based
  19624. on divisibility of physical pole, 308;
  19625. systematic structure of, 325; measure-
  19626. ment possible throughout, 332
  19627.  
  19628. Extensiveness: spatial and temporal, 61,
  19629. 77, 80, 238, 283, 301; aboriginal poten-
  19630. tiality of, 62; of actual entities, 77; as
  19631.  
  19632.  
  19633.  
  19634. basic fact, 91; grades of specialization
  19635. of, 91, 92; due to divisibility of satis-
  19636. faction, 69, 221; as indefinite divisi-
  19637. bility, 285; as pervading generic form,
  19638. 287; derivation of, 287; of present
  19639. cosmic epoch, 326
  19640. Extensive order, 286
  19641. Extensive perspective, 58
  19642. Extensive quantity, 97, 332, 333
  19643. Extensive quantum, 283, 284, 307
  19644. Extensive region, 168-70, 301, 310
  19645. Extensive relationships: knowledge of, 61,
  19646. 122; as fundamental, 67, 288; external,
  19647. 286, 287, 309; internal, 286, 309; as
  19648. condition of transmission, 288; Des-
  19649. cartes and Locke on, 288, 326; perma-
  19650. nence of, 327-28
  19651. Extensive scheme, 288, 318
  19652. Extensive society, 96-97
  19653. Extensive whole and part, 287, 288
  19654. External world, 54-56, 62, 63, 116, 117,
  19655. 120, 140, 156, 158, 171, 176, 206,
  19656. 234, 313, 314, 321, 333
  19657. Ezekiel, 85
  19658.  
  19659.  
  19660.  
  19661. Fact(s), 6,9, 11, 12, 13, 15, 17, 20, 39-
  19662. 40, 42, 46, 51, 96, 129, 161-62, 188,
  19663. 219, 220, 276, 290, 338, 343
  19664.  
  19665. False propositions, 184-85, 186
  19666.  
  19667. Fatigue, tedium, 16, 239, 339
  19668.  
  19669. Feeler, 88, 222, 237
  19670.  
  19671. Feeling (s) : Bradley's doctrine of, xiii;
  19672. definition of, 23, 40-42; and Lockian
  19673. ideas, 25, 51-53; as positive prehen-
  19674. sions, 26, 40-42, 142, 221; integration
  19675. of, 26, 232: mutual sensitivity (determi-
  19676. nation) of, 27, 192, 221/223, 235,
  19677. 275, 344; intensity of, 27, 277-78;
  19678. Descartes' use of, 41; of actual entities,
  19679. 49, 211, 230; vector character of, 55,
  19680. 87, 119, 231; of bodily actualities, 75,
  19681. 81; tone of, 85, 119, 120, 308; self-
  19682. definition of, 85-86; subjective forms
  19683. of, 85, 88, 211, 221, 232; aptness for,
  19684. 87; between data and feeler, 88; nar-
  19685. rowness and width of, 110-12; con-
  19686. formity of, 113; quantitative, 116; spe-
  19687. cific forms of, 116; intensity of, 118,
  19688. 244; visceral and visual, 121; common
  19689. sense requires, 128; give immediacy,
  19690. 136, 155; compatibility of, 148, 223;
  19691. blind, 161, 162, 163, 214; aesthetic,
  19692. 162; use of term, 164, 211; successive
  19693.  
  19694. - phases of, 164, 165-66; hierarchy of,
  19695.  
  19696.  
  19697.  
  19698. 366
  19699.  
  19700.  
  19701.  
  19702. Index
  19703.  
  19704.  
  19705.  
  19706. God, 343-51: as non- temporal, 7, 40, 46;
  19707. and ultimate, 7; and creativity, 7, 88,
  19708. 222, 225, 348-49; actual entity, 18, 40,
  19709. 46, 65, 87, 94, 110, 164, 244; and
  19710. reasons of highest absoluteness, 19; and
  19711. ontological principle, 19; objectification
  19712. (prehension) of, 31, 189, 207, 225,
  19713. 246, 316, 348; objective immortality
  19714. of, 32; reason for name, 31-32; and
  19715. religion, 31-32, 189, 207; satisfaction
  19716. of, 32, 88: originates from mental pole,
  19717. 36, 75, 87, 224, 345, 348; mediates
  19718. between actuality and potentiality, 40,
  19719. 49; as creator, 47, 225, 346, 348; of
  19720. theologians, 47; and knowledge, 49,
  19721. 144, 190; goodness of, 49, 345; power
  19722. of, 49, 346; as included in actual world,
  19723. 65, 220; as source of novelty, 67, 88,
  19724. 108, 164, 247, 349; Descartes on, 74-
  19725. 75, 144, 158; compared with occasions,
  19726. 75, 87, 88, 110, 224; has no past, 87;
  19727. threefold character of, 87-88; aim (pur-
  19728. pose) of, 88, 100, 105, 345; source of
  19729. order, 88, 108, 244, 247, 347: as self-
  19730. causing, 88, 222; and terms actual
  19731. entity and occasion, 88; as individual
  19732. for own sake, 88; super jective nature
  19733. of, 88; as transcended, 88, 222, 348;
  19734. transcendence of, 88, 93, 95, 164, 348;
  19735. as eternal, 93, 345, 349; immanence of,
  19736. 93, 111, 348; tenderness of, 105, 346;
  19737. fulfillment of, 105; source of initial aim,
  19738. 108, 224, 244, 283; as principle of con-
  19739. cretion (limitation), 164, 244; decision
  19740. of, 164; as macroscopic res vera, 167;
  19741. and ethics, art, error, 189; secularization
  19742. of, 207; permanence of, 208, 346-48;
  19743. relevance to conceptual valuations, 225,
  19744. 244; as creator, 225, 342; analogy to
  19745. Greek and Buddhist thought of, 244;
  19746. as goddess of mischief, 244, 351; func-
  19747. tions of, 207, 244, 350; intervention
  19748. of, 247; eternal objects not created by,
  19749. 257; source of physical law, 283; as
  19750. modifying agency, 325; interpretation
  19751. in doctrine of world and, 341
  19752.  
  19753. — consequent nature of, 343-51: and
  19754. truth, 12; growth of, 12, 346; impar-
  19755. tiality of, 13; results from prehensions
  19756. of world, 31, 345, 347; objective im-
  19757. mortality of, 32, 351; harmonious, 88,
  19758. 349; intensity of, 88; as locus of im-
  19759. partial nexus, 231
  19760.  
  19761. — primordial nature of, 343-51: non-
  19762.  
  19763.  
  19764.  
  19765. temporal, 7, 31, 46; relation to crea-
  19766. tivity, 7, 32, 105, 225, 344; completion
  19767. of, 13, 345, 347; as eternal, 13, 345;
  19768. conceptual, 13, 31, 87, 207, 343; crea-
  19769. ture, 31; source of order, 32, 107; im-
  19770. manence of, 32; efficacious, 32, 349;
  19771. deficient in actuality, 34, 343-44, 345,
  19772. 349, 350; and actual world, 44, 47, 105,
  19773. 344; eternal objects subsist in, 46;
  19774. standard of intensity, 47; as macro-
  19775. scopic fact. 47; freedom of, 47-48,
  19776. 344, 345; lure for feeling, source of
  19777. initial aim, 67, 189, 344; subjective
  19778. form of prehensions of, 88; seeks inten-
  19779. sity, 105; basis of relevance of eternal
  19780. objects, 108, 257, 278, 344, 349; pre-
  19781. hension of, 207
  19782.  
  19783. Good, 15, 33, 105, 338, 339, 346
  19784.  
  19785. Greatness, 337, 341
  19786.  
  19787. Habit, 140, 175
  19788.  
  19789. Hallucination, 324
  19790.  
  19791. Harmony: of thought, percepta, and sub-
  19792. jective forms, 16; pre-established, 48,
  19793. 255; ideal of, 102; requirements of,
  19794. 111, 112; complex structure of, 340
  19795.  
  19796. Hebrew, 208, 343, 347
  19797.  
  19798. Hegel(ian), 11, 113, 166, 167, 210
  19799.  
  19800. Heraclitus, 208, 309
  19801.  
  19802. Hierarchy: of societies, 96-109, 192; of
  19803. categories of feeling and thought, 166;
  19804. patience for, 192
  19805.  
  19806. High-grade, 222, 254, 314, 315, 318
  19807.  
  19808. Historic route (individuality), 56, 119,
  19809. 161, 188
  19810.  
  19811. History, 10, 46-48, 111, 167, 227
  19812.  
  19813. Hold u P> 280
  19814.  
  19815. Homology, 127-28
  19816.  
  19817. Human body: and rest of universe, 118-
  19818. 19; as amplifier, 119; as involved in
  19819. experience, 122, 129, 234; and pre-
  19820. sented locus, 126-28; as an actuality,
  19821. 287. See also Animal body; Body
  19822.  
  19823. Hume, xi, 11, 39, 83, 91: on ideas of
  19824. reflection, 40, 86-87, 160; skepticism
  19825. of, 48-49, 51, 140; on impressions of
  19826. sensation, 49, 86-87, 157, 159-60, 162,
  19827. 242, 248, 315-16; on mind as pro-
  19828. cess, 49, 54, 139-41, 151, 210; and
  19829. Locke, 51 , 73, 11 3, 128, 138-39, 147;
  19830. retains medieval assumptions, 51, 130,
  19831. 141; retains subject-predicate categories,
  19832. 51, 138, 159-60; on substantial form,
  19833. 55; on causation, 57, 84, 123, 124,
  19834.  
  19835.  
  19836.  
  19837. 368
  19838.  
  19839.  
  19840.  
  19841. Index
  19842.  
  19843.  
  19844.  
  19845. Indetermination(s) : as conditioned po-
  19846. tentiality, 23; of eternal objects, 29, 44,
  19847. 45, 149, 184, 256-57, 2*58; elimina-
  19848. tion of, 45, 149, 154, 212, 224, 232;
  19849. of transition, 207
  19850.  
  19851. Indication, theory of, 194-97
  19852.  
  19853. Indicative feeling, 258, 260, 261, 263,
  19854. 264, 266, 269, 270, 271, 272, 274
  19855.  
  19856. Indicative system, 194-95
  19857.  
  19858. Indirect perceptive feelings, 262, 268, 269,
  19859. 272
  19860.  
  19861. Individual actuality (unity of experience),
  19862. 15, 129, 198,211,245, 309, 318-19
  19863.  
  19864. Individuality, 45, 84, 152, 154, 289, 309
  19865.  
  19866. Individualization, 55-56, 115, 154, 225
  19867.  
  19868. Induction, Inductive judgment, 5, 83,
  19869. 199, 201, 203, 204-05, 207. See also
  19870. Probability
  19871.  
  19872. Inert facts, 310
  19873.  
  19874. Inertia, 177
  19875.  
  19876. Inference, 3, 49, 64, 272, 274
  19877.  
  19878. Infinitesimals, 328, 332-33
  19879.  
  19880. Infinity, 202-03, 206, 247
  19881.  
  19882. Ingression, 29, 40, 41, 44, 52, 59, 64,
  19883. 155, 233: definition of, 23, 25; requires
  19884. objectification, 149; as evocation of
  19885. determination, 149; and Locke's first
  19886. use of idea, 149; positive and negative,
  19887. 290; potential, 290-91; three primary
  19888. modes of, 290-91; restricted and unre-
  19889. stricted, 291
  19890.  
  19891. Inherence: of quality in substance, 29, 78,
  19892. 145, 158, 167, 232, 315; of subject in
  19893. process, 224; of subjective form in feel-
  19894. ing, 232; of quality in nexus, 315
  19895.  
  19896. Inheritance: of defining characteristic, 34,
  19897. 89; bodily, 109, 179; direct perception
  19898. as, 119; intuition of, 167; physical and
  19899. physiological, 171, 180; route of, 180,
  19900. 181, 279; of initial aim, 244
  19901.  
  19902. Inhibition, 90, 109, 163, 213, 223, 237,
  19903. 263
  19904.  
  19905. Initial aim (basic conceptual aim, initial
  19906. subjective aim): towards depth, 105;
  19907. inherited from God, 108, 224, 244,
  19908. 283; determines endurance, 128; simpli-
  19909. fication, modification of, 224, 245; con-
  19910. ditional alternatives in, 224; relevant to
  19911. actual world, 225; best for that im-
  19912. passe, 244; determines initial relevance
  19913. of eternal objects, 244; constitutes pri-
  19914. mary phase of subject, 244; basis of
  19915. self-causation, 244-45
  19916.  
  19917.  
  19918.  
  19919. Initial datum(-a), 152, 221, 231, 232,
  19920. 237, 238, 240, 241: as multiplicity, 30,
  19921. 221, 230; treatment of, 224; diverse
  19922. objectifications of, 226; of primary feel-
  19923. ings, 231; complexity of, 232; actual
  19924. entity as, 236; as cause, 236; actual
  19925. world as, 286. See also Datum
  19926.  
  19927. Initiative, 102. See also Originality; Origi-
  19928. nation
  19929.  
  19930. Inorganic, 98, 102, 103, 106, 177, 188
  19931.  
  19932. Insight, 4, 9, 15
  19933.  
  19934. Impectio, 49, 64, 76, 97, 325
  19935.  
  19936. Instability, 106
  19937.  
  19938. Instances, 194
  19939.  
  19940. Instant, 68
  19941.  
  19942. Integral feeling, 311
  19943.  
  19944. Integration, 26, 56, 69, 180, 211, 223,
  19945. 226, 232, 235, 245, 283: of physical
  19946. and conceptual prehensions, 58, 108,
  19947. 162, 164, 184, 214, 240-41, 248; initia-
  19948. tive in, 101; directed by subjective aim,
  19949. 102; final, 119; involving presentational
  19950. immediacy, 173, 311; in transmutation,
  19951. 227; at heart of concrescence, 227;
  19952. phases of, 236; and reintegration, 247
  19953.  
  19954. Intellect, 79, 209, 214, 254, 321
  19955.  
  19956. Intellectual, 42, 56, 113, 156, 168, 214,
  19957. 251
  19958.  
  19959. —feelings, 187, 191, 247, 270, 271, 276,
  19960. 280: definition of, 266; two species of,
  19961. 266; main function of, 272; negligible,
  19962. 275; and consciousness, 277, 280, 344;
  19963. haunted by everlasting order, 340; dis-
  19964. tinct from conceptual feelings, 344
  19965.  
  19966. — supplement, 213-14
  19967.  
  19968. Intelligence, 1 68
  19969.  
  19970. Intensification, 56, 107, HI, 213: as
  19971. God's aim, 67, 88; effected by propo-
  19972. sitions, 263
  19973.  
  19974. Intensity: minor, 15; as self-justifying, 16;
  19975. in present and future, 27, 277-78:
  19976. gradations of, 83, 84, 116; and order,
  19977. 83, 84-85, 98, 100, 339; heightening
  19978. of, 83, 272, 278, 279; and appetition,
  19979. 83; of God's consequent nature, 88;
  19980. enfeeblement of, 93; and specialization,
  19981. 101; capture of, 105; sought by God,
  19982. 105, 249; derived from body, 105; and
  19983. contrasts, 109, 244, 277; reward of
  19984. narrowness, 112; quantitative, 116-17,
  19985. 233-34, 332; of items of knowledge,
  19986. 161; and novel appetition, 184; subjec-
  19987. tive forms of, 211; pattern of, 233, 234;
  19988.  
  19989.  
  19990.  
  19991. 370
  19992.  
  19993.  
  19994.  
  19995. Index
  19996.  
  19997.  
  19998.  
  19999. Knowledge (cont.)
  20000.  
  20001. for theory of, 158; belongs to inter-
  20002. mediate phase, 160; as subjective form,
  20003. 160-61; negligible without complexity,
  20004. 161; as capacity, 161; has same explana-
  20005. tion as efficient causation, 190; of
  20006. nexus, 229; difficulties in theory of,
  20007. 243; Locke's view of, 274; limits of,
  20008. 276; of present world, 321; in scholar-
  20009. ship, 338
  20010.  
  20011. Language: ambiguous in relation to propo-
  20012. sitions, xiii, 11, 12, 13, 195, 260, 264;
  20013. ordinary (literary) and philosophical, 4,
  20014. 11, 12, 13, 167, 174; as storehouse
  20015. of knowledge, 5, 10, 11, 39; as ellip-
  20016. tical, 13, 260; and undifferentiated en-
  20017. durance, 77, 79; and substance-quality
  20018. concept, 158; primitive, 159; and inter-
  20019. preted presentational immediacy, 173;
  20020. as example of symbolism, 182-83;
  20021. Egyptian and Babylonian, 183; spoken,
  20022. 264; interpretative vagaries of, 324
  20023.  
  20024. Law(s), 14, 98: of cosmic epoch, 91, 98,
  20025. 116; as statistical, 92, 98, 106, 205,
  20026. 207; obedience to, 91, 98; interact with
  20027. societies of occasions, 106, 204, 205,
  20028. 327; of consciousness, 162; as substi-
  20029. tute for causation, 167; induction not
  20030. derivation of, 204; for feelings in satis-
  20031. faction, 231; God as basis of, 283;
  20032. arbitrary, 292; as problem in differential
  20033. geometry, 333; ultimate, 333
  20034.  
  20035. Least action, method of, 332
  20036.  
  20037. Leibniz, 19, 27, 47, 48, 80, 190, 251
  20038.  
  20039. Length, 333
  20040.  
  20041. Life: and novelty of appetition, 102, 104,
  20042. 178; not a defining characteristic, 104;
  20043. bid for freedom, 104, 107; robbery, 105;
  20044. clutch at vivid immediacy, 105; lurks in
  20045. interstices. 105-06: wandering of vivid
  20046. manifestations of, 106; catalytic agent,
  20047. 106; not essentially social, 106-07;
  20048. canalization of, 107-08; as gain of in-
  20049. tensity, 107; centers of, 108; trigger-
  20050. action of, 120; novel forms of energy
  20051. in, 120; of enduring object, 161; and
  20052. importance of presented duration, 177,
  20053. 178; symbolism in higher grades of,
  20054. 183; as approach to consciousness, 311;
  20055. order and novelty in, 339; selection re-
  20056. quired for depths of, 340
  20057.  
  20058. Light, 36, 78-79, 163
  20059.  
  20060. Limitation: implies decision, 43, 164; ex-
  20061.  
  20062.  
  20063.  
  20064. clusive, 45; and incompatibilities, 149;
  20065. God's role in, 164; in fluent things, 209;
  20066. and subjective unity, 237
  20067.  
  20068. Living occasions, 102, 104, 109, 184
  20069.  
  20070. Living person: as enduring object, 107,
  20071. 109; defining characteristic of, 107; re-
  20072. quires living, non-social nexus, 107; not
  20073. in cells, vegetables, lower animals, 107;
  20074. objectified in God's consequent nature,
  20075. 107n, 350; awareness of self as, 107;
  20076. only partially dominant, 107, 109; in
  20077. higher animals, 107
  20078.  
  20079. Living Society (-ies) : cell as, 99, 104; defi-
  20080. nition of, 102, 103; and non-living
  20081. societies, 102, 104; subservient appa-
  20082. ratus of, 103; requires food, 105-06;
  20083. non-social nexus of, 105; causal aware-
  20084. ness in lower, 176
  20085.  
  20086. Locke, John, xi, 11, 39, 60, 130: antici-
  20087. pated philosophy of organism, xi, 54,
  20088. 123, 128, 147; cosmology of, xiv, 19,
  20089. 91; on power, 18, 57-58, 210, 213;
  20090. on substance, 18-19, 54-60, 75, 79-80,
  20091. 228; on ideas, 19, 25, 41, 51, 52, 138,
  20092. 155, 213, 260; two substances of, 19; on
  20093. perpetual perishing, 29, 81, 210; over-
  20094. thrown by Hume, 51; inconsistency in
  20095. his epistemology, 51. 57, 113, 123, 128,
  20096. 138/143, 146, 147, 149, 152, 157, 210,
  20097. 242-43, 315; adequacy of, 51, 57,
  20098. 60, 145-46; inappropriate metaphysical
  20099. categories of, 51; book title of, 51; on
  20100. mind as cabinet, 53n, 54; on perception
  20101. of exterior things (ideas of particular
  20102. existents), 54-56, 113, 117, 122, 138,
  20103. 141, 146, 152, 213, 237, 242; on sub-
  20104. stantial form, 55; sensationalist, 57,
  20105. 146; and principle of relativity, 58; and
  20106. ontological principle, 58; and relational-
  20107. character of eternal objects, 58; ana-
  20108. logue to Plato, 60; systematized by
  20109. Hume, 73, 113, 128,' 147; reverses
  20110. order of perception, 113, 143, 173;
  20111. and substance-quality metaphysics, 138,
  20112. 159; superior to Hume, 138; and mor-
  20113. phology, 139-40; accepts sensationalist
  20114. principle, 141, 157; introduces shift
  20115. into philosophy, 144; followers of, 145;
  20116. importance of, 145, 147; discards meta-
  20117. physics, 145, 146-47, 153, 210; ana-
  20118. lyzed mental operations alone, 151; and
  20119. objective content of experience, 152;
  20120. introduced anti-rationalism, 153; on ex-
  20121. perience as constructive, 156; successor
  20122.  
  20123.  
  20124.  
  20125. 372
  20126.  
  20127.  
  20128.  
  20129. Index
  20130.  
  20131.  
  20132.  
  20133. Mentality (cont)
  20134.  
  20135. sitive experience, 248; as modifying
  20136. agency, 325
  20137.  
  20138. Mental operations: pure and impure, 33;
  20139. and mind, 85, 213; proper place of,
  20140. 151; abruptness of, 184, 187, 189; pri-
  20141. mary and derivative, 248; consciousness
  20142. not essential to, 248; as basis of efficient
  20143. causation, 277; double office of, 277
  20144.  
  20145. Mental originality, 107-08
  20146.  
  20147. Mental (conceptual) pole, 45, 108, 240,
  20148. 308, 316: first two phases of, 26, 249;
  20149. physical realization of, 32; determines
  20150. subjective forms, 70; enhancement of,
  20151. 101, 184; hybrid prehension of, 107;
  20152. inseparable from physical pole, 108,
  20153. 239, 248; variation in importance of,
  20154. 177, 239; life as novelty in, 184; God's
  20155. origination from, 224, 348; how oc-
  20156. casions originate from, 224; as subject
  20157. determining itself, 248; out of time,
  20158. 248; not necessarily conscious, 277; sub-
  20159. jective side of experience, 277; indi-
  20160. visibility of, 285, 308; originative energy
  20161. of, 285; as appetition, 348; as infinite,
  20162. 348
  20163.  
  20164. Mental prehension: in all actualities, 56;
  20165. pure, 63; blind, 308. See also Concep-
  20166. tual prehension
  20167.  
  20168. Mental progress, 254
  20169.  
  20170. Metaphors, 4
  20171.  
  20172. Metaphysical: systems, 8, 13, 14, 42; cate-
  20173. gories, 8, 29; knowledge, 12; truth, 13,
  20174. 28, 35, 225, 348; principles, 21, 40, 116-
  20175. 17, 167, 342, 343; character (istics),
  20176. 22, 90, 192, 220; stability, 40; gen-
  20177. erality, 96, 222, 308; schemes based on
  20178. Kant or Hegel, 113; difficulties, 117,
  20179. 168; reasons, 133; fact, 157; capacities,
  20180. 193; propositions, 193, 197-99; reason-
  20181. ing, 225: necessities, 288: reason, 340:
  20182. doctrine of creative origination, 341;
  20183. character of creative advance, 344
  20184.  
  20185. Metaphysicians, 237
  20186.  
  20187. Metaphysics: first principles of, 4; aim of,
  20188. 11, 219; novelty in, 12; as approxima-
  20189. tion, 12, 13; and practice, 13, 151;
  20190. success of, 14; haunted by abstract no-
  20191. tions, 18; and religion, 42, 208; justifi-
  20192. cation for, 42; motive for, 42; tasks of,
  20193. 84, 208; proper meaning of, 90; con-
  20194. nects behavior and formal nature, 94;
  20195. generalizes human experience, 112; gen-
  20196. eralizes physics, 116-17; investigates
  20197.  
  20198.  
  20199.  
  20200. generic notions, 116; and classical the-
  20201. ory of time, 125; Locke's avoidance of,
  20202. 145, 146-47; necessity of, 146; rule of
  20203. evidence, 151; and subjective experi-
  20204. encing, 160; final question of, 189;
  20205. thinness of modern, 208; complete prob-
  20206. lem of, 209; of flux, substance, 209;
  20207. and relevance of forms, 316. See also
  20208. Philosophy; Speculative philosophy
  20209.  
  20210. Method, philosophic, xiv, 3, 4-6, 8, 158
  20211.  
  20212. Microcosm, microcosmic, 47-48, 215
  20213.  
  20214. Microscopic, 128-29, 167, 214-15, 333n
  20215.  
  20216. Mill, John Stuart, 12
  20217.  
  20218. Milton, John, 95-96
  20219.  
  20220. Mind: Hume on, 49, 54, 138, 139-41,
  20221. 151, 159-60, 210; as process, 49, 54,
  20222. 138, 140, 151, 210; as subject with
  20223. predicates, 51; Locke on, 53-54, 213;
  20224. Cartesian notion of, 54, 62, 108, 122,
  20225. 160, 246; detached, 56; Newton on,
  20226. 70, 71-72; with private ideas, 76; men-
  20227. tal operations as, 85; lure for feeling as
  20228. germ of, 85; Aquinas on, 108; as en-
  20229. during object, 109; replaced by actual
  20230. entity, 141; greyness as qualifying, 159;
  20231. intellectual operations as, 214; suggests
  20232. independent substance, 214. See also
  20233. Body-mind problem
  20234.  
  20235. Minima sensibilia, 124
  20236.  
  20237. Modes: Spinoza's, 7, 81; of implication,
  20238. 23; of expression, 96; of functioning,
  20239. 166
  20240.  
  20241. Molecular theory, 78, 94-95
  20242.  
  20243. Molecule: in steel bar, 16; peculiar to
  20244. our cosmic epoch, 66; not actual occa-
  20245. sion, 73; as nexus, 73, 287; as moving
  20246. (changing) body, 73, 80; as event, 73,
  20247. 80; as enduring substance, 78; as his-
  20248. toric route, 80; formed from atoms, 95;
  20249. as society, 98; as enduring object, 99,
  20250. 326 (or society of); as structured so-
  20251. ciety, 99; as subservient society, 104;
  20252. its behaviour within animal body, 106;
  20253. span of life of, 287; prehensions of, 323;
  20254. and dynamics, 323
  20255.  
  20256. Monads, 19, 48, 80, 190
  20257.  
  20258. Monism: ultimate in, 7; Spinoza's, 7, 48,
  20259. 74, 81; static, 46; follows from subject-
  20260. predicate thought, 137, 145, 190; one
  20261. alternative for philosophy, 79; avoided
  20262. by principle of relativity, 148; Hegel's,
  20263. 210
  20264.  
  20265. Morality, xii, 15, 27, 42, 84, 105, 222,
  20266. 255, 317, 337, 343
  20267.  
  20268.  
  20269.  
  20270. 374
  20271.  
  20272.  
  20273.  
  20274. Index
  20275.  
  20276.  
  20277.  
  20278. Novelty: in science, 10; in metaphysics,
  20279. 12; creativity as principle of, 21; pro-
  20280. duction of, 21; creative advance into,
  20281. 28, 128, 187, 222, 349; inconceivability
  20282. of, 40; and ordering of eternal objects,
  20283. 40, 164; emergence of, 46, 187; God
  20284. as source of, 67, 88, 164, 248, 349; as
  20285. God's instrument, 88; as basis of trans-
  20286. cendence, 94; of subjective form, 102,
  20287. 164, 232, 233; originated by subjective
  20288. aim, 102; conceptual, 102, 161; of
  20289. definiteness, 104; primordial nature in-
  20290. different to ? 105; possible, 161; and
  20291. pure potentiality, 164; for God, 167,
  20292. 349; of appetition. 184; probability of,
  20293. 202, 203, 207; in phases of concrescence,
  20294. 224; proximate, 249; and reversion, 249,
  20295. 253; and transmutation, 269; and sys-
  20296. tematic order, 339; and route of domi-
  20297. nant occasions, 339; and loss, 340; in
  20298. God, 345; passage into, 349
  20299.  
  20300. Nunn, T. P., xii
  20301.  
  20302.  
  20303.  
  20304. Object (s): as topic of science, 16; four
  20305. main types of, 52; actual entities as,
  20306. 56, 239; meaning of, 88, 239; Locke's
  20307. talk of, 139; universals strictly are, 152;
  20308. and knowledge, 155-56; as form of
  20309. definiteness, 215; as transcendent, 215,
  20310. 239-40; necessary conformity to, 215;
  20311. Kant on, 21 5n; functioning as, 220;
  20312. components of datum become, 231; as
  20313. immanent, 239-40
  20314.  
  20315. Objectification, 49, 50, 52, 53, 116, 137,
  20316. 152,177, 180,206,210,235,245,246,
  20317. 291: definition of, 23, 25, 41; as con-
  20318. verse of prehension, 24; eternal objects
  20319. in, 58, 120, 149, 155, 191; and power,
  20320. 58; causal, 58, 64; presentational, 58,
  20321. 61, 64, 321; as abstraction, 62, 63, 101,
  20322. 160, 210, 221, 238, 307; of contempo-
  20323. raries, 63, 67, 310, 321; retains exten-
  20324. sive relationships, 67; and givenness, 76,
  20325. 171; extensive continuum in, 76; as
  20326. settled, 85; data of, 86; as efficient
  20327. cause, 87; massive average, 101; im-
  20328. mediate (direct), 112, 284, 307, 308;
  20329. line of, 120; and repetition, 137, 139,
  20330. 155; primitive mode of, 141; and
  20331. Locke's second use of idea, 149; and
  20332. immediacy, 155; relevant, 206; involves
  20333. elimination, 210, 226, 274, 340; and
  20334. divisibility, 227; of actual world, 233;
  20335.  
  20336.  
  20337.  
  20338. as perspective of initial datum, 236;
  20339. mediate (indirect), 284, 286, 307, 308
  20340.  
  20341. Objective actuality, 159
  20342.  
  20343. Objective content, 150, 152, 153, 155,
  20344. 160, 213
  20345.  
  20346. Objective datum, 164, 237, 240: of satis-
  20347. faction, 26; in transmuted feeling, 27,
  20348. 160, 232; and negative prehensions, 41
  20349. (pi); as actual world, 65, 83, 212, 230;
  20350. as primary phase, 65; as settled, 83, 150;
  20351. order in, 88 (pi.); complexity of, 106,
  20352. 210, 232; as perspective, 150, 221, 231
  20353. (pi.), 236, 241; as real potentiality,
  20354. 150; as objective content, 150, 152;
  20355. proposition as, 221; nexus as, 221, 291;
  20356. diverse elements cannot coalesce in,
  20357. 225; particularities in, 228; as one,
  20358. 230-31; of various feelings, 232; not
  20359. formless, 233; subjective form repro-
  20360. duces pattern of, 233-34; a feeling as,
  20361. 236; as cause, 238; ingression in, 238,
  20362. 291; physical, 248; as contrast, 283.
  20363. See also Datum
  20364.  
  20365. Objective diversity, category of, 26, 222,
  20366. 225, 227-28, 230, 271
  20367.  
  20368. Objective existence (objective), 45, 76,
  20369. 83, 215, 219, 237
  20370.  
  20371. Objective identity (unity), category of,
  20372. 26, 57, 165 (unity), 222-23, 225,
  20373. 227-28, 230, 231, 238, 249, 266, 271
  20374. (unity)
  20375.  
  20376. Objective immortality: as relatedness of
  20377. actualities, xiii; attained in perishing,
  20378. transcendence, 29, 60, 82, 223; condi-
  20379. tions creativity, 31-32, 108; of super-
  20380. ject, 45, 84, 245; enjoyment of, 56, 215,
  20381. 278; involves repetition, 137; of mutual
  20382. prehensions, 230; of nexus, 230; sub-
  20383. jectivity of cause retained in, 237; em-
  20384. bodied in simple physical feelings, 238;
  20385. as reason for transmission, efficient
  20386. causation, 245, 292; of God's concep-
  20387. tual valuation, 247; everlasting, 347;
  20388. requires God's primordial nature, 347;
  20389. reconciled with immediacy, 351; final
  20390. application of, 351
  20391.  
  20392. Objective lure, 86: and subjective aim,
  20393. 87; definition of, 87, 185; and potential
  20394. difference, 87; richness of, 89; propo-
  20395. sitions as elements in, 187. See also
  20396. Lure for feeling
  20397.  
  20398. Objectivism, 158, 159
  20399.  
  20400. Objectivist principle, 160
  20401.  
  20402. Objectivity, 156
  20403.  
  20404.  
  20405.  
  20406. 376
  20407.  
  20408.  
  20409.  
  20410. Index
  20411.  
  20412.  
  20413.  
  20414. Originality: of conceptual prehension,
  20415. 102; of response, 104; of living occa-
  20416. sions, 106; canalization of, 107; con-
  20417. ditioned by initial aim, 108; God as
  20418. ground of all, 108. See also Initiative
  20419.  
  20420. Origination: physical, 48; conceptual, 49;
  20421. of energy, 117, 246; of feeling, 186,
  20422. 232, 249; negation of, 213; of actual
  20423. entity, 224; of decisions, 232; as private,
  20424. 290, 310. See also Initiative
  20425.  
  20426. Originative phases, 115, 117, 122, 168,
  20427. 172, 177
  20428.  
  20429. Ovate regions, classes, 302-09
  20430.  
  20431. Overintellectualism, 141, 186
  20432.  
  20433. Overlapping, 296
  20434.  
  20435. Overstatement, 7
  20436.  
  20437. Parallelograms, 331
  20438.  
  20439. Participation, 20, 21, 40, 46, 95
  20440.  
  20441. Particularity: of religion, 15; of experience,
  20442. 43; of actualities, 55, 229-31; of propo-
  20443. sitions, 197; of each entity, 225; two
  20444. meanings of, 229; of nexus, 229-31; of
  20445. contrasts, 229, 230; and first three cate-
  20446. gories, 230; of feelings, 237, 255
  20447.  
  20448. Particulars. 33-34, 41, 52-53, 57, 128,
  20449. 146-47, 152, 158, 194, 210, 229, 344:
  20450. and universals, 20, 48-50, 158
  20451.  
  20452. Past: and present, 14, 105, 339; remote,
  20453. 63; as source of datum, 116, 150; per-
  20454. ception of, 120; defined by causal
  20455. efficacy, 123, 170, 319-20, 322; practi-
  20456. cally common, 127, 169; of personal ex-
  20457. perience, 129; as determinate beyond,
  20458. 163; not defined by presentational im-
  20459. mediacy, 168; immediate, 178; as effi-
  20460. cient cause, 210; conformity with power
  20461. of, 210; immortality, 210, 238; as
  20462. nexus. 214; determined by immediate
  20463. decision, 284; durational, 320; treasures
  20464. of, 339; paradoxical attitude toward,
  20465. 340; present under abstraction, 340;
  20466. inheritance of future from, 350
  20467.  
  20468. Pathology, 102, 109
  20469.  
  20470. Pattern, 192, 230-31, 245: as given, 44;
  20471. sensa and, 114; as manner of contrast,
  20472. 115; as simple, 115; individual essence
  20473. of, 115; as complex, 115; as eternal
  20474. object, 120, 257; predicative, 194, 197,
  20475. 257, 280; two factors of, 233; qualita-
  20476. tive, 233-35; of emotional intensity,
  20477. 233-35, 237, 240; emotional, 273, 275,
  20478. 280
  20479.  
  20480.  
  20481.  
  20482. Percepta, 180, 181, 242
  20483.  
  20484. Perception, xii, 3: sensationalist doctrine
  20485. of, xiii, 52, 156 (see also Sensationalist
  20486. principle; Subjectivist principle; Sensa-
  20487. tionalism); confused, 27; visual, 36, 44,
  20488. 117, 121; Humian doctrine of, 48-49;
  20489. Descartes' view of, 48-49; of actual
  20490. entities, 49, 58, 122, 158; representative
  20491. theory of, 49, 54, 76; Locke's use of,
  20492. 52; and power, 58; ordinary meaning of,
  20493. 58; delusive, 64, 122; drops of, 68;
  20494. crude (primitive), 81, 117, 119; of
  20495. contemporary world, 81; sophisticated
  20496. (higher grades of), 81, 117, 121; direct,
  20497. 81, 113, 116-17, 119, 124; problems
  20498. in theory of, 113, 117, 121; and causa-
  20499. tion, 116, 173-75, 239, 290; common
  20500. elements of, 117; ultimate truth of ani-
  20501. mal, 118; interplay of two pure modes
  20502. of, 121, 168; human, 125, 168; as
  20503. awareness of universal, 158-60; nega-
  20504. tive, 161; positive, 161; as interpreta-
  20505. tive, 168; heightening of, 213; memory
  20506. as physical, 239; blind, 287; fact of,
  20507. 290. See also Causal efficacy, perception
  20508. in the mode of; Presentational im-
  20509. mediacy; Representation; Symbolic ref-
  20510. erence; Sense-perception
  20511.  
  20512. Perceptive feelings, 260, 261-63, 264,
  20513. 266, 268, 270: definition of, 261, 269;
  20514. three species of, 262
  20515.  
  20516. —authentic, 262, 264, 268-69, 270
  20517.  
  20518. —unauthentic, 263, 268, 270, 272
  20519.  
  20520. Percipient: occasion, 63, 120, 145; final,
  20521. 119-20, 245, 312, 313, 319; memoriz-
  20522. ing, 120; enduring, 270
  20523.  
  20524. Perfection, 47, 338, 345, 347, 348-49,
  20525. 350, 351
  20526.  
  20527. Periodicity, 327
  20528.  
  20529. Perishing: of immediacy, xiii, 29, 85; con-
  20530. trasted with changing, 35; as objective
  20531. immortality, 81-82; everlastingness as
  20532. devoid of, 346, 347; and yet living,
  20533. 349, 351
  20534.  
  20535. — perpetual: meaning of, 29; Locke on,
  20536. 29, 146-47, 210; of absoluteness, 60;
  20537. as attainment of immortality, 60; time
  20538. as, 81, 128, 210, 340; as transition,
  20539. 210
  20540.  
  20541. Permanence: of forms, 29; enhanced by
  20542. width, 163; and flux, 167, 209, 338,
  20543. 341, 347, 348: as result of reproduction,
  20544. 238; in measurement, 327-29
  20545.  
  20546.  
  20547.  
  20548. 378
  20549.  
  20550.  
  20551.  
  20552. Index
  20553.  
  20554.  
  20555.  
  20556. Physical pole (cont.)
  20557.  
  20558. 308; finite, exclusive, 348; as enjoyment,
  20559. 348
  20560.  
  20561. Physical purposes, 256n: and Bergson's
  20562. intuition, 33, 280; subjective form of,
  20563. 184; definition of, 184, 266; initial,
  20564. 244; phase of, 248-49, 280; as com-
  20565. parative feelings, 254, 275-80; more
  20566. primitive than perceptive and intellec-
  20567. tual feelings, 266, 272-73, 275; all
  20568. actualities have, 276; eternal objects
  20569. and objective datum in, 276; explain
  20570. endurance, 276; two species of, 276-80;
  20571. explain rhythm and vibration, 276;
  20572. blind, 308; reinforce conceptual feeling,
  20573. 316; and impressions of sensation, 316;
  20574. in transmutation, 317; in presentational
  20575. immediacy, 323
  20576.  
  20577. Physical realization, 341, 346, 348
  20578.  
  20579. Physical recognition (recollection), 260,
  20580. 261-64, 269, 270, 271, 272, 274
  20581.  
  20582. Physical time, 283, 288-89
  20583.  
  20584. Physical world, 238, 325
  20585.  
  20586. Physics (physical science, theory) : and
  20587. metaphysics, xii, 4, 5, 116-17; Greek
  20588. and mediaeval, 12; progress in, 14;
  20589. relativity theory of, 35, 65, 125,
  20590. 126; atomism and continuity in, 35-36;
  20591. and Descartes' view of space, 72; po-
  20592. tential difference in, 87; and Newton,
  20593. 94, 96, 177; on chemical facts, 95;
  20594. mathematical relations in, 98, 128, 231,
  20595. 326, 327; electromagnetic field as topic
  20596. of, 98; seventeenth-century, 113; and
  20597. epistemology, 113, 117, 119; on body
  20598. and universe, 119; and straight lines,
  20599. 127; morphology in, 139-40; and the-
  20600. ory of light, 163; and distinction of past
  20601. and future, 170; on cause of sensa, 171;
  20602. vibration in, 187-88; scalar and vector
  20603. forms in, 212, 231, 238; investigates
  20604. aspects of simple physical feelings, 238;
  20605. quantum theory of, 238-39, 254; and
  20606. continuous transmission, 307; and ac-
  20607. tion at a distance, 308; from material-
  20608. ism to organism in, 309; geometrical
  20609. pattern in, 312; form of energy in, 315;
  20610. needs distinction of intensive and ex-
  20611. tensive quantity, 332
  20612.  
  20613. Physiology, 5, 87, 103-04, 114, 118, 141,
  20614. 171, 174-75, 234, 312
  20615.  
  20616. Planes, 127, 306, 310, 319, 331
  20617.  
  20618. Plato, 21, 39, 83, 159: founder of West-
  20619. ern thought, xi; dominance of his cos-
  20620.  
  20621.  
  20622.  
  20623. mology, xiv, 93; advance of philosophy
  20624. since, 7; abiding appeal of, 20; foot-
  20625. notes to, 39; and philosophy of orga-
  20626. nism, 39, 44, 94-96; and limits of
  20627. rationalism, 42; forms of, 43-44, 46,
  20628. 96, 209, 291; modification of his real-
  20629. ism, 50; analogue to Locke, 60; on
  20630. mathematics, 62; inspired by Pythago-
  20631. reans, 71; on perishing, 82, 84, 85; on
  20632. peculiar ideals, 84; and recent logical-
  20633. mathematical discoveries, 91; compared
  20634. with Newton, 93-96; poeticized by
  20635. Milton, 95-96; and substance-quality
  20636. metaphysics, 137; on permanence and
  20637. flux, 209; his vision of heavenly per-
  20638. fection, 209; subordinated fluency, 209;
  20639. schools based on, 209; on reminiscence,
  20640. 242, 249; and straight lines, 302; prob-
  20641. lem of, 346-47
  20642.  
  20643. Plenum, world as, 238
  20644.  
  20645. Pluralism, 18, 73-74, 78, 79, 137
  20646.  
  20647. Points, 287, 292, 299-332 passim
  20648.  
  20649. Position, 25, 195, 258
  20650.  
  20651. Possibility: of interconnection, xii; trans-
  20652. cendent, 31; of division, 61-62; of
  20653. novelty, 161; abstract, 220, 276 (see
  20654. also Eternal objects); of finite truth,
  20655. 220
  20656.  
  20657. Potential difference, 87
  20658.  
  20659. Potentiality: pure (abstract, general), 22,
  20660. 23, 40, 65, 66, 80, 149, 164, 184, 188,
  20661. 214, 239, 343 (see also Eternal ob-
  20662. jects); impure, 22, 188 (see also Propo-
  20663. sitions); and principle of relativity, 22,
  20664. 43, 212; real, 23, 27, 65-66, 67, 72-73,
  20665. 76, 80, 96, 123, 150, 168-69, 220,
  20666. 223, 267, 288, 308, 324, 326, 333;
  20667. passes into actuality, 29, 308; con-
  20668. trasted with actuality, 39-40, 148-49;
  20669. correlate of givenness, 44, 133; meaning
  20670. of, 45-46; unrealized, 46, 86; locus of,
  20671. 46; and continuity, 61, 62; datum as,
  20672. 65, 88, 113; in space- time, 70; as in-
  20673. cluded in actuality, 72, 227, 290-91;
  20674. and freedom, 133; retains message of
  20675. alternatives, 149; propositional, 187,
  20676. 267; in nature, 239; conceptually
  20677. realized in God, 343; forms of, 349
  20678.  
  20679. Power: and substance, 18-19, 56-58,
  20680. 79-80; and ontological principle, 18,
  20681. 79-80; of God, 49, 346; and enduring
  20682. things, 56; active and passive, 57; as
  20683. including relation, 57-58; and objecti-
  20684. fication, 58; and perception, 58; in act-
  20685.  
  20686.  
  20687.  
  20688. 380
  20689.  
  20690.  
  20691.  
  20692. Index
  20693.  
  20694.  
  20695.  
  20696. Primary feelings, 231, 239, 241-42
  20697. Primary substance, xiii, 21, 30, 50, 138,
  20698.  
  20699. 157," 158
  20700. Principia Mathematica, 149n, 198n
  20701. Principle of Relativity, The, 333
  20702. Principles of Natural Knowledge, The,
  20703.  
  20704. USn, 288n
  20705. Priority, 54, 143, 162, 315
  20706. Private: sensation, 18, 141, 234, 311, 315;
  20707. subjective forms as, 22; synthesis, 85;
  20708. and public, 151, 289-90, 310, 314, 316,
  20709. 317, 329; qualities, 160; ideal, 212; indi-
  20710. vidual fact, 213; nothing purely, 212;
  20711. immediacy, 213; eliminated by theory
  20712. of extensions, 292; psychological field,
  20713. 325, 326, 333
  20714. Probability, 6, 167, 199-207, 268, 274.
  20715.  
  20716. See also Induction
  20717. Process, 128: description of, 7; as ex-
  20718. periencing subject, 16; actual entities
  20719. as, 21, 22, 41, 54, 140, 219, 227, 243,
  20720. 283; principle of, 23, 166, 235; genetic,
  20721. 26, 154; and ingression of forms, 39-
  20722. 40, 96, 154; of world, 39, 96, 340, 349;
  20723. potentiality for, 43; as evaporation of
  20724. indetermination, 45, 150; mind as, 49,
  20725. 54, 138, 140-41, 151, 210; Hume's
  20726. emphasis on, 54, 140; and product, 84,
  20727. 255; as basic notion, 128; as attainment
  20728. of end, 150; creative, 151; and under-
  20729. standing, 153, 210; as essentially feel-
  20730. ing, 153; correct order of, 156; repeti-
  20731. tions of, 210; phases of, 212, 214-15;
  20732. microscopic and macroscopic, 214-15;
  20733. efficient and teleological, 214; and
  20734. organism, 214-15; of integration, 227;
  20735. genetic, 230; and loss, 340. See also
  20736. Concrescence; Transition
  20737. Progress, 14, 111, 187, 247, 254, 339
  20738. Projection, 126, 172, 176, 177-78, 180,
  20739.  
  20740. 310, 312, 314, 322-26, 330
  20741. Proper entities, 30, 221, 224, 228
  20742. Propositional feelings (prehensions): type
  20743. of comparative feeling, 164; form of
  20744. appetition, 184; and pure conceptual
  20745. feelings, 185, 313; origin of, 191, 261,
  20746. 263; definition of, 214, 256; conscious-
  20747. ness, judgment not necessary for, 232,
  20748. 259, 242, 261, 263; as pure mental
  20749. feeling, 241; arise in late phase, 247,
  20750. 260; analogous to transmuted feelings,
  20751. 253; arise from integration, 257, 261 ,
  20752. 264; two kinds of pure, 260, 261-62;
  20753.  
  20754.  
  20755.  
  20756. elimination involved in, 261, 263; as
  20757. imaginative freedom, 261; as lure, 263;
  20758. involved in comparative feelings, 266;
  20759. involve evaluative hold up, 280; lie be-
  20760. tween physical purposes and intellectual
  20761. feelings, 280; and Bergson's intuition,
  20762. 280; importance of, 280; as approach to
  20763. consciousness, 308
  20764.  
  20765. Propositional imagination, 274
  20766.  
  20767. Propositions, 22: and verbal statements,
  20768. xiii, 11-13, 192-93, 195-97, 256, 268;
  20769. truth and falsehood of, 8, 184-85, 186,
  20770. 256, 258-59, 261, 268, 271, 285; pre-
  20771. suppose context, 11-12, 195; meta-
  20772. physical, 11, 193, 197-99; as impure
  20773. entities, 22, 185, 187, 188, 257; as
  20774. theories, 22, 184; novel, 33, 188, 219,
  20775. 259; definition of, 24, 188, 196-97,
  20776. 257; lures for feeling, 25, 185, 186-87,
  20777. 224, 259, 273, 280; and judgments, 25,
  20778. 184-85, 186-87, 189, 191, 192-93,
  20779. 259; as indeterminate, 29, 257, 258,
  20780. 263; subject-predicate form of, 30, 159;
  20781. include demonstratives, 43; as objects,
  20782. data, 52, 184, 189, 221, 243; present in
  20783. actual entities, 147; consciousness not
  20784. necessary for, 184, 186, 263; general
  20785. and singular, 186, 196; universal, 186,
  20786. 188; locus of, 186, 195; realization
  20787. of, 186, 197, 267; logical subjects of,
  20788. 188, 193, 258-59; and judging sub-
  20789. jects, 193, 196-97; and eternal objects,
  20790. 197, 256-57, 258; compared with
  20791. actual entities, feelings, nexus, 196-97,
  20792. 258-59; metaphysical, 197-99; incom-
  20793. plete phase as, 224, 237, 247, 261; self-
  20794. consistency of, 224; mere potentiality
  20795. of, 224; not a class, 228; tales that
  20796. might be told, 256; partially abstract
  20797. from actual entities, 256, 258; intensify
  20798. or inhibit, 263; objective probability of,
  20799. 268; in coordinate division, 285
  20800.  
  20801. Protons, 66, 78, 79, 91, 92, 98, 99, 326
  20802.  
  20803. Psychology, xiii, 5, 18, 103, 141, 268, 325,
  20804. 326
  20805.  
  20806. Publicity, 22, 151, 289-90, 310, 314, 317,
  20807.  
  20808. _ 329
  20809.  
  20810. Pure conceptual (mental) prehension
  20811. (feeling), 33, 63, 184, 241
  20812.  
  20813. Pure physical prehension (feeling) : as
  20814. opposed to impure, 33, 63, 214, 242,
  20815. 316; as opposed to hybrid, 245, 250,
  20816. 251-52, 308
  20817.  
  20818.  
  20819.  
  20820. 382
  20821.  
  20822.  
  20823.  
  20824. Index
  20825.  
  20826.  
  20827.  
  20828. Reminiscence, 242, 249
  20829.  
  20830. Repetition, 133-37, 139, 140, 148, 155,
  20831. 210, 253, 279, 338
  20832.  
  20833. Representation, 53, 54, 76, 144, 237
  20834.  
  20835. Reproduction, 91, 92, 237, 238: concep-
  20836. tual, 26, 249
  20837.  
  20838. Responsibility, 47, 222, 224, 255
  20839.  
  20840. Responsive phase. See Phase, first
  20841.  
  20842. Rest, 319, 321, 323
  20843.  
  20844. Res vera(e), xiii, 22, 29, 68, 69-70, 74-
  20845. 75, 128, 137, 166, 167
  20846.  
  20847. Reversion (category of), 26, 101, 104, 246,
  20848. 247, 249-50, 251-53, 254-55, 260,
  20849. 261, 262, 263, 269, 272, 277-79; as
  20850. abolished, 250; double, 252; and physics,
  20851. 254, 277, 278-79
  20852.  
  20853. Rhythm, 78-79, 213, 327
  20854.  
  20855.  
  20856.  
  20857. Sampling, 202-03, 206
  20858.  
  20859. Santayana, George, 48-49, 52, 54, 81,
  20860. 142-43, 152, 158
  20861.  
  20862. Satisfaction, 40, 89, 153, 164, 219-
  20863. 21, 227, 232-33, 235, 280, 292-93
  20864. and subjective aim, 19, 87, 255; defini
  20865. tion of, 25, 26, 211-12, 283; God's 32
  20866. 88; unity of, 32, 115, 185, 235; sub
  20867. jective form of, 41, 247, 267; exclusive
  20868. ness of, 44, 45; as determinate, 48, 85
  20869. 149, 154-55; subjectivity of, 52, 160
  20870. as superject, sentiri, efficient cause, use
  20871. ful, 60, 84, 85, 166, 188, 219, 220
  20872. 292-93; temporal halves of, 69; divisi
  20873. biltty of, 69, 220-21, 238, 283-86
  20874. 292-93; intensity of, 83, 84, 92-93
  20875. 100, 101, 111-12, 115, 116, 119; and
  20876. order, 84, 110; differences in, 84, 111
  20877. and notion of substance, 84; and indi
  20878. viduality. 84, 154: no consciousness of
  20879. 85; novelty in, 102, 232; depth of, 105
  20880. 110-12; narrowness, width, triviality
  20881. and vagueness in, 110-12; quantitative.
  20882. 116; and Kant's apparent objective con
  20883. tent, 155; transitoriness of, 163; as two
  20884. dimensional, 166; as contentment of
  20885. creative urge, 219; morphology of, 220
  20886. genetic analysis of, 220, 235; objective
  20887. datum of, 225, 235; two laws for, 231
  20888. integrates simple physical feelings, 237
  20889. withness of body in, 312; and God's
  20890. completion, 347
  20891.  
  20892. Scalar, 116, 177, 212
  20893.  
  20894. Scheme of thought, xiv, 3-4, 8, 9, 14, 39,
  20895. 337, 339
  20896.  
  20897.  
  20898.  
  20899. Science, 11, 15, 39, 100, 264: special,
  20900. xiv, 9-10, 11, 17, 116; first principles
  20901. of, 8, 10; and philosophy, 9-10, 15-17,
  20902. 116-17, 329; progress in, 14, 61, 71;
  20903. and religion, 16, 42; theory of, 17, 169,
  20904. 274, 323; of dynamics, 35, 72, 101,
  20905. 173, 323; motive for, 42; and undif-
  20906. ferentiated endurance, 77-78; explana-
  20907. tion (interpretation) in, 77-78, 324,
  20908. 326; observation, measurement, 127,
  20909. 169, 329: induction in, 129, 204: and
  20910. autonomy, 245; and mathematical rela-
  20911. tions, 327; and publicity, 333. See also
  20912. Physics
  20913.  
  20914. Science and the Modern World, 11 n, 189,
  20915. 204
  20916.  
  20917. Seat, 310-11, 312-14, 322, 323, 326
  20918.  
  20919. Secondary qualities, 63-64, 78, 113, 122,
  20920. 323, 325
  20921.  
  20922. Self, 150, 154: -correction, 15; -justifica-
  20923. tion, 16; -creation, 25, 47, 69, 85, 289;
  20924. -functioning, 25; -diversity, 25; -iden-
  20925. tity, 25, 55, 57, 78, 79, 225, 227;
  20926. -consistency, 26; -experience, 57; -defi-
  20927. nition, 85-86; -causation, 88, 150, 222,
  20928. 244; -production, 93, 224; -preservation,
  20929. 102; -consciousness, 107; -analysis, 107;
  20930. -formation, 108, 308; -enjoyment, 145,
  20931. 289; -construction, 179; -realization, 222;
  20932. -revelation and -transcendence, 227;
  20933. -criticism, 244; -constitution, 244; -de-
  20934. termination, 245, 255; -restraint, 337;
  20935. -attainment, 350
  20936.  
  20937. Sensa: as forms of emotion, 114, 115, 116,
  20938. 314-15; as simple and complex, 114,
  20939. 115; as eternal objects, 114, 120, 291;
  20940. functions of, 114, 119, 121, 314-15,
  20941. 325; zero width of, 114, 115; meta-
  20942. physical definition of, 114; individual
  20943. and relational essences of, 115, 314-
  20944. 15; as forms of energy, 116; types of,
  20945. 119; enhancement, change in character
  20946. of, 120; effect presentational immedi-
  20947. acy, 121, 124; and presented locus, 124,
  20948. 126-27; and wave-lengths, 163; dona-
  20949. tion of, 171, 176; well-marked, 176;
  20950. projection of, 176, 310, 323-24; physi-
  20951. cal feeling of, 316; participate in nature,
  20952. 325
  20953.  
  20954. Sensation, 141, 157, 172: private, 141,
  20955. 142, 158-59, 234
  20956.  
  20957. Sensationalism, sensationalist doctrine,
  20958. 52-53, 57, 74, 128, 135, 141-42, 145-
  20959. 46, 147, 155, 156, 190: rejection of,
  20960.  
  20961.  
  20962.  
  20963. 384
  20964.  
  20965.  
  20966.  
  20967. Index
  20968.  
  20969.  
  20970.  
  20971. Strain (-feeling) (cont.)
  20972.  
  20973. 318, 322: definition of, 310; geometri-
  20974. cal interest in, 310; not require life,
  20975. 311; and enduring objects, 311; straight
  20976. lines ingredient in, 323
  20977.  
  20978. Strain-locus, 126, 128, 322, 330: defini-
  20979. tion of, 319; as four-dimensional, 319;
  20980. and presented duration, 321, 322-23;
  20981. real and potential, 323
  20982.  
  20983. Stream of experience, 189, 190
  20984.  
  20985. Structured societies, 99-109: definition of,
  20986. 99, 103; examples of, 99, 102; domi-
  20987. nant members of, 102; democratic, 108
  20988.  
  20989. Stubborn fact, xiii, xiv, 43, 128-29, 219,
  20990. 239
  20991.  
  20992. Subject, 41, 45, 59, 182: as topic of re-
  20993. ligion, 16; and feelings, 23, 88, 221—
  20994. 22, 223-24, 231, 232, 233, 235, 236,
  20995. 311; actual entity as, 23, 25, 28, 56,
  20996. 87, 221-22; as superject, 28, 29, 45,
  20997. 47, 69, 83, 84, 88, 151, 155, 166,
  20998. 222, 223, 232, 233, 241, 245, 255,
  20999. 289; never experiences twice, 29; as
  21000. substance, 84, 157; meaning of, 88;
  21001. ultimate, 118, 120, 180; prehending,
  21002. 141, 258-64 passim, 268, 269; judging,
  21003. 191, 200, 203, 258; and experienced
  21004. fact, 195: entertaining, 266; as private
  21005. side of actual entity, 289; feels itself,
  21006. 315; triple character of, 316. See also
  21007. Logical subjects
  21008.  
  21009. Subjective aim: determinant of subjective
  21010. forms, 19, 27, 235, 275; and final
  21011. causation, 19, 24, 87, 104, 210, 277;
  21012. definition of, 25; and reversion, 26, 102;
  21013. as twofold, 27, 85, 277; at intensity,
  21014. 27, 249, 277, 278; modification, self-
  21015. creation of, 47, 69, 167, 224, 241, 244;
  21016. phases of, 47; initial phase of, 67, 224,
  21017. 244, 283, 344, 347 {see also Initial
  21018. aim); indivisibility of, 69; and super-
  21019. ject,' 69, 114; lure for feeling, 85, 328;
  21020. germ of mind, 85; and objective lure,
  21021. 87; God's, 88, 344; directs integration,
  21022. 102, 224, 308; categoreal conditions of,
  21023. 128; and Hegelian idea, 167; three
  21024. possibilities for, 187-88; and ontologi-
  21025. cal principle, 244; due to mental oper-
  21026. ations, 277; and subjective harmony,
  21027. 278, 279
  21028.  
  21029. Subjective end, 224
  21030.  
  21031. Subjective form(s), 16, 85-86, 88, 89,
  21032. 141, 154, 155, 157, 168, 211, 226,
  21033. 231-35, 249, 311: determination of,
  21034.  
  21035.  
  21036.  
  21037. 19, 70, 106, 164, 192, 235, 244-45,
  21038. 285; as private, 22, 233, 290; novelty
  21039. in, 22, 102, 164, 232, 233; definition
  21040. of, 23, 52, 85, 221; examples of, 24,
  21041. 25, 86, 192, 234, 311; consciousness as,
  21042. 23, 53, 162, 236, 241; of conceptual
  21043. feelings as valuational, 27, 33, 240-41,
  21044.  
  21045. 246, 247, 248; and subject-predicate
  21046. proposition, 30; mutual sensitivity of,
  21047. 42, 221; of satisfaction, 41, 154, 235,
  21048. 283, 285; of negative prehensions, 41,
  21049. 226, 237; and eternal objects, 85-86,
  21050. 233, 241, 290, 291; partial conformity
  21051. of, 85, 104, 106, 108, 164, 233, 235,
  21052. 237, 241, 244, 246, 275, 291, 315, 316;
  21053. of physical purpose, 184; judgment as,
  21054. 190; as inhering in feeling, 232; em-
  21055. bodies pragmatic aspect, 233; qualita-
  21056. tive and quantitative factors of, 233-34;
  21057. absent in first phase, 234; of preposi-
  21058. tional feeling, 261, 263; of coordinate
  21059. division, 285; as epiphenomenal, 292;
  21060. omitted by presentational immediacy,
  21061. 327
  21062.  
  21063. Subjective harmony (category of), 27,
  21064. 235, 241, 247, 249, 254-55, 261, 267,
  21065. 279
  21066. Subjective immediacy, 25, 29, 155
  21067. Subjective intensity (category of), 47,
  21068.  
  21069. 247, 277, 278, 279
  21070.  
  21071. Subjective unity (category of), 26, 219,
  21072. 222-25, 226-27, 230, 231, 235, 237,
  21073. 240, 246, 247, 248, 249, 255, 283-84
  21074.  
  21075. Subjective valuation, category of, 246
  21076.  
  21077. Subjectivism: Cartesian, 80, 160, 309;
  21078. solipsist, 152, 158
  21079.  
  21080. Subjectivist bias, 159, 166
  21081.  
  21082. Subjectivist doctrine, 189, 190: reformed,
  21083. 189, 190
  21084.  
  21085. Subjectivist principle, 29: regarding datum,
  21086. 157, 158, 160; reformed, 157, 160,
  21087. 166, 167; regarding reality, 166, 167,
  21088. 191
  21089.  
  21090. Subjectivity, 15, 40, 155, 237-38
  21091.  
  21092. Subject-predicate, xiii, 7, 13, 30, 49, 51,
  21093. 54, 56, 75, 137, 145, 159, 222
  21094.  
  21095. Subordinate (sub-) societies, 99-100, 103,
  21096. 104
  21097.  
  21098. Sub-region, 284, 285, 287-88
  21099.  
  21100. Subsistence, 46
  21101.  
  21102. Substance, 25, 29, 40, 77, 81, 136: actual
  21103. entity as ? xiii, 19, 41, 58, 75 ? 78;
  21104. Descartes on, xiii, 6, 48, 50, 59, 74, 75,
  21105. 80, 84, 108, 122, 144-45, 159, 160,
  21106.  
  21107.  
  21108.  
  21109. 386
  21110.  
  21111.  
  21112.  
  21113. Index
  21114.  
  21115.  
  21116.  
  21117. Transmutation (category of), 63, 65, 77,
  21118. 101-02, 111-12, 250-54, 262, 269,
  21119. 272, 279, 280, 291, 292, 311, 313, 314,
  21120. 317, 323: defintition of, 27, 251; and
  21121. material bodies, 101; and functions of
  21122. sensa, 114, 325; of causal efficacy into
  21123. presentational immediacy, 119, 339; of
  21124. conceptual origination into physical
  21125. world, 164, 246; as physical feeling, 232,
  21126. 253; and consciousness, 236; simplifies,
  21127. 250, 253, 317; analogies to, 253; and
  21128. error, 253; effected by propositions,
  21129. 263; in strain, 310; in God, 350
  21130.  
  21131. Triangle, 291
  21132.  
  21133. Triviality, 110, 111, 254, 277, 285, 340-
  21134. 41, 346
  21135.  
  21136. Truth, 14, 16, 39, 159, 264, 342: and
  21137. falsehood, 8, 11, 223, 256, 258, 261,
  21138. 273; of propositions, 8, 184, 186, 259,
  21139. 268; possibility of finite, 11, 220; and
  21140. God, 12-13, 189, 346; pragmatic mean-
  21141. ing of, 181; and value, 185; phase as
  21142. proposition seeking, 224; -value of meta-
  21143. physical propositions, 197; adds to in-
  21144. terest, 259; coherence as, 271; attention
  21145. and inattention to, 275
  21146.  
  21147. Ultimate, the, 7, 20, 21, 342
  21148.  
  21149. Unauthentic perceptive feelings, 263, 268,
  21150. 270, 272
  21151.  
  21152. Unconscious, subconscious, 52, 54, 186,
  21153. 187, 242, 338
  21154.  
  21155. Understanding, 52, 153, 251
  21156.  
  21157. Uniformity, 112, 333n
  21158.  
  21159. Unifying control, 107, 108
  21160.  
  21161. Unison of becoming (immediacy), 124,
  21162. 126, 128, 320, 322, 340, 345-46, 350,
  21163. 351
  21164.  
  21165. Unity: of actual entities, 22, 45, 47, 150,
  21166. 211, 212, 286, 348; real, 22, 224, 229;
  21167. of a multiplicity, 30, 46; of experience,
  21168. 108, 113,' 128; of satisfaction, 115,
  21169. 211; of a datum, 210; of aesthetic ap-
  21170. preciation, 212; propositional, 224, 236;
  21171. universe's genetic, 286; ultimate, ever-
  21172. lasting, 346, 347, 348, 349, 350; of
  21173. vision, 348-49. See also One
  21174.  
  21175. Universality, 4
  21176.  
  21177. Universal 14, 21, 43, 55, 57, 128, 146,
  21178. 151-52, 158, 190, 229, 230, 273: and
  21179. particulars, 20, 48-50, 56, 158; eternal
  21180. objects mis-described as, 48, 149, 158;
  21181. eternal objects as, 184, 283
  21182.  
  21183. Universe, 22, 26, 47, 89, 94, 95, 166, 225:
  21184.  
  21185.  
  21186.  
  21187. essence of, 4; rationality of, 4; included
  21188. in each actuality, 28, 44, 80, 148, 154,
  21189. 165, 223, 245, 316; not abstractable
  21190. from an entity, 28, 192; solidarity of,
  21191. 40, 56, 164, 220; as static, 46, 222; po-
  21192. tentiality of, 46, 223; prehension of, 56;
  21193. as one and many, 57, 167, 228, 167;
  21194. evolving, 59, 88; freedom inherent in,
  21195. 88; knowledge about, 119, 121, 122,
  21196. 327; actuality of, 200; as organism, 215;
  21197. novelty in, 222, 231; creativity of, 225,
  21198. 346, 350. See also World
  21199.  
  21200. Unrest, 28, 29, 32, 340
  21201.  
  21202. Urge, 129, 219, 228, 239, 285
  21203.  
  21204. Vacuous actuality, xiii, 29, 167, 309
  21205.  
  21206. Vagueness, 65, 76, 81, 111-12, 116, 120,
  21207. 121, 163, 176, 178, 237, 253
  21208.  
  21209. Valuation, 19, 24, 108, 187, 254: pri-
  21210. mordial, 40, 244; and reality, 142; as
  21211. subjective form of conceptual feelings,
  21212. 240, 247, 248, 311, 313; qualitative
  21213. and intensive, 241; three characteristics
  21214. of, 241; up and down, 241, 247, 248,
  21215. 278 (see also Adversion and aversion);
  21216. eternal principles of, 248: important in
  21217. high-grade organisms, 254; and con-
  21218. ceptual feelings, 254. See also Concep-
  21219. tual prehension
  21220.  
  21221. Value, 84, 104, 185, 228
  21222.  
  21223. Vector(s), 55, 87, 117, 119, 120, 151,
  21224. 177, 180, 212, 213, 231, 237-38, 309,
  21225. 315, 316, 317, 319, 325: meaning of,
  21226. 19, 116, 163; and scalar quantities, 177;
  21227. all things as, 309
  21228.  
  21229. Vegetables, 33, 98, 107
  21230.  
  21231. Velocity, 321
  21232.  
  21233. Vera causa, 77, 119
  21234.  
  21235. Verification, 8, 10
  21236.  
  21237. Vibration, 79, 94, 163, 188, 239, 277,
  21238. 279
  21239.  
  21240. Viscera, 118, 121, 141
  21241.  
  21242. Vision, 33, 117, 118, 121, 167, 212, 214,
  21243. 346, 347, 348, 349
  21244.  
  21245. Volume, 300-01, 313, 322
  21246.  
  21247. Von Staudt, Karl G.C., 331, 332
  21248.  
  21249. Wave-lengths, 163, 327
  21250.  
  21251. Waves, 36, 98
  21252.  
  21253. Weierstrass, K.W.T., 328
  21254.  
  21255. Whewell, William, 12
  21256.  
  21257. Whole and part 96, 287, 288, 292
  21258.  
  21259. Width, 110-12, 114, 163, 166, 279
  21260.  
  21261. Words, 182
  21262.  
  21263.  
  21264.  
  21265. 392 Editors' Notes
  21266.  
  21267. Macmillan edition. In such a case we have not actually introduced a change,
  21268. but have simply made this new edition conform to one of the original editions
  21269. (in this case Cambridge).
  21270.  
  21271. The external sources cited as the basis for some of the changes have been
  21272. identified in the Editors' Preface.
  21273.  
  21274. * xi.2 The bracketed number in the text indicates the exact place at which
  21275.  
  21276. the corresponding page began in the 1929 Macmillan edition.
  21277.  
  21278. t xi.14 inserted 'the' before 'scheme' (M v.17)— As explained above, the
  21279. fact that there is a reference to only the Macmillan edition (M) means
  21280. that this corrected edition follows Cambridge at this point.
  21281.  
  21282. t xi.16 inserted comma after 'part' (M v.20) to conform to parallels in the
  21283. previous and following paragraphs (as Cambridge did)— Series of intro-
  21284. ductory phrases (e.g., "In the first case, ... in the second case, . . .")
  21285. were quite often punctuated inconsistently. We have made the punc-
  21286. tuation consistent at these points without further notation.
  21287.  
  21288. * xi fn.l Whitehead used the thirtieth edition of Locke's Essay, which was
  21289.  
  21290. printed for Thomas Tegg in London in 1846 by James Nichols. In the
  21291. "Advertisement" at the front, Nichols says that this edition "is nearly
  21292. an exact reprint of the sixth"; however, he also says that the sixth
  21293. edition was "carelessly executed," and that in his edition "considerable
  21294. pains have been bestowed on the punctuation." The punctuation of this
  21295. edition differs considerably from that of the editions preferred today.
  21296. In those few places where the quotations in Cambridge and Macmillan
  21297. differed from this edition, we have brought them into conformity
  21298. with it.
  21299.  
  21300. t xii.8 deleted comma after 'cosmology' (M vi.25; C vi.15); changed 'bring'
  21301. to 'brings' (M vi.26; C vi.16)
  21302.  
  21303. f xii.25 changed 'them' to 'their' (M vii.IO)
  21304.  
  21305. t xiv.20 decapitalized 'the' (M x.3)
  21306.  
  21307. t xvii.26 decapitalized 'between' (M 3.22; C v.25)— We have made the cap-
  21308. italization in the Table of Contents consistent without further notation.
  21309.  
  21310. t xviii.18 inserted comma after 'namely' (M 4.8; C xii.7)
  21311.  
  21312. t xviii.37 changed 'Giveness' to 'Givenness' (M 57.11)
  21313.  
  21314. t xix.10 inserted comma after 'Determined' (M 57.20)
  21315.  
  21316. t xix.22 italicized 'Essay' (M 57.32; C xiii.l)
  21317.  
  21318. ** xx. 11 It might be supposed that 'Lure of Feeling' is an error, since White-
  21319. head usually writes 'lure for feeling'; however, the text corresponding to
  21320. this entry in the Table of Contents has 'lures of feeling' (88.3) .
  21321.  
  21322. t xx.13 inserted comma after 'Environment' (M 58.29)
  21323.  
  21324. t xx. 32 changed 'Trivial ty' here and in following line . to 'Triviality'
  21325. (M 59.8, 9)
  21326.  
  21327. t xx. 3 5 changed 'Co-ordination' to 'Coordination' (C xiv.ll)— Macmillan
  21328. usually did not hyphenate 'coordination' and 'coordinate'; Cambridge
  21329. always did. We have, usually without further notation, written these
  21330. words without the hyphen.
  21331.  
  21332. t xxi.7 changed 'Amplifyer' to 'Amplifier' (M 59.23)
  21333.  
  21334. t xxii.23 changed comma after 'Feeling' to colon (M 60.40; C xv.37)
  21335.  
  21336. f xxii.3 1 changed semicolon after 'Misconceptions' to colon (M 61.8)
  21337.  
  21338. f xxiii.5 changed 'Propositions' to 'The Propositions' (M 61.23)
  21339.  
  21340. * xxiii.29 'Samples' is evidently used here as a verb.
  21341.  
  21342. t xxiii.35 changed comma after 'Spatialization' to semicolon and comma after
  21343. 'Fluency' to colon (M 62.14; C xvii.3)
  21344.  
  21345.  
  21346.  
  21347. 394 Editors' Notes
  21348.  
  21349. t 18.2 While correcting proofs, Whitehead changed the title of this chapter
  21350. from "The Categorical Scheme" to "The Categoreal Scheme." Mac-
  21351. millan, unlike Cambridge, did not change the running heads accord-
  21352. ingly. We have made these changes without further notation.
  21353.  
  21354. f 1832 capitalized 'Cartesian' (M 28.11)
  21355.  
  21356. f 18.34 Macmillan inserted the abbreviations 'Bk./ 'Ch/ and 'Sect/ into
  21357. this reference, the first one to Locke's Essay within the body of the
  21358. work (C 25.8). For the edition used, see the note for xi fn.l.
  21359.  
  21360. f 18.35 put quoted words in double instead of single quotation marks
  21361. (M 28.14-15; C 25.8-9)
  21362.  
  21363. i 19.40 changed 'MonodoZogy' to 'Monadology 9 (M 29.28; C 26.19)— This
  21364. change was made by Whitehead throughout his Macmillan copy. We
  21365. have incorporated this correction without further notation.
  21366.  
  21367. f 20 fn.2 added Tress' (M 30 fn.2)
  21368.  
  21369. $ 21.1 capitalized 'Category' (M 31.8)— Both editions were hopelessly in-
  21370. consistent in the matter of capitalizing references to particular cate-
  21371. gories. There are three major types of references involved: (1) Expres-
  21372. sions such as 'fourth category of explanation' and 'ninth categoreal
  21373. obligation' were usually not capitalized, but occasionally were — e.g.,
  21374. 'fourth Category of Explanation/ (2) Whitehead often used Roman
  21375. numerals to refer to the categoreal obligations. Such references in the
  21376. present chapter were uncapitalized — e.g., 'category (iv)' — in conformity
  21377. with the fact that the Roman numerals were not capitalized in the
  21378. initial listing of the categoreal obligations in this chapter. Later in the
  21379. book, the Roman numerals were capitalized, in conformity with the
  21380. presentation of the categoreal obligations in Part III. The word 'cate-
  21381. gory' preceding the Roman numeral was also capitalized— e.g., 'Cate-
  21382. gory IV/ However, when the term 'categoreal condition' was used, it
  21383. was left uncapitalized, even though the Roman numeral was capitalized—
  21384. e.g., 'categoreal condition IV.' (3) In references to 'the Category of the
  21385. Ultimate,' and to particular categoreal obligations which designate them
  21386. by name (e.g., 'the Category of Transmutation'), either the name of
  21387. the category, or both it and the term 'category' (or 'categoreal condi-
  21388. tion'), were very frequently capitalized. In a couple of places (here and
  21389. 247.27), Cambridge capitalized the entire reference which Macmillan
  21390. had left partially or wholly uncapitalized. On the basis of these prece-
  21391. dents, and of the high frequency with which instances of this third type
  21392. were already capitalized, we capitalized (without further notation) the
  21393. remaining instances of this third type. However, there was no similar
  21394. justification for bringing consistency into the references of the first and
  21395. second types.
  21396.  
  21397. * 21.14 In the margin of his Macmillan copy, Whitehead wrote: " 'Poten-
  21398.  
  21399. tiality' is closely allied to 'disjunctive diversity/ "
  21400.  
  21401. * 21.18 In the margin of his Macmillan copy, Whitehead wrote: "cf. p. 47/'
  21402.  
  21403. The reference is to 31.29 of this corrected edition.
  21404.  
  21405. + 22.17 changed period after 'Prehension' in previous line to comma and in-
  21406. serted 'or Patterned Entities.' (M 33.6; C 29.28)— This change was
  21407. made by Whitehead in his Macmillan copy.
  21408.  
  21409. i 22.29 inserted 'in disjunctive diversity' (M 33.21; C 30.7)— This change
  21410. was made by Whitehead in his Macmillan copy.
  21411.  
  21412. * 22.35 In the margin of his Macmillan copy, Whitehead wrote: "cf. Plato's
  21413.  
  21414. Sophist 247 i.e. disjunctive diversity is potentiality."
  21415. f 22.36 deleted comma after 'actuality' (M 33.30; C 30.15)
  21416. t 23.4 deleted comma after 'concrescence' (M 34.7; C 30.27)
  21417.  
  21418.  
  21419.  
  21420. 396 Editors' Notes
  21421.  
  21422. t 36.39 took Tarts' out of single quotation marks (M 5428; C 50.11)
  21423.  
  21424. t 39.13 inserted 'the' before 'European' (M 63.3; C 53.15)
  21425.  
  21426. t 39.28 changed writing' to 'writings' (M 63.23)
  21427.  
  21428. ** 40.13 It has been suggested that 'orderings' should read 'ordering/ Evi-
  21429. dence for this is provided by the fact that the Table of Contents has it
  21430. in the singular. However, the content of the previous sentence in the
  21431. text, along with the use of 'such' (which normally takes a plural noun),
  21432. supports the text as it is.
  21433.  
  21434. * 40fn.l Whitehead would have, of course, been using their 1911-12 trans-
  21435.  
  21436. lation, not their 1931 corrected edition, which most scholars today use.
  21437. t 41 fn.6 took 'for' out of italics (M 65 fn.6)
  21438. t 42.1 changed 'from' to 'form' (M 66.35)— This change was included on
  21439.  
  21440. the list entitled "Misprints."
  21441. t 42.7 deleted comma after 'theory* (M 67.4; C 57.10)
  21442.  
  21443. * 42 fn.7 The quotation is from p. 455.
  21444.  
  21445. ** 43.23 It has been suggested that 'decision' should read 'decisions.'
  21446.  
  21447. * 43.29 In British usage, 'eat' can express the past tense.
  21448. t 44.24 changed 'be' to 'the' (M 70.24)
  21449.  
  21450. t 44.25 decapitalized 'he' (C 60.27)— Cambridge capitalized occurrences of
  21451. 'he' and 'him' referring to God; Macmillan did not. We have followed
  21452. Macmillan's convention without further notation.
  21453.  
  21454. * 44.32 In the margin of his Cambridge copy, Whitehead wrote: "Thus con-
  21455.  
  21456. sciousness is a factor in the subjective form of the prehension of data
  21457. as given. Cf. pp. 344, 369, on the 'affirmation-negation contrast.' "
  21458. These pages correspond to pp. 371-72 and 399 of the Macmillan edition
  21459. and to pp. 243 and 261 of this corrected edition.
  21460.  
  21461. * 44.39 In the margin of his Cambridge copy, Whitehead wrote: "Law of
  21462.  
  21463. Excluded Middle."
  21464.  
  21465. * 45.28 In the margin of his Cambridge copy, Whitehead wrote: "i.e. the
  21466.  
  21467. 'Satisfaction' is always objective. It never feels itself."
  21468. t 46.12 inserted closing quotation mark after 'God' (M 73.12)
  21469. t 46.15 changed 'efficacity' to 'efficacy' (M 73.16; C 63.12)— Both editions
  21470. sometimes had the archaic form 'efficacity' instead of 'efficacy.' The
  21471. list entitled "Misprints" drew attention to this discrepancy in reference
  21472. to Macmillan 184 (120 of this corrected edition); Cambridge changed
  21473. 'efficacity' to 'efficacy' at 316.39. We have changed the remaining in-
  21474. stances to 'efficacy' without further notation.
  21475. t 46.24 put quotation mark before 'the' here and in preceding line instead of
  21476.  
  21477. before 'multiplicity' and 'class' (M 73.28-29)
  21478. t 47.17 deleted 'only' after 'illustrated' (M 74.38; C 64.31)— The presence
  21479. of 'only' produced a contradiction between this sentence and the follow-
  21480. ing one. This 'only' was perhaps transposed by the typist from the
  21481. following sentence.
  21482. t 49.33 italicized 'Meditations IV and 'IIV (M 78.24)
  21483.  
  21484. * 50.4 The quotation is from Shakespeare's A Midsummer-Night's Dream,
  21485.  
  21486. Act III.
  21487. f 50.6 changed 'commonsense' to 'common sense' (M 79.3)
  21488. f 50.28 deleted parentheses around 'A substance' (M 79.30; C 69.16)—
  21489.  
  21490. They (or brackets) are not needed, since this is not a direct quotation.
  21491.  
  21492. * 50fn.l3 As stated in the note for 40 fn.I, Whitehead was using the
  21493.  
  21494. 1911-12 Haldane and Ross translation; this sentence was completely
  21495.  
  21496. retranslated in their 1931 corrected edition,
  21497. t 51.5 changed 'on 7 to 'Concerning 7 (M 80.17; C 70.2)
  21498. t 51.28 capitalized 'Concerning 7 (M 81.9; C 70.29)
  21499.  
  21500.  
  21501.  
  21502. 398 Editors' Notes
  21503.  
  21504. t 75.21 changed period after 'conceive it' to comma (M 116.29; C 104.9)
  21505. t 76.9 changed well' to 'dwell' (M 117-31) — This change was made by
  21506.  
  21507. Whitehead in his Macmillan copy.
  21508. t 76.9 put both passages in double instead of single quotation marks (M
  21509.  
  21510. 117.29-31; C 105.7-9)
  21511. t 76.41 changed 'exemplication' to 'exemplification' (M 118.33)
  21512. t 76fn.8 decapitaiized 'the 9 (M 118 fn.8; C 105 fn.l)
  21513. t 77.18 changed 'synonomously' to 'synonymously' (M 119.23)
  21514. t 78.34 changed 'adventure' to 'adventures' (M 121.23; C 108.35)
  21515. f 80.1 changed 'substance' to 'substances' (M 123.19; C 110.28)— This,
  21516.  
  21517. incidentally, is a place where correcting the punctuation in quoted
  21518.  
  21519. material required adding italics.
  21520. f 80.5 inserted comma after 'substance' (M 123.25)
  21521.  
  21522. t 80.24 put 'nexus' in single instead of double quotation marks (M 124.13)
  21523. t 82.8 changed 'the' to 'a' (M 126.31: C 114.2)
  21524.  
  21525. t 82 fn.9 inserted '28A'; changed W to TlatoW (M 126 fn.9; C 113 fn.l)
  21526. t 83.17 changed comma before 'disorder' to semicolon (M 127.21; C
  21527.  
  21528. 115.20)
  21529. t 84.15 put 'final causes' in quotation marks (M 128.36; C 116.28)
  21530. t 85.9 changed double to single quotation marks (M 130.12-13; C 118.2)
  21531.  
  21532. — This is not a direct quotation: 'It' is not in the quoted passage,
  21533. t 85 fn.l inserted '10' after 'xxxvii (M 131 fn.l; C 118 fn.l)
  21534.  
  21535. * 86.15 Whitehead used The Philosophical Works of David Hume, in four
  21536.  
  21537. volumes, published in 1854 by Little, Brown and Company, Boston,
  21538. and by Adam and Charles Black, Edinburgh. The punctuation of the
  21539. Treatise in this edition differs considerably from that in editions of the
  21540. Treatise which are now more commonly used. In those few places where
  21541. the quotations in Cambridge and Macmillan differed from this edition,
  21542. we have brought them into conformity with it.
  21543.  
  21544. t 86.30 changed 'of to 'or' (M 132.25)
  21545.  
  21546. t 86.38 changed 'has never' to 'never has' (M 132.34; C 120.17)
  21547.  
  21548. t 86.42 changed 'between' to 'betwixt' (M 133.3; C 120.22)
  21549.  
  21550. f 86.44 deleted 'to' before 'raise' (M 133.6; C 120.24)
  21551.  
  21552. f 87.4 changed 'instances' to 'instance' (M 133.11)
  21553.  
  21554. t 87.35 deleted hyphen in 'threefold' (M 134.15)
  21555.  
  21556. t 87.45 changed 'an unity' to 'a unity' (M 134.28)
  21557.  
  21558. * 88.3 See the note for xx.II.
  21559.  
  21560. t 88.6 changed 'This' to 'His' (M 134.35; C 122.9) -Whitehead's hand-
  21561. written 'H' is such that it could appear to a typist to be 'TV; cf. the
  21562. notes for 139.34 and 225.36.
  21563.  
  21564. t 88.9 put closing quotation mark after 'nature' instead of after 'superjective'
  21565. (M 135.2; C 122.13) to conform to parallels above
  21566.  
  21567. t 88.13 changed 'goal' to 'goad' (M 135.8; C 122.18)-In agreement with
  21568. most other scholars consulted, we do not think that the expression 'goal
  21569. towards novelty' makes sense. Also, the presence of 'goal' in the text is
  21570. easily intelligible as a mistranscription of Whitehead's handwriting. An
  21571. objection to this change might be that the use of the word 'goad' in this
  21572. context is incompatible with Whitehead's conception as to how God
  21573. influences the world, i.e., by presenting ideals which serve as lures for
  21574. feeling. It is, however, quite normal to say that one person goads another
  21575. to action when the former insistently presents the latter with an attrac-
  21576. tive ideal.
  21577.  
  21578. ** 89.35 It has been suggested that 'a' should be inserted before 'man.'
  21579.  
  21580.  
  21581.  
  21582. 400 Editors' Notes
  21583.  
  21584. f 111.42 changed semicolon after 'character' to comma (M 170.35)
  21585.  
  21586. f 113.6 changed 'experiental' to 'experiential' (M 172.27); deleted comma
  21587.  
  21588. after 'attained' "(M 172.27; C 158.16)
  21589. } 113.11 deleted 'as' after 'aesthetic' (M 172.33)— This occurrence of 'trans-
  21590. cendental aesthetic/ unlike the other two in the immediate context, was
  21591. neither capitalized nor put in quotes. The other two clearly name a part
  21592. of the Critique, whereas this occurrence can be regarded as a reference
  21593. to its content. On this reading, it is possible that the deleted 'as'
  21594. was a mistranscription from an V originally completing the word
  21595. 'aesthetics.'
  21596.  
  21597. * 113.20 In his Macmillan copy, Whitehead underlined 'responsive con-
  21598.  
  21599. formity of feeling' and wrote "cf. p. 53" in the margin. The reference
  21600. is to pp. 35-36 of this corrected edition; cf. the note for 36.1.
  21601. t 113.34 deleted comma after 'question* (M 173.25; C 159.12)
  21602. t 114.24 changed 'for' to 'from' (M 174.34^
  21603. t 114.42 changed 'show' to 'shows' (M 175.20; C 161.5)
  21604. t 115.34 deleted comma after 'feelings' (M 176.29; C 162.11)
  21605. t 116.41 changed 'experiment' to 'experient' (M 178.20-21; C 163.37)
  21606. t 117.35 changed 'anything' to 'any thing' (M 179.33; C 165.10)
  21607. t 117 fn.l inserted 'Bk.I/ (M 179fn.l; C 165 fn.l)— The references to the
  21608. Treatise were not uniform: sometimes 'Treatise' was omitted; sometimes
  21609. the Part; and always the Book. We have, without further notation,
  21610. brought all footnote references to the Treatise into standard form.
  21611.  
  21612. * 117 fn.2 The italics in this quotation were also (as in the one before it)
  21613.  
  21614. not in the original.
  21615.  
  21616. t 118.8 inserted hyphens in 'such-and-such' here (M 180.14-15; C 165.25-
  21617. 26) and in lines 10 and 18 (M 180.16-17 & 27-28; C 165.28, 166.2)
  21618.  
  21619. t 118.11 changed 'though' to 'through' (M 180.19)— This change was in-
  21620. cluded on the list entitled "Misprints."
  21621.  
  21622. t 118.23 deleted comma after 'conclusion' (C 166.9)
  21623.  
  21624. t 118.29 inserted 'to us' (M 181.4; C 166.13)
  21625.  
  21626. f 119.36 changed 'nexus' to 'nexus' (M 182.32: C 168.2)— This change was
  21627. made by Whitehead in his Macmillan copy.
  21628.  
  21629. t 120.1 changed 'gives' to 'give' (M 183.6; C 168.11)
  21630.  
  21631. t 120.6 changed 'vector-character' to 'vector character' (M 183.12-13; C
  21632. 168.17) to conform to the usual spelling
  21633.  
  21634. f 120.19 changed %' (M 183.29) and 'S' (C 168.35) to 'S/-This change
  21635. was made by Whitehead in his Macmillan copy.
  21636.  
  21637. + 121.11 changed 'be' to 'have been' and inserted 'a' before 'missile' (M
  21638. 185.1; C 170.6)
  21639.  
  21640. t 121.30 inserted dash after 'immediacy (M 185.27)
  21641.  
  21642. t 121 fn.4 changed 'of to 'cf.' (M 185 fn.4; C 170 fn.l)— This change was
  21643. made by Whitehead in his Macmillan copy.
  21644.  
  21645. t 121 fn. 5 changed 'Meaning and Importance' to 'Meaning and Effect ';
  21646. changed 'Macmillan' to '(New York: Macmillan, 1927; Cambridge
  21647. University Press, 1928)' (M 185 fn.5; C 170 fn.2) -Parentheses were
  21648. introduced to distinguish clearly the data relating to the lectures from
  21649. that referring to the publications. It might be inferred that 'Meaning
  21650. and Importance' was used in the title of the lectures; however, White-
  21651. head's letter to the University, and the announcement in the Univer-
  21652. sity's newspaper, had the following as the announced topic: "Symbolic
  21653. Expression, Its Function for the Individual and for Society."
  21654.  
  21655. t 123.42 changed 'ways' to 'way' (M 189.5; C 174.2)— The following sen-
  21656.  
  21657.  
  21658.  
  21659. 402 Editors' Notes
  21660.  
  21661. was responsible for the Index, it was not done with great care — e.g.,
  21662. the important footnote on p. 333 was not indexed. Also, it is noteworthy
  21663. that the Cambridge edition had the '-scopic 7 and '-cosmic' occurrences
  21664. correctly indexed.
  21665. f 131.21 changed 'colored' to 'coloured' (M 200.2)
  21666. f 131.24 changed 'change' to 'chance' (M 200.4; C 183.34)
  21667. f 131.25 changed 'would' to 'should' (M 200.5; C 18335)
  21668. t 132.1 changed 'the' before 'substance' to 'a' (M 200.25; C 184.19)
  21669.  
  21670. * 132 fn. 7 For the edition quoted, see the note for 86.15.
  21671.  
  21672. f 133.10 deleted comma after 'freedom' (M 202.19; C 186.5)
  21673.  
  21674. * 133.16 The italics are Whitehead's.
  21675.  
  21676. t 134.27 deleted 'that' before 'this' (M 204.17; C 187.37)
  21677. f 134.29 changed single to double quotation marks (M 204.20-21; C 187.
  21678. 40-188.1)
  21679.  
  21680. * 134.41 These latter italics are also Hume's.
  21681.  
  21682. t 135.3 deleted 'by' before 'the nature' (M 205.5; C 188.19)
  21683. t 135.29 changed single to double quotation marks; changed 'Ideas' to 'the
  21684. Idea'; and decapitalized 'external' (M 206.5-6; C 189.18-19)
  21685.  
  21686. * 135 fn.9 The passage to which Whitehead refers does not come at the end
  21687.  
  21688. of the Appendix in some editions of the Treatise, e.g., that of Selby-
  21689. Bigge, but is followed by other material. The last three sentences of
  21690. the edition Whitehead used (see the note for 86.15) read: "The second
  21691. error may be found in [Bk.I, Part III, Sect. VII], where I say, that two
  21692. ideas of the same object can only be different by their different degrees
  21693. of force and vivacity. I believe there are other differences among ideas,
  21694. which cannot properly be comprehended under these terms. Had I said,
  21695. that two ideas of the same object can only be different by their different
  21696. feeling, I should have been nearer the truth."
  21697.  
  21698. t 137.7 moved closing bracket from after 'time' to after 'such' (M 208.2;
  21699. C 191.13)
  21700.  
  21701. f 137.20 changed 'endeavor' to 'endeavour' (M 208.20)
  21702.  
  21703. * 138.15 Whitehead used an edition (cf. the note for xi fn.l) based on
  21704.  
  21705. Locke's English arrangement of the introductory material, not one based
  21706. on Coste's French translation. In editions following Coste's arrange-
  21707. ment, such as that of Campbell Fraser, the reference here would be
  21708. 'Introduction, 8.'
  21709. t 138.18 changed '6 and T to '6' (M 20936; C 193.8) -Although the
  21710. quoted material is only from Sect. 6, Whitehead perhaps wanted to
  21711. draw attention to some material in Sect. 7.
  21712.  
  21713. * 138 fn.l 3 Whitehead means that the italics throughout the remainder of
  21714.  
  21715. this paragraph are his.
  21716. t 13934 changed 'thence' to 'hence' (M 212.1); changed 'This' to 'His'
  21717.  
  21718. (M 212.2; C 195.7)— Cf. the note for 88.6.
  21719. t 139 fn.l 5 changed footnote to its present reading from 'Cf. treatise, Bk.
  21720.  
  21721. Ill, Sects. V and VI' (M 211 fn.l 5; C 194 fn.l)
  21722. t 139 fn.16 put 'Transcendental Logic in quotation marks and changed
  21723.  
  21724. 'Intro. I' to 'Introduction, Sect. Y (M 211 fn.16; C 195 fn.l) for the
  21725.  
  21726. sake of consistency
  21727. t 14038 changed 'founded in' (M 213.25) and 'founded on' (C 196.27) to
  21728.  
  21729. 'found in'
  21730. t 141.8 changed 'reflections' to 'reflection' (M 214.2-3)
  21731.  
  21732. * 142.23 The quotation is from Scepticism and Animal Faith, Ch s 7=
  21733. f 142.27 changed 'in' to 'is' (M 216.11)
  21734.  
  21735. t 1433 decapitalized 'books' (M 216.35; C 199.29)— References elsewhere
  21736. to the books of Locke's Essay are not capitalized.
  21737.  
  21738.  
  21739.  
  21740. 404 Editors' Notes
  21741.  
  21742. which is the "subjectivist principle"— which is "mitigated" by Descartes 7
  21743. use of "realitas objectiva" We could have achieved the same effect by
  21744. changing 'sensationalist principle" to 'sensationalist doctrine/ since the
  21745. sensationalist doctrine includes the subjectivist principle and hence
  21746. would likewise be mitigated by one who sometimes referred to real ob-
  21747. jects. But we thought it more likely that Whitehead intended 'subjec-
  21748. tivist principle/ For one thing, that is the term used in the previous
  21749. sentence. Also, the inadvertent substitution of 'sensationalist' for 'sub-
  21750. jectivist' seems more likely than the substitution of 'principle' for
  21751. 'doctrine/ especially given the previous paragraphs.
  21752. f 158.29 changed 'generalization' to 'generalizations' (M 240.17: C 221.9)
  21753.  
  21754. to conform to the following sentence and to 159.17
  21755. t 158.43 inserted comma after 'is' (M 240.36)
  21756. t 159.10 deleted comma after 'experiences' (M 241.14; C 222.4)
  21757. f 159.36 inserted comma after 'muddle' (M 242.10)
  21758. f 159.42 inserted single quotation mark before 'realitas' (M 242.17)
  21759. f 160.6 deleted comma after 'mind' (M 242.30; C 223.19)
  21760. f 160.9 changed 'an' to 'a' (M 242.33)
  21761.  
  21762. * 160.19 The quotation is from the Treatise, Bk. I, Part I, Sect. I.
  21763.  
  21764. r 160.26 moved comma from outside to inside the quotation marks (M
  21765.  
  21766. 243.17)
  21767. f 161.29 changed exclamation point to question mark (M 245.2)
  21768. t 161.37 inserted 'in' after 'is' (M 245.13)
  21769. t 162.6 changed comma to semicolon (M 245.28)
  21770. t 163.2 changed 'feelings' to 'feeling' (M 247.6)
  21771. t 163.4 inserted comma after 'world' (M 247.8^
  21772. f 163.22 changed 'are' to 'is' (M 247.32)
  21773.  
  21774. t 164.4 inserted comma after 'prehensions' (M 248.27; C 229.9)
  21775. t 164.27 put 'conformal' in quotation marks (M 249.19; C 230.3)
  21776. t 164.35 changed 'earlier' to 'latter' (M 249.29; C 230.12)— 'Latter' is used
  21777.  
  21778. instead of 'later' to conform to 165.36 and 166.5.
  21779. f 165.14 inserted comma after 'example' (M 250.22)
  21780. t 166.2 changed 'synthetized' to 'synthesized' (M 251.28)
  21781. ** 166.36 This is clearly not a reference to the "subjectivist principle" as
  21782.  
  21783. denned in the opening section of this chapter at 157.28-29; the same is
  21784.  
  21785. true of the reference at 167.13. For one thing, the definition on 157
  21786.  
  21787. is of a principle which Whitehead rejects, whereas these latter two
  21788.  
  21789. references are to a principle which he accepts.
  21790. ** 167.13 See the note for 166.36.
  21791.  
  21792. t 167.17 changed 'presentation' to 'presentational' (M 253.29)
  21793. t 167.31 changed all four instances of 'res veroe y on this Daze to l res verae'
  21794.  
  21795. (M 254.10, 14, 28)
  21796. t 167.37 changed 'conscresence' to 'concrescence' (M 254.18)
  21797. t 171.2 changed 'sense' to 'sensa' (M 259.19; C 240.13)
  21798. t 171.3 changed 'justaposition' to 'juxtaposition' (M 259.20-21)
  21799.  
  21800. * 171 fn.l The words 'sensation 7 and 'reflection 7 were italicized in the
  21801.  
  21802. original.
  21803. t 172.35 changed 'grey-colour' to 'grey colour' (M 262.8)
  21804. t 172.37 changed 'sensation' to 'sensations' (M 262.10-11)
  21805. f 173.12 decapitalized 'dynamics' (M 262.37; C 243.27)
  21806. f 173.15 inserted comma after 'always' (M 263.2)
  21807. f 173.16 changed 'interpretive' to 'interpretative' (M 263.4)
  21808. f 173.28 deleted commas after 'problem' and 'perception' (M 263.17-18)
  21809. f 174.9 took 'Critiques' out of single quotation marks and italicized it (M
  21810.  
  21811. 264.14; C 245.2) for the sake of consistency
  21812.  
  21813.  
  21814.  
  21815. Editors' Notes 405
  21816.  
  21817. t 174.15 changed 'behavior' to 'behaviour' (M 264.22) to conform to the
  21818. usual spelling of both editions
  21819.  
  21820. t 175.7 changed 'are' to 'is' (M 265.29; C 246.15)
  21821.  
  21822. t 175.27 deleted comma after 'dogma' (M 266.19)
  21823.  
  21824. t 175.29 inserted comma after 'Besides' (M 266.21)
  21825.  
  21826. t 176.22 changed 'experience' to 'experiences' (M 267.30)
  21827.  
  21828. t 176.23 italicized 'hand' (M 26732; C 248.15) to correspond to 'eye'
  21829.  
  21830. t 176.35 deleted 'to' after 'descend' (M 268.10; C 248.29) -The discussion
  21831. was already about 'organic being.'
  21832.  
  21833. t 177.9 deleted' comma after 'definition' (M 268.34)
  21834.  
  21835. t 177.40 changed 'spatiatization' to 'spatialization' (M 269.34)
  21836.  
  21837. t 179.12 changed 'produce' to 'produces' (M 271.38)— This change was in-
  21838. cluded on the list entitled "Misprints."
  21839.  
  21840. f 179.23 changed 'principle' to 'principal' (M 272.15)
  21841.  
  21842. f 179.25 changed 'sensations' to 'sensation' (M 272.16-17; C 252.32)
  21843.  
  21844. t 179.26 changed 'discernable' to 'discernible' (M 272.18)
  21845.  
  21846. t 179.32 changed 'conjectually' to 'conjecturally' (M 272.26)
  21847.  
  21848. t 179.45 changed 'experiental' to 'experiential' (M 273.4)
  21849.  
  21850. M80.7^ changed 'are' to 'is' (M 273.13; C 253.27)
  21851.  
  21852. ** 180.11 Some have suggested that 'construed' should be changed to 'con-
  21853. structed/ but we believe that the text is correct as it stands.
  21854.  
  21855. t 180.13 deleted comma after 'organs' (M 273.21; C 253.34)
  21856.  
  21857. f 181.9 inserted 'with' before 'which' (M 274.32)
  21858.  
  21859. t 181.15 inserted 'as' after 'far' (M 275.4)
  21860.  
  21861. f 181.42 changed 'percept' to 'percepta' and deleted comma after 'symbols'
  21862. (M 276.2) — The first change was made by Whitehead in his Macmillan
  21863. copy.
  21864.  
  21865. f 181.44 changed 'precipient' to percipient' (M 276.6)
  21866.  
  21867. t 182.28 inserted comma after 'word'^M 277.3)
  21868.  
  21869. t 182.38 deleted 'of after 'suggest' (M 277.16)
  21870.  
  21871. t 184.33 italicized 'Logic' (M 281.10)
  21872.  
  21873. t 184.35 inserted 'a' after 'is' (M 281.13)
  21874.  
  21875. t 185.42 changed 'in' to 'is' (M 282.29)
  21876.  
  21877. t 185.44 inserted 'a' before 'new' (M 282.31)
  21878.  
  21879. f 187.10 inserted comma after 'of (M 284.25)
  21880.  
  21881. f 187.13 changed 'a non-conformal proposition is' to 'non-conformal proposi-
  21882. tions are' (M 284.29-30)— As usual, the change made by Cambridge
  21883. was an improvement, since the following sentence uses the plural pro-
  21884. noun.
  21885.  
  21886. f 187.17 inserted comma after 'entities' (M 284.34; C 264.26)
  21887.  
  21888. f 187.22 inserted 'of before 'feeling' (M 2853)
  21889.  
  21890. t 18732 inserted '(i),' after 'Either' and changed 'satisfaction' to 'satisfac-
  21891. tions' (M 285.16)
  21892.  
  21893. f 187.43 changed 'data. But' to 'data, but' (M 28531)
  21894.  
  21895. f 188.27 inserted comma after 'entities' (M 286.31)
  21896.  
  21897. f 18839 deleted comma after 'entity' (M ?« 7 9; C 26634)
  21898.  
  21899. f 189.9 decapitalized 'the' (M 287.27; C 267.14)^
  21900.  
  21901. * 189.12 The word 'abrupt was not italicized in Science and the Modern
  21902. World, but Whitehead evidently wanted it stressed here.
  21903.  
  21904. f 189.14 inserted 'graded' before 'envisagernent' (M 28734; C 267.19)
  21905.  
  21906. f 189.18 changed 'VI' to 'IF (M 288.1)
  21907.  
  21908. f 189.20 inserted comma after 'hand' (M 288.4; C 267.25)
  21909.  
  21910. f 190.27 changed both instances of 'illusioriness' to 'illusoriness' (M 289.30,
  21911.  
  21912. 31)
  21913. f 190.44 inserted 'a' before 'proposition' (M 290.14; C 26934)
  21914.  
  21915.  
  21916.  
  21917. 406 Editors' Notes
  21918.  
  21919. t 191.15 changed 'experiment' to 'experient' (M 29036; C 270.18)
  21920. t 191.21 deleted comma after 'suspension' (M 291.5)
  21921. t 191.36 inserted 'a' before 'feeling' (M 291.26; C 2*71.6)
  21922. ** 191.43 Whitehead's sentence can lead to confusion as to which of the
  21923. two senses is the 'latter.' Some scholars have thought a change to be
  21924. necessary. But we believe that the text is correct, with the 'latter' sense
  21925. being the one introduced second in the previous paragraph, i.e., in the
  21926. sentence at 191.37-40.
  21927. t 192.22 changed 'on' to 'in' (M 292.28; C 272.7)
  21928. t 192.40 deleted comma after 'background' (M 293.13; C 272.28)
  21929. t 193.15 inserted comma after 'include' (M 294.2)
  21930. t 193 fn.l changed 'Ch. VI' to 'Ch. V (M 293 fn.l; C 273 fn.l)
  21931. t 196.26 inserted 'a' between 'of and 'more' (M 298.34; C 278.6)
  21932. t 197.6 deleted comma after 'direct' (M 299.28)
  21933.  
  21934. t 197.19 inserted hyphen in 'judgment-feelings' (M 300.7; C 279.14) —
  21935. Cambridge always printed this expression without the hyphen; Mac-
  21936. millan sometimes inserted it. In bringing consistency into the text,
  21937. which we have done without further notation, we chose to use the
  21938. hyphen, since 'judgment' is not an adjective.
  21939. f 197.21 changed 'terms' to 'term' (M 300.10)
  21940. t 197.39 inserted hyphen in 'truth-value' (M 300.33)
  21941. t 198.20 deleted commas after 'analogous' and 'simple' (M 301.27; C 280.31-
  21942.  
  21943. 32) to conform to similar passages
  21944. * 198 fn.2 The asterisk in this footnote is not ours, but is part of the refer-
  21945. ence to Principia.
  21946. f 200.27 inserted comma after 'Thus' (M 305.2)
  21947.  
  21948. t 201.27 changed 'next section' to 'next two sections' (M 306.17; C 285.13)
  21949. — Whitehead evidently added one more section than he had intended
  21950. when writing this passage; cf. the note for 206.35.
  21951. t 201.30 changed 'relevant' to 'relative' (M 306.21; C 285.16)
  21952. f 201.34 inserted comma after 'reason' (M 306.27)
  21953.  
  21954. t 202.10 changed 'as to which set—favourable or unfavourable— the proposi-
  21955. tion belongs' to the present reading (M 307.16-17)
  21956. t 202.36 deleted comma after 'overcome' (M 308.12)
  21957. t 202.41 deleted comma after 'ground' (M 308.19)
  21958. t 202.43 inserted 'an' after 'have' (M 308.21; C 287.13)
  21959. f 203.13 changed 'these' to 'there' (M 309.2)
  21960. t 203.21 deleted comma after 'induction' (M 309.13)
  21961. t 204.18 changed 'derivation' to 'divination' (M 310.28; C 289.15)
  21962. t 206.19 inserted comma after 'depend' (M 313.32)
  21963.  
  21964. f 206.21 changed 'require that exact statistical calculations are' (M 313.35)
  21965. and 'require exact statistical calculations to be' (C 292.14) to the
  21966. present reading
  21967. f 206.32 deleted comma after 'theory' and inserted commas after 'which'
  21968.  
  21969. and 'me' (M 314.10)
  21970. t 206.35 changed 'two' to 'three' (M 314.13; C 292.29)-Cf. the note for
  21971.  
  21972. 201.27.
  21973. f 207.5 changed brackets around 'by (hi)' to commas (M 314.31; C 293.8)
  21974. t 208.9 changed 'banquetting' to 'banqueting' (M 317.11; C 295.10)
  21975. t 208.25 deleted comma after 'flow' (M 317.32; C 295.31)
  21976. t 208.29 inserted 'that with which' after 'as' (M 318.3)
  21977. t 209.22 changed 'difference' to 'different' (M 319.3)
  21978. t 210.7 italicized 'concrescence' (M 320.4; C 297.36)— It is parallel with
  21979.  
  21980.  
  21981.  
  21982. Editors Notes 407
  21983.  
  21984. 'transition' (and both terms are put in quotation marks in the following
  21985. paragraph ) .
  21986.  
  21987. t 211.9 put quotation mark before 'the' instead of before 'novel' (M
  21988. 321.26)
  21989.  
  21990. ** 211.24 It has been suggested that 'relative' ought to read 'relatively/
  21991. but we believe that this change would be incorrect.
  21992.  
  21993. f 211.25 deleted comma after 'concrescence' (M 322.10; C 300.1)
  21994.  
  21995. f 211.30 deleted comma after 'alien' (M 322.17; C 300.7)— This change
  21996. was made by Whitehead in his Macmillan copy.
  21997.  
  21998. ** 212.37 It might be thought that the twofold reference in this paragraph
  21999. to the 'principle of relativity/ which is the fourth category of explana-
  22000. tion (and is often referred to as such), as the third metaphysical prin-
  22001. ciple is erroneous. However, it is possible that this paragraph was
  22002. incorporated from Whitehead's GifFord Lectures (which were greatly
  22003. revised and expanded for publication)- and that this reference reflects
  22004. a numbering used therein for some of his metaphysical principles, such
  22005. as the ontological principle, and the principles of process and of rela-
  22006. tivity; compare 22.35-40, 23.26-29, and 24.35-39 with 149.37-40 and
  22007. 166.27-42.
  22008.  
  22009. t 213.11 inserted closing quotation mark after 'passing on' (M 324,30)
  22010.  
  22011. t 213 fn.l changed 'II, XXI, 1' to 'Essay, II, XXI, 3' (M 325 fn.l; C 302
  22012. fn.l)
  22013.  
  22014. t 214-5 changed 'negations' to 'negation' (M 326.2)
  22015.  
  22016. t 214.6 deleted comma after 'irrelevance' (M 326.3)
  22017.  
  22018. t 214.26 inserted 'of before 'the full' (M 326.28; C 304.14)
  22019.  
  22020. f 214.29 changed 'rnascroscopic' to 'macroscopic' (M 326.32) — This change
  22021. was included on the list entitled "Misprints."
  22022.  
  22023. t 214.35 changed 'in' to 'is' (M 327.4)
  22024.  
  22025. f 215.21 changed 'rnascroscopic' to 'macroscopic' (M 327.38)
  22026.  
  22027. t 215.26 changed '2d' to '2nd' (M 328.6)
  22028.  
  22029. t 219.8 changed 'genetic-theory' to 'genetic theory' here and in line 11
  22030. (M 334.38, 335.4)
  22031.  
  22032. t 219.15 changed 'already-constituted 7 to 'already constituted' (M 335.9)
  22033.  
  22034. t 219.37 changed 'objective' to 'objective' (M 336.1)
  22035.  
  22036. t 220.3 inserted 'a' before 'given' (M 336.6; C 310.13)
  22037.  
  22038. I 221.25 changed 'datum' to 'data' (M 338.16; C 312.20)
  22039.  
  22040. ** 222.35 When Whitehead was writing this material he evidently had not
  22041. yet formulated the ninth categoreal condition, that of 'Freedom and
  22042. Determination' (cf. 27.41). However, although there are six categoreal
  22043. conditions beyond the three discussed in the present chapter, we have
  22044. let 'five' stand, since 'Freedom and Determination' is not discussed as
  22045. a categoreal condition in the following material; cf. 248.6 and the note
  22046. for 278.6.
  22047.  
  22048. f 224.31 changed 'in' to 'into' (M 343.3; C 317.3)
  22049.  
  22050. t 224.32 deleted comma after 'process' (M 343.5; C 317.5)
  22051.  
  22052. f 225.18 inserted comma after 'But' (M 344.8)
  22053.  
  22054. f 225.21 put 'creativity' on previous line in quotation marks (M 344.9); put
  22055. 'temporal creatures' in quotation marks (M 344.10; C 318.8)
  22056.  
  22057. t 225.36 changed 'There' to 'Here' (M 344.30; C 318.25)— Cf. the note
  22058. for 88.6.
  22059.  
  22060. f 226.6 inserted comma after 'entities' (M 345.12; C 319.8)
  22061.  
  22062. j 226.32 changed 'phrase' to 'phase' (M 346.8)
  22063.  
  22064. f 226.40 deleted comma after 'itself (M 346.17; C 320.11)
  22065.  
  22066.  
  22067.  
  22068. 408 Editors' Notes
  22069.  
  22070. t 227.36 This paragraph was originally preceded by the paragraph which now
  22071. closes this section.
  22072.  
  22073. t 228.5 inserted hyphen in 'class-theory' (M 348.20)
  22074.  
  22075. f 228.7 inserted 'Bk.I,' (M 348.23; C 322.14)
  22076.  
  22077. t 228.16 This paragraph originally appeared two paragraphs higher, i.e., prior
  22078. to the paragraph beginning 'The third category. . . .'
  22079.  
  22080. t 229.43 changed 'are' to 'is' (M 351.3; C 324.28)
  22081.  
  22082. t 230.24 deleted comma after 'percipient' (M 351.36; C 325.23)
  22083.  
  22084. t 231.39 changed 'constitutions' to 'constitution' (M 353.36; C 327.21)
  22085.  
  22086. t 232.10 changed 'is' (M 354.18) and 'in a' (C 328.4) to 'in'-This is a
  22087. place where the Cambridge editor "miscorrected" the text; Whitehead
  22088. uses this and similar expressions (i.e., without an article) several times,
  22089. e.g., in the latter part of the same sentence.
  22090.  
  22091. f 232.29 changed commas after 'entity' and 'object' to semicolons (M
  22092. 355.5, 6)
  22093.  
  22094. ** 233.22 Many scholars have thought that some of the instances of 'quali-
  22095. tative' in this paragraph should have been 'quantitative,' but we believe
  22096. the text to be correct. To see how two types of pattern are involved,
  22097. the reader will be aided by mentally inserting 'quantitative' before each
  22098. 'intensive.'
  22099.  
  22100. f 233.34 changed 'iself to 'itself (M 356.35)
  22101.  
  22102. t 234.19 inserted 'is' after 'which' (M 357.35; C 331.16); deleted 'displays'
  22103. after 'tone quality' (C 331.17)— This is another place at which the
  22104. Cambridge editor "miscorrected" the text.
  22105.  
  22106. t 234.21 changed comma after 'separate' to dash (M 358.1; C 331.19)
  22107.  
  22108. t 235.29 changed 'determinations' to 'determination' (M 359.33; C 333.10)
  22109.  
  22110. t 237.27 deleted comma after 'effect' (M 363.12; C 336.5)
  22111.  
  22112. t 239.3 inserted comma after 'Further' (M 365.25)
  22113.  
  22114. f 240.11 deleted comma after 'conceptual' (M 367.16; C 340.2)
  22115.  
  22116. t 241.2 inserted comma after 'object' (M 368.24)
  22117.  
  22118. t 242.23 changed 'this' to 'his' (M 370.30; C 343.13)
  22119.  
  22120. t 242.27 took 'e.g.' out of italics (M 370.35)
  22121.  
  22122. t 242.41 inserted 'Bk.I,' (M 371.15; C 343.32-33)
  22123.  
  22124. t 242.43 changed single to double quotation marks (M 371.15-18)
  22125.  
  22126. t 244.25 moved take-out quotation mark from after 'society' (M 373.29;
  22127. C 344.29) to end of sentence
  22128.  
  22129. t 245.37 deleted comma after 'simple' (M 375.26; C 347.19)
  22130.  
  22131. t 247.42 deleted comma after 'chapter' (M 378.34)
  22132.  
  22133. * 248.6 Cf. the notes for 222.35 and 278.6.
  22134.  
  22135. t 248.14 inserted 'of before 'the nexus' (M 379.18; C 351.2)— Cf. 26.36.
  22136.  
  22137. * 250.10 In his Macmillan copy, Whitehead underlined 'The Category of
  22138.  
  22139. Reversion is then abolished' and wrote "cf. p. 40" in the margin. The
  22140.  
  22141. reference is to p. 26 of this corrected edition.
  22142. t 251.13 deleted commas after 'one' and 'same' (M 384.3; C 355.15-16)
  22143. t 253.9 changed 'cf. Ch.V, and also' to 'Ch.V; cf. also' (M 386.38; C 358.8)
  22144. t 254.2 changed 'transmuted' to 'transmitted' (M 388.11; C 359.15)
  22145. t 254.42 changed 'subject' to 'subjective' (M 389.25)
  22146. ** 255.19 It has been suggested that 'Aesthetic Harmony' should be changed
  22147.  
  22148. to 'Subjective Harmony,' but this expression seems to be simply an
  22149.  
  22150. alternative way of referring to Categoreal Obligation VII. (This is one
  22151.  
  22152. of the places where we added the capitalization; cf. the note for 21.1.)
  22153. % 255.26 This paragraph was originally followed by the two paragraphs which
  22154.  
  22155. now appear prior to the last paragraph of Section V of the following
  22156.  
  22157. chapter; cf. the note for 264.15.
  22158.  
  22159.  
  22160.  
  22161. Editors' Notes 409
  22162.  
  22163. t 256.32 changed 'seventeenth' to 'eighteenth* (M 392.10-11; C 363.6)
  22164. f 256fn.l deleted comma after 'Cf.' (M 391 fn.l)
  22165.  
  22166. t 257.29 In his Cambridge copy, Whitehead indicated that '(qua possi-
  22167. bility)' should be inserted in the text after 'referent' (M 393.17;
  22168. C 364.9).
  22169. t 257.36 inserted comma after 'eternal object' (M 393.25; C 364.17);
  22170.  
  22171. changed 'nexus' to 'nexus' (M 393.26; C 364.18)
  22172. t 259.5 inserted 'a' before 'datum' (M 395.24; C 366.13)
  22173. t 259.27 deleted comma after 'subjects' (M 396.16; C 367.4)
  22174. t 261.10 changed 'predicate' to 'predicative' (M 398.31; C 369.16)
  22175. t 261.43 This paragraph was originally preceded by the paragraph which now
  22176.  
  22177. appears prior to the last paragraph of this section.
  22178. + 262.44 This paragraph originally appeared as the second paragraph of this
  22179.  
  22180. section.
  22181. t 263.10 deleted comma after 'feeling' (M 401.32; C 372.11)
  22182. t 264.15 This and the following paragraph originally appeared at the end of
  22183. Chapter III of this Part. The correct location of these two paragraphs
  22184. is less obvious than that of those moved in Section VII of Chapter I
  22185. and Section IV of Chapter IV, but they seem to fit here better than
  22186. anywhere else.
  22187. f 265.5 changed 'are' to 'is' (M 404.16; C 374.26)
  22188.  
  22189. t 265.26 deleted 'as well as "immortality," and' after 'Athenianism' and
  22190. put 'mortality' in quotation marks (M 405.5, 6; C 375.16, 17)— The
  22191. deletion was made by Whitehead in his Cambridge copy,
  22192. t 267.4 deleted comma after 'respectively' (M 407.18; C 377.16)
  22193. t 267.21 changed comma after first 'feelings' to semicolon (M 408.4; C 378.1 )
  22194.  
  22195. — This change was included on the list entitled "Misprints."
  22196. f 268.2 inserted 'the' after 'all' (M 40834; C 378.28)
  22197. t 268.37 deleted comma after 'feelings' (M 410.5; C 379.33)
  22198. f 270.42 put 'suspense-form' in quotation marks (M 413.11; C 382.32)
  22199. t 271.16 changed 'imaginative feelings' to 'imaginative feeling' (M 413.34;
  22200.  
  22201. C 383.18)
  22202. t 271.18 changed 'doctrine' to 'datum' (M 413.36; C 383.19)— The datum
  22203. of a propositional feeling is a proposition, and a proposition is what is
  22204. constituted by logical subjects and a predicative pattern. This is one of
  22205. those errors most easily explainable as due to the typist's misreading of
  22206. Whitehead's handwriting.
  22207. f 271.18 changed 'indicative feelings' to 'indicative feeling' (M 413.36;
  22208.  
  22209. C 383.20)
  22210. t 271.19 inserted 'the' before 'physical' (M 413.37; C 383.21)
  22211. t 272.21 put 'physical recollection' in quotation marks (M 415.25; C 385.3)
  22212. f 272.22 inserted comma after 'imaginative feeling' (M 415.26; C 385.3)
  22213. t 272.23 put 'intuitive judgment' in quotation marks (M 415.27-28;
  22214.  
  22215. C 385.5)
  22216. t 272.24 put 'indicative feeling' in quotation marks (M 415.29)
  22217. t 272.36 deleted comma after 'other' (M 416.8)
  22218. t 272.45 changed 'more' to 'mere' (M 416.19; C 385.33)
  22219. f 274.6 deleted comma after parentheses (M 418.8)
  22220. t 274.27 changed 'practice' to 'predicate' (M 418.33; C 388.4)
  22221. t 275.36 deleted comma after 'subject' (M 420.30; C 389.34)
  22222. t 276.16 changed 'physical' to 'conceptual' (M 421.25; C 390.25)
  22223. t 276.23 deleted comma after 'developed' and changed 'required' to 're-
  22224. quires' (M 421.34; C 390.34)
  22225. t 276.38 changed 'according' to 'accorded' (M 422.16; C 391.16)— The
  22226.  
  22227.  
  22228.  
  22229. 410 Editors' Notes
  22230.  
  22231. word 'according' would suggest, contrary to Whitehead's position, that
  22232. the conceptual valuation is completely determined by the physical feel-
  22233. ing. It would also prevent this sentence from speaking to the issue that
  22234. dominates the rest of the paragraph, which is how, in a physical pur-
  22235. pose, the fate of a physical feeling is determined by the conceptual
  22236. valuation given (accorded) to it. Whitehead does, in other places, stress
  22237. that the conceptual valuation is partly determined by the physical feel-
  22238. ing; but that is not the topic of this paragraph.
  22239. t 277.12 deleted comma after 'phase' (M 423.3; C 392.1)
  22240. f 277.22 inserted comma after 'subjective aim' (M 423.18; C 392.15) to
  22241. conform to the parallel in the first part of the sentence and to avoid the
  22242. false suggestion that there might be a subjective aim which is not "the
  22243. final cause"
  22244. t 277.42 changed 'subject' to 'subjective' and inserted 'at' before 'intensity'
  22245. (M 424.6 & 7: C 393.2 & 3^ to conform to 27.30-31
  22246.  
  22247. t 278.6 deleted 'final' after 'this' '(M 424.17; C 393.11)— As mentioned in
  22248. the note for 222.35, Whitehead evidently added the ninth category
  22249. after writing this section; cf. also the note for 278.35.
  22250.  
  22251. f 278.31 changed 'Category IV to 'Category V (M 425.11; C 394.4)
  22252.  
  22253. t 278.35 changed 'this final category' to 'Category VIII' (M 425.16-17;
  22254. C 394.9)-Cf. the note for 278.6.
  22255.  
  22256. t 278.36 changed 'had' to 'has' (M 425.17; C 394.10)
  22257.  
  22258. f 279.33 changed 'are' to 'is' (M 426.35; C 393.23)
  22259.  
  22260. t 279fn.l inserted 'Sect. VII' (M 427 fn.I; C 395 fn.l)
  22261.  
  22262. t 280.34 inserted comma after 'Also' (M 428.17)
  22263.  
  22264. t 283.2 changed 'CO-ORDINATE' to 'COORDINATE (C 401.2)-Cf.
  22265. the note for xx.35.
  22266.  
  22267. f 283.26 changed 'soZjdo' to 'soZido' (M 434.23)
  22268.  
  22269. f 284.39 deleted comma after 'separate' (M 436.10; C 403.21)
  22270.  
  22271. t 286.17 changed 'Ch. VIII, Sects. IV to IX' (M 438.22-23) and 'Ch.
  22272. VIII, JJ IV to VI' (C 405.28) to 'Ch. IV, Sects. IV to IX'-Chapter
  22273. VIII has only six sections, so the Macmillan reference is clearly errone-
  22274. ous, and the subject at issue is not discussed in the sections cited by
  22275. Cambridge.
  22276.  
  22277. t 286.19 deleted commas after 'sense' and 'influences' (M 438.23-24;
  22278. C 405.29-30)
  22279.  
  22280. t 286.26 deleted comma after 'plan' (M 438.34)
  22281.  
  22282. t 286.39 italicized 'Q a Q 2 ' and changed 'either' to 'other' (M 439.13-14)
  22283.  
  22284. t 287.1 inserted comma after 'as' (M 439.21)
  22285.  
  22286. t 287.3 changed 'purpose' to 'purposes' (M 439.23)
  22287.  
  22288. t 287.8 inserted 'the' before 'morphological' and changed 'structure' to 'struc-
  22289. tures' (M 439.29; C 406.32-33)
  22290.  
  22291. t 287.15 changed 'taken in by my' to 'taken by me in my' (M 439.38)
  22292.  
  22293. t 287.17 deleted comma after 'point' (M 440.3; C 407.8)
  22294.  
  22295. t 287.30 capitalized 'Part' (M 440.19; C 407.23)
  22296.  
  22297. t 287 fn.2 changed 'Lajuna's' to 'Laguna's' (M 440 fn.2)
  22298.  
  22299. t 288.17 inserted comma after 'Also' (M 441.22)
  22300.  
  22301. t 290.2 changed 'an' to 'a' (M 444.1)
  22302.  
  22303. f 290.22 changed comma after 'fact' to semicolon (M 444.27)
  22304.  
  22305. t 291.25 capitalized 'Platonic' (M 446.11; C 413.7)
  22306.  
  22307. t 291.26 changed 'VIII' to 'IV (M 446.14; C 413.9)
  22308.  
  22309. t 294.26 changed semicolon to colon (C 416.31)
  22310.  
  22311. $ 294.34 We have followed Macmillan, as against Cambridge, in italicizing
  22312. the numbers of Definitions and Assumptions here (C 417.6) and below.
  22313.  
  22314.  
  22315.  
  22316. Editors' Notes 411
  22317.  
  22318. f 296.1 These diagrams were on p. 451 of the Macmillan edition.
  22319.  
  22320. t 296.22 changed '15' to '13' (M 452.37}
  22321.  
  22322. f 297.1 changed 'Iff to '14' (M 453.1) '
  22323.  
  22324. f 297.7 deleted '1/ after 'Definition 6/ (M 453.9; C 419.34)
  22325.  
  22326. t 297.11 changed 'IT to '19 (M 453.14)
  22327.  
  22328. f 297.14 changed '18' to 'Iff (M 453.17)
  22329.  
  22330. t 297.15 changed '19' to 'IT (M 453.19)
  22331.  
  22332. t 297.17 changed '20' to '18' (M 453.21)
  22333.  
  22334. t 298.1 inserted 'and' before '(ii)' (M 454.18-19; C 421.4)
  22335.  
  22336. f 298.23 changed period after l B' to comma (M 455.9)
  22337.  
  22338. t 298.33 changed comma after 'A/ to semicolon (M 455.23; C 422.7)
  22339.  
  22340. t 298.35 changed comma after 'A 2 ' to semicolon (M 455.25; C 422.9)
  22341.  
  22342. f 298.42 changed '2V to '19' (M 455.34)
  22343.  
  22344. t 299.3 changed 'IT to '20' (M 456.3)
  22345.  
  22346. t 299.10 deleted comma after 'belones' (M 456.12; C 422.32)
  22347.  
  22348. t 299.13 changed '23' to '2V (M 456.15)
  22349.  
  22350. f 299.14 deleted comma after 'element' (M 456.16; C 422.36)
  22351.  
  22352. t 299.15 changed '24' to '22' (M 456.18)
  22353.  
  22354. f 299.16 deleted comma after 'element' (M 456.19; C 432.2)
  22355.  
  22356. t 299.17 changed '19 to '23' (M 456.21)
  22357.  
  22358. t 299.23 changed l 2ff to '24' (M 456.28)
  22359.  
  22360. f 299.33 changed 'satisfied' to 'satisfies' (M 457.3-4)
  22361.  
  22362. t 299.41 changed 'definitions' to 'definition' (M 457.13)
  22363.  
  22364. t 300.7 changed '27' to '29 (M 457.26)
  22365.  
  22366. f 300.8 changed colon after 'end-points' to semicolon (M 457.27; C 424.10)
  22367.  
  22368. f 30030 changed '28' to 'Iff (M 458.18)
  22369.  
  22370. t 300.40 changed '33' (M 459.33) and '3J' (C 426.11) to '27— This As-
  22371. sumption appears to have been added after the text was otherwise com-
  22372. pleted; it came at the very end of the chapter in both editions. Since
  22373. it refers explicitly to Definition 23, it has been relocated directly after
  22374. this Definition.
  22375.  
  22376. f 301.4 changed '29' (M 459.3) and '27 (C 425.20) to '28'
  22377.  
  22378. t 301.8 changed '30' (M 459.8) and '28' (C 425.24) to '29'
  22379.  
  22380. f 301.10 changed '3V (M 459.11) and '29' (C 425.27) to '30'
  22381.  
  22382. t 301.12 changed '32' (M 459.14) and '30' (C 425.30) to '3V
  22383.  
  22384. t 301.20 Neither edition had a new paragraph at this point (M 459.25;
  22385. C 426.3), but it is clearly desirable.
  22386.  
  22387. t 301.25 This paragraph was originally followed by Assumption 33, which
  22388. has been changed to Assumption 21 and moved to the appropriate place,
  22389.  
  22390. X 301.26 Whereas Cambridge placed this paragraph at this point in the text,
  22391. Macmillan had it (under the heading "Corrigenda") at the very back
  22392. of the book, after the Index, with an indication that it belonged on
  22393. page 459. The page references in the paragraph were to 504 and 463 of
  22394. the Macmillan edition. We took each 'i.e.' out of italics (M 544.5, 19).
  22395.  
  22396. t 302.12 changed single to double quotation marks (M 460.17-18; C 427.16-
  22397.  
  22398. 17)
  22399. f 302.18 deleted comma after 'imply' (M 460.25)
  22400. t 302.27 changed single to double quotation marks (M 461.6-7; C 427.32-
  22401.  
  22402. 33)
  22403. I 303.30 inserted comma after 'words' (M 462.19)
  22404. f 304.17 changed 'Ch. Ill' to 'Ch. IP (M 463.18); changed 'Ass. 33' (M
  22405.  
  22406. 463.19) and 'Ass. 31' (C 430.8) to 'Ass. 27'
  22407. * 304.25 See the added paragraph on p. 301.
  22408. t 304.38 changed 'These' to 'There' (M 464.9)
  22409.  
  22410.  
  22411.  
  22412. 412 Editors' Notes
  22413.  
  22414. t 305.8 changed 'relatively' to 'relating' (M 464.24)
  22415.  
  22416. f 306.19 changed lies' to 'lie' (C 433.7)— Whitehead has consistently been
  22417.  
  22418. using the subjunctive.
  22419. f 306.21 changed '6' to '6.V (M 466.26)
  22420. f 306.39 changed 'lies' to 'lie' (C 433.32)
  22421. f 309.2 changed 'become' to 'becomes' (M 470.23)
  22422. t 309.18 deleted comma after 'bodies' (M 471.8; C 437.21)
  22423. t 311.8 inserted comma after 'case' (M 473.28; C 440.22) to conform to
  22424.  
  22425. parallel two sentences above
  22426. t 311.35 changed 'realisation' to 'realization' (M 474.24)
  22427. f 314.7 inserted hyphen in 'high-grade' (M 478.9)
  22428. t 314.39 inserted hyphen in 'life-history' (M 479.14; C 446.4) to conform
  22429.  
  22430. to other occurrences
  22431. t 315.20 changed colon after 'physics' to semicolon (M 480.8; C 446.35)
  22432. t 316.22 inserted comma after 'forms' (M 481.32: C 448.18)
  22433. t 317 fn.l placed commas around 'Symbolism' in place of Cambridge's pa-
  22434. rentheses; changed comma after 'New York' to colon; added '1928'; and
  22435.  
  22436. put publication data in parentheses (M 482 fn.l; C 449 fn.l)— Cf. the
  22437.  
  22438. note for 121 fn.5.
  22439. t 319.2 inserted comma after 'example' (M 485.24)
  22440. f 319.8 changed semicolon after 'world' to comma (M 485.38)
  22441. f 319.27 changed '-dimensioned' to '-dimensional' (M 486.20)
  22442. t 319.33 took reference out of italics (M 486.28); changed 'VI' to 'VIII'
  22443.  
  22444. (M 486.28; C 453.10)— The reference is to Part II, Ch. IV, Sect. VIII.
  22445. f 319.43 changed 'parts' to 'pasts' (M 487.4; C 453.23)
  22446. t 320.1 deleted comma after 'occasions' (M 487.5; C 453.23); inserted
  22447.  
  22448. comma after 'S' (M 487.5)
  22449. t 320.22 deleted comma after 'M' (M 487.33; C 454.14)
  22450. t 320.26 inserted comma after 'views' (M 487.37)
  22451. t 320.38 changed 'present' to 'future' (M 488.15; C 454.33)
  22452. f 320.44 inserted comma after 'secondly' (M 488.22; C 455.2)
  22453. t 321.3 deleted comma after 'M' (M 488.26)
  22454. t 321.13 inserted comma after 'occasions' (M 489.3)
  22455. t 321.35 inserted hyphen in 'life-history' (M 489.31)
  22456. t 322.16 deleted comma after 'future' (M 491.19)
  22457. t 323.20 changed The' to 'The' (M 493.4)
  22458. i 324.21 changed 'previous chapter' to 'Ch. IIP (M 494.26; C 460.16)-
  22459.  
  22460. Whitehead evidently ended up with one more chapter in Part IV than
  22461.  
  22462. he had intended when writing this passage.
  22463. t 325.15 changed 'the previous chapter' to 'Ch. Ill' (M 495.38; C 461.27) —
  22464.  
  22465. Cf. the note for 324.21.
  22466. t 325.36 changed 'presentation' to 'presentational' (M 496.28)
  22467. f 325.43 italicized 'Meditation I' (M 496.36-37)
  22468.  
  22469. t 326.3 changed 'Part I, Sect. XII' to 'Sect. XII, Part I' (M 497.4; C 462.29)
  22470. f 326.4 inserted comma after 'Hume' (M 497.5)
  22471. t 326.16 inserted comma after 'When' (M 497.21)
  22472. t 326.42 changed 'natures' to 'nature' (M 498.16; C 464.2)
  22473. f 328.8 changed 'In-mathematics' to 'In mathematics' (M 500.10-11)
  22474. t 328.14 inserted hyphen in 'yard-measure' here, at 328.27, and at 329.8 & 9
  22475.  
  22476. (M 500.18 & 37; M 501.29 & 31)
  22477. f 328.36 inserted comma after 'from' (M 501.9; C 466.29)
  22478. f 329.3 inserted hyphen in 'wave-lengths' (M 501.23)
  22479. t 329.5 inserted 'are' after 'tests' (M 501.26) — This change was included on
  22480.  
  22481. the list entitled "Misprints."
  22482.  
  22483.  
  22484.  
  22485. Editors' Notes 413
  22486.  
  22487. t 329.7 deleted comma after 'congruence' (M 501.28; C 467.9)
  22488.  
  22489. t 329.30 changed 'depend' to 'depends' (M 502.21)
  22490.  
  22491. t 330.2 inserted 'the' before 'meaning' (M 503.4; C 468.21)
  22492.  
  22493. f 330.12 changed 'inter-connections' to 'interconnections', (M 503.16)
  22494.  
  22495. * 330.42 See the added paragraph on p. 301.
  22496.  
  22497. t 331.7 inserted comma after 'containing' (M 504.29)
  22498.  
  22499. t 331.16 deleted comma after 'line' and changed 'itself is' to 'is itself
  22500. (M 505.2-3)
  22501.  
  22502. t 331.36 deleted comma after 'parallelograms' (M 505.29; C 471.7)
  22503.  
  22504. t 331 fn.l took 'Sixth Memoir on Quantics' out of italics and put it in quota-
  22505. tion marks; changed 'Trans. R.S.' to 'Transactions of the Royal Society';
  22506. and decapitalized 'von' (M 505 fn.l; C 470 fn.l)
  22507.  
  22508. f 333 fn.3 inserted comma after 'measurement' in second line (M 508 fn.3);
  22509. changed 'Vol. XXIV to 'Vol. XXV (M 508 fn.3; C 473 fn.l)
  22510.  
  22511. t 337.14 inserted comma after 'selection' (M 512.17; C 477.17)
  22512.  
  22513. f 339.6 deleted comma after 'curse' (M 514.36; C 479.33)
  22514.  
  22515. * 340.11 Mathew Arnold's poem, "Resignation/' which was written as advice
  22516.  
  22517. to his sister, begins with the following two lines in italics:
  22518. To die be given us, or attain!
  22519. Fierce work it were, to do again.
  22520. These lines are presented as sentiments expressed by pilgrims on the
  22521. way to Mecca. Whitehead evidently quoted these lines (imperfectly)
  22522. from memory, and they clearly conveyed a different message to him
  22523. from the one implied by the title of Arnold's poem.
  22524. t 340.38 deleted 'the' after 'means' (M 517.26; C 482.20)
  22525. t 341.8 inserted comma after 'therefore' (M 518.4)
  22526. f 342.3 inserted 'SECTION I' (M 519.3)
  22527. i 343.9 changed 'theistic idolatrous' to 'idolatrous theistic' (M 520.26;
  22528.  
  22529. C 485.21)
  22530. f 344.20 inserted comma after 'creative act' (M 522.24)
  22531. t 344.25 changed 'mover' to 'moves' (M 522.30; C 487.23)
  22532. f 344.26 changed ' a mover' to 'something' (M 522.31; C 487.24)
  22533. + 344.29 inserted 'move in this way; they move without being moved. The
  22534.  
  22535. primary objects of desire and of thought' (M 522.33; C 487.26)
  22536. t 344.31 changed 'desire' to 'wish' (M 522.35; C 487.28)
  22537. t 344.33 deleted 'side' after 'one' and changed 'list' to 'two columns' (M
  22538.  
  22539. 523.3; C 487.30)
  22540. t 344 fn.l changed '1072' to '1072a 23-32' (M 522 fn.l; C 487 fn.l)
  22541. t 345.9 inserted comma after 'Thus' (M 523.26)
  22542. t 346.21 deleted comma after 'nature' (M 525.25; C 490.10)
  22543. ** 346.35 In his Macmillan copy, Whitehead crossed out 'leading' and wrote
  22544. both "persuading" and "swaying" in the margin. No change was made
  22545. in the text, partly because Whitehead did not clearly specify a sub-
  22546. stitute.
  22547. f 347.1 capitalized 'Platonic' (M 526.18; C 491.3)
  22548. f 348.2 changed 'self-contradiction' to 'self-contradictions' (M 528.2);
  22549.  
  22550. changed 'depends' to 'depend' (C 492.21)
  22551. f 348.20 changed 'these' to 'there' (M 528.24)'
  22552.  
  22553. f 349.7 changed colon after 'forms' to semicolon (M 529.29; C 4947)
  22554. t 350.6 deleted comma after 'suffering' (M 531.7; C 495.20)— This change
  22555. was made by Whitehead on Mrs. Greene's typescript.
Advertisement
Add Comment
Please, Sign In to add comment
Advertisement